jueves, 10 de marzo de 2011

“Vamos a cantar juntos compañeros, para borrar su nombre de esta tierra” (Made in-Noble)

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gGTA1CFv-Ss

Construyó un imperio. Las leyes se ignoraron, o se amoldaron a sus placeres y la de sus sucesores. Explotó a sus asalariados. Los echó y los recontrató como quiso. Les pagó como quiso. Devastó enormes sectores de la Argentina. Distorsionó la realidad. ¿”La Forestal”? ¿O los dueños (el fundador y su esposa) del multimedios más poderoso de las últimas décadas?

El texto que sigue puede ser obviado por el/la lector/a. Es un ejercicio, nada más. Puede leerlo o no, lo importante es que nos permite debatir:
“(…) Curioso destino familiar tener que construir el futuro a partir de la ausencia. Hablo de la ausencia física, claro, porque en todos los demás planos, hubo, hay y seguirá habiendo una presencia fuerte, clara, permanente. Pero la ausencia duele y es injusta. No hay voces, no hay manos, no hay besos. Sólo el recuerdo. Sólo esos retazos de vida que se agitan en el fondo de nuestros ojos como las primeras imágenes del sueño, cuando llega, en ese difuso momento en el que todavía no sabemos si estamos despiertos o ya estamos soñando.
No existe el momento ideal para perder a un padre. Siempre es demasiado temprano. Siempre nos encuentra indefensos, desarmados. Pero cuando es temprano de verdad, cronológicamente, cuando esa moneda de dos caras que es la vida se encarga de mostrarnos el reverso mucho antes de que estemos preparados, entonces, no tenemos otra opción que seguir adelante con lo que nos queda, con lo que quien ha partido nos dejó.
(…) A pesar de lo efímero de su presencia física, mi padre fue extremadamente generoso conmigo, pues me dejó un nombre, un ejemplo, un legado y esa acariciante sensación de orgullo que siento al ver mi sendero iluminado por un hombre singular. Fue un hombre completo, que cuando usaba la cabeza no olvidaba escuchar el corazón, un hombre que supo estar a la altura de sus responsabilidades como empleador, como amigo, como padre, como ciudadano. Ser agradecido, para un hijo, es honrar la memoria de su padre.
Es tomar el testimonio de sus convicciones y llevarlo en el trecho de camino que a uno le toca recorrer, para después transmitirlo a quien nos suceda en el próximo tramo. Con esa convicción encaro la tarea de unir recuerdos, testimonios, documentos y escritos sobre Roberto Noble, para mostrar a un hombre íntegro y coherente con sus propias ideas y en la relación con sus semejantes.
Se trata de un libro doblemente necesario. Para mí, porque es una manera de dar testimonio acerca de mis orígenes, de saldar una deuda de gratitud y de asomarme con prolija minuciosidad al sorprendente mundo de mi padre. Para la comunidad, porque las nuevas generaciones merecen conocer los aportes y las convicciones de un argentino que trabajó con todas sus energías y su talento por un país próspero y equitativo, con vocación de servicio, con generosidad, con espíritu patriótico.
Para ser coherente con lo declarado, necesito, como punto de partida, reivindicar la manera en que Roberto Noble asumió su paternidad, un rol tan desdibujado en este tiempo de límites difusos y de escasa contención afectiva. Me propongo contar cómo ese hombre respetado y admirado era capaz de jugar conmigo, manteniendo al mismo tiempo la conciencia clara de su compromiso con los valores que debía inculcarme. Tenía el don de hacer convivir el permiso y el límite, sin que el uno desdibujara o confundiera al otro. La ternura y la firmeza emanaban de él con la misma fluidez con que lo hacían sus ideas.
Es que mi padre era lo que hacía y hacía lo que era. No necesitaba cambiar de atuendo para vestirse de padre, o de legislador, o de periodista. Era consecuente con sus valores, porque se había formado en otra escuela, en un tiempo distinto, en una sociedad que todavía contaba con materiales para formar hombres así. En última instancia, todos somos hijos del tiempo que nos toca vivir. Después, naturalmente, se pone de manifiesto lo que cada uno es capaz de dar de sí. Y así, interactuamos con valientes y cobardes, genios y mediocres, impulsivos y racionales, honestos y taimados, héroes y villanos. La variopinta fauna humana puede ofrecer todos los matices, pero hay un punto de partida que facilita o dificulta el destino particular.
Esa búsqueda tiñe la intención última de este libro. La búsqueda de un país diferente, de una matriz mejor, capaz de volver a parir hombres y mujeres valientes, comprometidos con su tiempo, enamorados de la libertad, respetuosos de la justicia, amantes del saber, rebeldes ante la desigualdad, conscientes de sus deberes ciudadanos.
Mi padre perteneció a esa casta de hombres, por esfuerzo y convicciones propias, es cierto, pero también porque creció en un marco, un tiempo, un país, que le permitieron desplegar sus alas y alcanzar sus ideales. Mi padre tenía una clara conciencia del devenir. Sabía que su tiempo en este mundo era limitado. Sin embargo, esa certeza no lo condujo a la indiferencia. Él sabía que la vida es un hálito que nos trasciende a los simples individuos, que hay un sentido de patria, de comunidad, de especie, que nos compromete, y sabía que este mundo que padecemos y disfrutamos no ha sido hecho sólo para los que lo habitamos en el presente. Es el mundo que construyeron nuestros ancestros, que modelamos nosotros, que continuarán nuestros hijos.
Eso significa tomar el testimonio, recorrer el camino que nos toca y después pasarlo. Hacia adelante, siempre hacia adelante. Mi padre lo sintió así. Lo tenía asumido. Por eso, pudo sacarse de encima el estrecho corset de la coyuntura, del beneficio inmediato, y construyó mirando hacia el futuro. Es lo que explica que su legado jurídico, literario, político y periodístico haya atravesado las décadas y llegue intacto hasta hoy. Cuarenta años después de su partida física, sus obras siguen vigentes, su nombre continúa siendo recordado, su espíritu late, vivo, en todo lo que dejó, como seguramente seguirá sucediendo.
En el rompecabezas que siempre resulta una vida, una persona es la suma de sus muchas miradas. La mía, como hija, pero además como ciudadana comprometida con su tiempo y su país, está sintetizada en las páginas que siguen. Para esa historia que escribimos entre todos, aquí va mi contribución. Otros estudiarán, desde distintos puntos de vista, su pensamiento político, su obra, su aporte al periodismo y al país. Pero esta primera pieza del rompecabezas me corresponde.
Para concebirla elegí privilegiar los documentos, las obras, los testimonios y sus propias definiciones. Ese conjunto de hechos, pensamientos y elecciones personales lo pintan como un estadista que no se sirvió de la política para alcanzar sus fines personales, sino que él sirvió a la política como instrumento de cambio”.


Soy un delincuente. Acabo de cometer un ilícito, y voy a explicar por qué: el fragmento que se reproduce aquí contiene exactamente 1028 palabras (estimad@ lector, se puede tomar el trabajo de contarlas una por una, yo usé un programa informático), pertenece al prólogo del libro “Noble, un argentino visionario”, (Sudamericana, Buenos Aires, 2010) escrito la hija del fundador de Clarín (Guadalupe Noble). La ley 11723, de propiedad intelectual, cuyo autor es Roberto Noble, establece en su artículo 10 “Cualquiera puede publicar con fines didácticos o científicos, comentarios, críticas o notas referentes a las obras intelectuales, incluyendo hasta mil palabras de obras literarias o científicas u ocho compases en las musicales y en todos los casos sólo las partes del texto indispensables a ese efecto. Quedan comprendidas en esta disposición las obras docentes, de enseñanza, colecciones, antologías y otras semejantes
Es decir, si uno reproduce (aunque se lleve adelante con fines didácticos, por más que no esté lucrando con la utilización del trabajo ajeno) más de 1000 palabras de una obra ajena, está infringiendo la ley. Para que esa colección de frases ingrese al “dominio público”, tendría que esperar que transcurriesen 70 años desde la muerte de la autora (siempre y cuando no haya nuevas modificaciones a las leyes que rigen la “propiedad intelectual”). La pregunta es ¿por qué?
Nadie es absolutamente original, ningún autor crea “ex nihilo” sus obras, porque cada uno abreva de un fondo común a toda la humanidad. Vale aquí la frase tan difundida (atribuida a Newton, pero que otros autores la remontan a Bernardo de Chartres): “si he visto más lejos, es porque estoy sentado sobre hombros de gigantes”.
Por esa razón, otra vez nace la pregunta: ¿por qué? ¿Qué es lo que hace que un autor (o mejor dicho, las editoriales, dado que se arrogan ellas el derecho de “propiedad intelectual” sobre las obras publicadas) tenga tanto poder sobre su obra? ¿Qué es lo que permite que una biblioteca pública no pueda efectuar una fotocopia de una obra que se encuentra en su catálogo, dado que “requiere el consentimiento escrito del autor, del editor o sus derechohabientes”, aunque la obra no se haya reeditado hace años? ¿Por qué los lectores tenemos que soportar imágenes y expresiones falaces como las que incluyen las grandes editoriales en la primera o segunda página de cada libro, en la que apocalípticamente indican “la fotocopia mata al libro”?
¿No es hora que tengamos una ley que contemple los derechos de autor, pero a la vez, posibilite el verdadero objetivo de un libro, que es la difusión de la cultura? Esa sí que sería una “ley noble”

viernes, 13 de noviembre de 2009

Los simpson 2º parte, traducido por Google Traductor

Incluso antes, aunque sin recordar su nombre, Jesús, como alguien que iba en contra de ortodoxos
prácticas y, sin embargo tenía razón para hacerlo ( "Homer the Heretic"). Homero incluso muestra raras
momentos en que parece conocer sus propias limitaciones. Le preguntó una vez a Marge, "You're
aquí a verme, ¿verdad? ", cuando se presentó en la planta, lo que revela su convicción de que, desde
era un hombre de propiedades humilde, que necesitaba para asegurarse de que Marge estaba allí para verlo
( "Life On The Fast Lane"). Y doble - y triples - comprobar Lurleen Lumpkin es coquetear
con él para asegurarse de que realmente era sexualmente interesado en él ( "El coronel Homero").
Evaluación: A juzgar por Homero
¿Qué vamos a hacer de todo esto? ¿Cómo funciona exactamente Homero frente a ética
evaluación? Homero no es una mala persona. Aunque no es un paradigma de la virtud, sin duda
no es malintencionado. La más dura reacción que pueden tener hacia él es pena. Hay por lo menos
dos razones para ello. La primera razón es que la educación de Homero, deja mucho que desear.
Para empezar, se crió en su mayoría en Springfield, una ciudad cuyos habitantes - con la rara
excepción de Lisa - tienen problemas de carácter grave y severo, que van desde la estupidez de
malicia, a ser simplemente incompetentes y desorientados en los caminos del mundo (incluso Marge,
, que es un buen candidato para ser otra excepción a los habitantes de Springfield, es
muy convencional y, a menudo carece de críticos abilities7). Tenga en cuenta que incluso cuando los miembros de
del capítulo de Springfield de Mensa rigen la ciudad (después que el alcalde Quimby huido), que
a proponer las normas injustas, restrictivas, y muy idealista. Huelga decir que el caos
Siguió ( "Brain Ellos salvaron de Lisa") .8
El efecto de ser criado en un ambiente así podría ser perjudicial para la propia
la formación del carácter futuro y las capacidades intelectuales. Además, se plantean de una manera sana
el medio ambiente es una de las principales reivindicaciones que el proyecto de motivos de Aristóteles en la Política: "Nuestra
propósito es considerar qué tipo de comunidad política es el mejor de todos para aquellos que son
más capaces de realizar su ideal de vida "(1260b25). En efecto, la ética de Aristóteles, también se dirige a
el estadista que es pensar en lo que el personaje mejor ética es, a fin de diseñar una política
de la comunidad capaz de producir tal carácter. Si esto es correcto, entonces una razón por la que tendemos
a la piedad de Homero es porque creemos que este aspecto de su educación, a saber, Springfield, es
más allá de su control.
Además, la cría de Homero en la casa deja mucho que desear. Su madre lo dejó
cuando era joven, y su padre nunca le animó a convertirse en cualquier cosa de valor;
cuando Homero tenía algunas aspiraciones, su padre les disparó hacia abajo ( "Mother Simpson" y
"Bart Star"). Por otra parte, una cualidad sobre Homero que ciertamente no puede controlar es el
Gen Simpson, que al parecer produce un Simpson a crecer más estúpido como las edades. "Es
defectuosos sólo en el cromosoma Y "y no en el X, y es por eso que Lisa y otros
Simpson han sido las mujeres inteligentes y de éxito ( "Lisa Simpson"). Si es así, entonces no hay
poco que Homero podía hacer para mejorar. Y estos factores explican por qué tendemos a mirar
a Homero con compasión y no con desprecio o el odio.
La segunda razón por nuestro juicio de carácter de Homero no es duro, incluso
aunque no es virtuoso, es que no es generalmente una persona con malas intenciones. Él es egoísta, es
un glotón, que es codicioso, y él puede ser muy tonta, pero rara vez es una de esas personas que
tienen envidia de los demás y que les deseo la mala voluntad. Es cierto que a menudo actúa con deliberada
intención de hacer daño a algunas personas, pero creemos que de alguna manera estas personas no son dignas de
un mejor tratamiento. El desprecio, por ejemplo, que montones de Homero en Selma y Patty parece que
ser apropiado, dada la forma en que tratan a él, y dada su actitud de desprecio hacia él.
Homero también le gustan (aunque también los temores) Sr. Burns. Y cualquier otra cosa se puede decir sobre
Burns, que es el caso paradigmático de un avaro, mal, y despiadado capitalista que está dispuesto a
caminar por un camino de cadáveres para lograr su ends.9 Por último, Homero trata de Flandes en indecente
formas, que van desde la indiferencia al desdén. Pero, de nuevo, Flandes es un exceso de rodamiento,
ingenuo, siempre predicando person.10 Esto no quiere decir que se justifica el tratamiento de Homero de él,
pero es para decir que es comprensible. Con estas excepciones en mente, Homero es en general
no es una persona mala y no tratar a las personas con malicia. Esta es otra razón por la cual,
aunque está lejos de tener un carácter ético, Homer no provoca negativo
reacciones en nosotros.
Podemos, entonces, emitir un juicio calificado en el sentido de que Homero no es un círculo vicioso
persona en el sentido de estar gobernado por el vicio. Digo "cualificada", porque hay una excepción
a este juicio: cuando se trata de apetitos corporales de los alimentos y bebidas, Homer es vicioso.
Él no tiene el placer de comer y beber con moderación, y esto excluye la virtud en este
dominio. Rara vez, o nunca, tiene la creencia en el sentido de que debe abstenerse de excesiva
comer y beber, y esto excluye la continencia y la incontinencia. Además, él no
parecen pensar que haya nada malo (que no sea inmediato para la salud de vez en cuando
a) Consideraciones a la práctica de los alimentos y bebidas, incluso en lugares inapropiados, por lo que
dijo una vez a Marge, "Si Dios no quería que comiéramos en la iglesia, Él ha hecho una gula
"pecado (" King of the Hill "). Estas consideraciones nos permiten concluir con seguridad que
Homer exhibe el vicio en el dominio de los apetitos corporales para alimentos y bebidas.
Dada la abundancia de pruebas y ejemplos, podemos llegar a la siguiente
sentencia: Homer no es una persona virtuosa. Un número de factores que nos permiten llegar a esta
conclusión, pero tal vez el más sobresaliente es que Homero no tiene la estabilidad de
carácter que marca la persona virtuosa. Uno simplemente no puede contar con él para hacer la derecha
nada, ni siquiera con respecto a las acciones hacia los miembros de su familia. Además, la
juicio de que Homero no es virtuoso es, a diferencia de la que no es vicioso, no cualificado.
Porque, aunque a veces actúa correctamente Homero, sus razones para hacerlo son por lo general
sesgada, ambigua o en el mejor (sus actos de valor son un buen ejemplo de esto). Y, en la medida
que se refiere a su familia, incluso cuando Homer hace lo que pensamos que un buen padre o esposo
iba a hacer, simplemente hay demasiados ejemplos que demuestran lo contrario. Homero simplemente
no posee el tipo de carácter estable que es necesario para ser virtuoso.
Hay que recordar también que en muchos de los casos en que Homero hace la derecha
cosa, sobre todo en lo que se refiere a su familia, él tiene que luchar contra sus deseos de
no hacer otra cosa. En ambas ocasiones, cuando compró Lisa su saxofón, tuvo que luchar
en contra de su deseo de comprar un acondicionador de aire ( "Lisa's Sax"). A veces, a pesar de su
conocimiento de lo que se debe hacer, él decide hacer lo incorrecto, lo que exhiben
lo que los griegos llamaron akrasia, o "debilidad de la voluntad." Por ejemplo, en "La Guerra de la
Simpsons ", que elige para ir a pescar durante su retiro en el Lago Bagre pesar de que sabía
que su atención debe centrarse en Marge y en su matrimonio.
Homero no es una persona virtuosa. Expone vicio cuando se trata de los apetitos de los alimentos
y la bebida, y en cuanto a las otras esferas de la vida, lanzaderas de ida y vuelta entre las
la continencia y la incontinencia. Esto, por supuesto, no demuestra que la división de Aristóteles de la
tipos de caracteres era demasiado ordenada o poco realistas o simplistas, porque la división de Aristóteles era un
lógico, no una descripción de qué tipo de personas que realmente son. Homer crea una instancia
tipos de caracteres diferentes, dependiendo de la zona de vida con respecto a la cual la pregunta es
planteadas.
Conclusión:
La importancia de llamarse Homero
Al comienzo de este ensayo, afirmó que hay algo éticamente admirable,
Homer Simpson. Pero esta afirmación plantea un problema: ¿Cómo puede ser cierto si Homero no es
virtuoso? Porque si el paradigma de carácter ético admirable es ser virtuoso, y si es
Homero está a la altura de esta norma, entonces la afirmación de que es éticamente admirable, parece
evidentemente falso. Además, aunque no creemos que Homero es malicioso, e incluso si
pensamos que la formación de su carácter era - al menos en su mayoría - más allá de su control, estas
factores no son suficientes para hacer lo éticamente admirable. Para esta última afirmación debe ser al menos
plausible, algo más debe estar en el trabajo. Y esta otra cosa no puede ser el hecho de que el
Homero a veces hace lo correcto, porque la demanda es de él, su carácter, y
No se trata de un subconjunto de sus acciones.
En "Escenas de la lucha de clases en Springfield, Marge se da cuenta de su error en la
tratando de presionar a su familia a ajustarse a un círculo social elitista que se ha unido recientemente. En
la aceptación de los miembros de su familia por lo que son, que enumera las cualidades que le gusta
acerca de ellos (no podía, sin embargo, encontrar uno de Bart). La calidad que menciona de Homero es
su "en-su-cara la humanidad", y esta calidad, si se entiende de manera suficientemente amplia, no sólo es
el caso de él, pero también va un largo camino para explicar de qué manera él es éticamente admirable.
Esta calidad no sólo abarca aquellos rasgos que Homer conducen a hacer cosas en
público de que muchos de nosotros, en diferentes grados, tímido lejos de hacer, como eructos,
la liberación de gases, rascarse nuestros traseros, y comer y beber hasta el punto de perder el
nuestros sentidos. Si fuera sólo eso, Homero sería simplemente un patán. Más bien, se cubre de Homero,
el amor y el disfrute de la vida, en sus elementos más básicos, mientras que al mismo tiempo, no dar
mucho, en su caso, atención a lo que piensa la gente. Homero lo general no se preocupa acerca de la etiqueta
o sobre lo que la gente piensa de él. Él se encuentra en disfrutar de la vida - o su versión de la misma - a la
máximo. Este entusiasmo por la vida no se calcula por su parte, ni es siquiera necesariamente consciente
de la misma. Pero se manifiesta en sus acciones, en sus actitudes, en su falta de malicia, y en su
infantil (incluso infantil) el comportamiento, y, de hecho, se puede encontrar en la mayoría de los
ejemplos citados en este ensayo. Si añadimos a esto el hecho de que Homero es una lucha,
"superior e inferior de clase media" ciudadano, trabajando en una fábrica bajo la tiranía de un despiadado
capitalista, y cuando también se suma el hecho de que la vida de Homero en Springfield, una ciudad que se
debe hacer una parada y pensar antes de que uno decide que la vida es digna de ser amada, llegamos
a una persona que tiene mucho para ser admirado.
Esta cualidad que explica admirability de Homero - vamos a llamarlo "amor a la vida",
siguientes a Ned Flanders de etiquetado de la lujuria como "tóxica para la vida de Homero" ( "Viva Ned
Flanders ") - no es una virtud en sí. Esto es así no porque no aparece en Aristóteles
lista, sino porque, como bien sabemos, esta calidad, si aún no aprovechados, puede ser peligroso tanto para las
otros y para su poseedor (como, creo, es en el caso de Homero). Al igual que la ambición, es un
cualidad positiva, y es admirable en eso. Es también una cualidad ética. Mejora, si
bien poseído, la vida de la persona que lo tiene por hacer su vida más agradable,
y hace que el resto de nosotros quiere estar en compañía de esta persona, no sólo para que algunos de ellos
puede frotar sobre nosotros, sino también porque es simplemente agradable estar cerca de estas personas. Si
las cualidades que contribuyen a la felicidad de una persona y, en general son florecientes
plausiblemente interpretado como ética, a continuación, una calidad, como el amor de la vida se ajustan a este proyecto de ley, si se utiliza
y regulada por la razón práctica. En el caso de Homero, la calidad no viene aprovechado por
la razón y viene con otras características que hacen de su poder peligroso. Pero nosotros
Homero, sin embargo lo admiro por haber, y por haber contra todos sus odds.11
Además, esta calidad, y sobre todo porque se trata de incontrolados que en Homero,
lo lleva a ser abiertamente honesto acerca de sus deseos y sus necesidades - incluso a una falta. Dónde
régimen y otros cómplices a la vez que pretende ser socialmente conformista, Homer está abierto,
honesta, e incluso contundente acerca de quién es, lo que quiere, y lo que piensa de los demás. Él
conoce sus limitaciones, que ama a su familia - en su propia manera moralmente atenuado - y es
una en-su-tipo de la cara de la persona.
Sin embargo, yo no quisiera ser malinterpretado. No estoy diciendo que Homero es, como
tal, una persona admirable, pero sólo que él tiene un rasgo admirable. Es tentador diapositiva
de esta última afirmación a la anterior, porque, en primer lugar, mientras que Homero no es virtuoso, es
Asimismo, ni malicioso, ni, a excepción de los apetitos del cuerpo, vicioso, en segundo lugar, el hecho de que Homero
ama la vida, a pesar de su financiera y económicamente modestos recursos, y a pesar de su creciente
y vivir en una ciudad como Springfield (que no es propicio para una buena vida), podría
nos hacen pensar que es admirable para conservar su amor por la vida en la cara de estos difíciles
situaciones. Pero la tentación debe ser resistido, y esto es así por tres razones.
En primer lugar, y como ya he subrayado, la calidad del amor de la vida en caso de Homero es
no regulada por la razón, y esto podría hacer que moralmente peligroso. En segundo lugar, disfrutando de
la vida no es lo mismo que vivir una floreciente. Una persona podría, en efecto disfrutar la vida al
más completa aún no llevar una vida floreciente. Piense en alguien que está pasando plenamente felices de su vida
contar las hojas de hierba o el cobro de tapas de botella, pero que es capaz de llevar a cabo más digno
objetivos. No importa cuán feliz es esa persona, no importa lo mucho que está disfrutando de su vida, que
seguramente no quiere decir de su vida que es bien vivida. Teniendo en cuenta los ejemplos mencionados en
la tercera sección anterior, Homer es claramente capaz de vivir una vida mejor que la que él dirige.
En tercer lugar, hay una razón lógica: tener un rasgo admirable no es, como tal, implica que su
poseedor es admirable. Villanos a menudo tienen el carácter de superación del miedo en la cara de riesgo,
y si bien este rasgo es admirable, no solemos pensar en los villanos como admirable. Es más,
es por eso que a veces decimos de una persona sin escrúpulos, "Bueno, al menos, ha de ser coherente",
reconociendo así la coherencia como un rasgo admirable al mismo tiempo reconoce que no es
suficiente para que su poseedor una persona admirable.
Por otra parte, un momento de reflexión nos debe decir que Homero es, de hecho, no una
persona admirable como tal. Él no es virtuoso, y este hecho es suficiente para debilitar la
cualquier intento serio de admirability atribuyen a él como un juicio global. Sin embargo,
a veces las personas no virtuoso sin embargo tienen admirable si compensan
su falta de virtud, por, por ejemplo, obras de arte que da al mundo. La tradicional
ejemplo dado en este sentido es el artista de Gauguin, que dejó a su familia a valerse por sí mismo
mientras continuaba haciendo arte en Tahití. Estos factores atenuantes, sin embargo, no se aplican a
Homer: ¿Qué contribución duradera que ha dado al mundo por la manera de compensar su
la falta de virtud para merecer la denominación "admirable"?
Pero el amor de Homero de la vida, no obstante, un rasgo muy admirable, y esta conclusión
no es trivial, pues muchas personas se ven tentados a ver en nada, pero Homer y bufonadas
la inmoralidad. Por otra parte, el amor de Homero de la vida se destaca como una cualidad importante, especialmente en
nuestra época, una época en que la corrección política, el exceso de cortesía, la falta de voluntad para juzgar
otros, la obsesión de inflado con la salud física, y el pesimismo acerca de lo que es bueno y
disfrutar de la vida más o menos el reinado supremo. En esta época, Homer Simpson - cuya
calcomanía dice "Sassy n" único "- brilla como alguien que se burla de estas" verdades ". Él es
no es políticamente correcto, es más que feliz de juzgar a los demás, y ciertamente no
parecen estar obsesionados con su salud. Estas cualidades no podría hacer una admirable Homero
persona, pero sí lo hacen admirable en algunos aspectos, y, más importante aún, nos hacen
anhelan él y el Homer Simpson de este mundo.12
1 Mis comentarios sobre Aristóteles se deriva principalmente de su Ética a Nicómaco, Libros I, II, V, y
VIII, traducido por Terence Irwin (Indianápolis: Hackett, 1985) y su Política (traducido por B. Jowett, en
Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Las obras completas de Aristóteles, volumen 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1984). Referencias específicas en el cuerpo del documento. Huelga decir que mucho de lo que digo en Aristóteles
objeto de debate.
2 Hay que resistir la tentación de pensar que la persona vicioso también tiene la sabiduría práctica. El
vicioso, según Aristóteles, no tiene phrónesis, sino que tiene inteligencia. Para Aristóteles,
la razón práctica tiene fuerza normativa y no sólo desempeñan un papel significa-final. Phronesis nos permite conocer
¿Qué cosas son importantes y éticos en la vida. Por eso dice Aristóteles en varias ocasiones que lo que es correcto es lo que
parece ser que el agente virtuoso (véase, por ejemplo Ética 1176a16-19).
3 Véase la guía de los episodios al final de este libro para una lista ordenada de los episodios. Muchos de los
citas y de todos los títulos de los episodios en mi trabajo son de Los Simpson: Una guía completa de nuestra
Favorito de la familia, editado por Ray Richmond (Nueva York: Harper Collins, 1997), y Los Simpson siempre,
editado por Scott M. Gimple (Nueva York: Harper Collins, 1999).
4 Marge podría pensarse que encajan en esta descripción, habida cuenta de la conclusión de Homero, que es su alma gemela,
( "El misterioso viaje de Homero"), pero la mayoría de los episodios de la serie en realidad indican lo mucho que la
ambas divergen en cuanto a sus objetivos, intereses y actividades.
5 Véase el capítulo 3 de este volumen.
6 digo "a sabiendas" porque en "Viva Ned Flanders" Homer se despierta en un hotel en Las Vegas a
descubrir que había, durante la borrachera de la noche pasada, se casó con una camarera, y se deja
claro si en realidad había tenido relaciones sexuales con ella.
7 Para una visión aristotélica del carácter de Marge, véase el Capítulo 4 de este volumen.
8 A los vicios de Springfield, véase el capítulo 12 de este volumen.
9 Y nunca será feliz tampoco. Véase el capítulo 13 de este volumen.
10 El personaje de Flanders, véase el capítulo 14 de este volumen.
11 Las probabilidades de que se incluyen aquí moderada medios intelectuales y financieros y de vida de los
los habitantes de Springfield. Debemos tener en cuenta también que podemos admirar el carácter de Homero para otros
razones. Se trata, obviamente, muy gracioso. También es posible que lo admiran porque vemos una exagerada
sentido de lo que somos - o algunos de nosotros - están en él.
12 Deseo agradecer a las siguientes: los editores de este volumen de comentarios de gran ayuda, especialmente Bill
Irwin también para darme constante apoyo y aliento; Steve Jones por participar conmigo en excelente
conversaciones acerca de Homero Simpson y por tolerar (y, a veces disfrutando) mi constante uso de
Homero cita en mi discurso ordinario; mis estudiantes brillantes en la Escuela del Instituto de Arte de Chicago para
discutir el tema de este trabajo conmigo en numerosas ocasiones (que implican la indulgencia inmoderado tanto en
alimentos y bebidas), para el uso de ejemplos de Los Simpson, muestran en sus documentos de la filosofía, y por su
alegría contagiosa en el simple hecho de saber que yo estaba escribiendo este artículo: Annika Connor, Ted Dumitrescu, Christopher
Koch, Cory Poole, Sara Puzey, Austin Stewart, y Dahlia Tulett (este artículo está dedicado a ellos).
2
Lisa y American Anti-intelectualismo
AEON J. Skoble
La sociedad estadounidense en general ha tenido una relación amor-odio con la idea de la
intelectual. Por un lado, hay un sentido de respeto por el profesor o el científico,
pero al mismo tiempo, hay un gran resentimiento de la "torre de marfil" o el "ratón de biblioteca", un
actitud defensiva inteligente o la gente aprendió. Los ideales republicanos de los Fundadores
presupone una ciudadanía ilustrada, sin embargo, a día de hoy, la introducción de ni siquiera remotamente
sofisticados análisis de temas políticos es denunciado como "elitismo". Todo el mundo respeta a un
historiador, sin embargo, un historiador opinión pueda tenerse en cuenta en la base de que "no es más
comentaristas populistas válido "que el de" hombre de trabajo. "y los políticos con frecuencia
aprovechar esta experiencia, mientras que el resentimiento de confiar en ella, ya que les conviene, por ejemplo, cuando un
los ataques al candidato de su oponente de ser un elitista "Ivy League", mientras que en el hecho de ser un
producto de (o confiar en los asesores de) una formación académica similar.
Del mismo modo, un hospital puede consultar a un especialista en bioética, o puede rechazar el consejo de
en bioética, sobre la base de que son demasiado abstractas y ajenas a las realidades de la
la medicina. De hecho, parece como si la mayoría de la gente como ser capaz de apoyar sus posiciones
por los expertos se cita, pero a continuación, invocar el sentimiento populista cuando los expertos no apoyan a sus
ver. Por ejemplo, yo puedo apoyar a mi argumento citando a un experto que está de acuerdo con
de mí, pero si un experto no está de acuerdo, puedo responder "¿qué sabe?" o "Tengo derecho a mi
opinión también. "Curiosamente, vemos que el anti-intelectualismo, incluso entre los intelectuales. Por ejemplo, en
muchas universidades de hoy, tanto entre el alumnado y el profesorado, el papel de la
clásicos, y las humanidades en general, ha disminuido considerablemente. La tendencia ha sido claramente
para desarrollar programas de pre-profesional y poner de relieve la "pertinencia", mientras que tradicional
humanidades, las clases son considerados como un lujo o una mejora, pero no realmente necesario
características de una educación universitaria. En el mejor de ellos son vistos como vehículos para el desarrollo de
"habilidades transferibles", como la composición o el pensamiento crítico.
Parece que hay péndulo periódicos: en los años 1950 y 1960, se
fue un gran respeto por los científicos, como la nación se encontraba compitiendo contra la
Soviéticos en áreas como la exploración del espacio. Hoy en día, parece que el péndulo se ha invertido
swing, como el Zeitgeist actual tiene todas las opiniones son igualmente válidas. Pero, al mismo tiempo,
la gente todavía parece estar interesado en qué supuestos los expertos tienen que decir. Una rápida revisión de la TV
programas de entrevistas o cartas de los periódicos de al editor revela esta ambivalencia. El talk show se
libro de un experto, porque, presumiblemente, la gente estará interesada en el análisis de esa persona o
opinión. Sin embargo, los panelistas o miembros de la audiencia que están en desacuerdo con los expertos afirman
de que sus opiniones, sus puntos de vista, son tan vale la pena. Un periódico se ejecuta un
columna de opinión de un especialista, cuyo análisis sobre la situación puede estar mejor informados que
de la persona media, pero las cartas de personas que están en desacuerdo con frecuencia se basa en la
subyacente (si no declarada) premisa de que "Nadie sabe nada" o "Es todo una cuestión de
opinión, y el mío también cuenta. "Esta última razón es especialmente insidiosa: de hecho, si se
cierto que todo se limita a una cuestión de opinión, los que en realidad se sigue que
el mío es tan relevante como el experto y, de hecho, no habría tal cosa como la experiencia.
Por lo tanto, es justo decir que la sociedad norteamericana está en conflicto acerca de los intelectuales. Respeto
para ellos parece prácticamente a ir de la mano con el resentimiento. Este es un bien social desconcertante
problema, y también uno de gran importancia, ya que parecen estar al borde de una nueva y oscura "
las edades ", donde no sólo la noción de experiencia, pero todos los estándares de la racionalidad se
tela de juicio. Evidentemente, esto tiene importantes consecuencias sociales. Como vehículo para la exploración
de este problema, puede ser sorprendente para elegir un programa de televisión que, a primera vista, parece dedicado
a la idea de que tonto es mejor, pero en realidad, de las muchas cosas que Los Simpson
hábilmente ilustra acerca de la sociedad, la ambivalencia de América acerca de la experiencia y la
la racionalidad es claramente uno de ellas.1
En Los Simpson, Homer es un ejemplo clásico de un anti-bobo intelectual, como son
la mayoría de sus conocidos, y su hijo. Pero su hija, Lisa, no sólo pro-intelectual,
ella es inteligente más allá de sus años. Ella es extremadamente inteligente y sofisticado, y es a menudo
visto salir el pensamiento de quienes la rodean. Naturalmente, para esto, ella se burla de los otros niños
en la escuela y generalmente ignorado por los adultos. Por otra parte, su programa de televisión favorito es
la misma que su hermano: una historieta sin pensar violentos. Su tratamiento en el programa, me
argumentan, captura el amor-odio de la sociedad americana tiene relación con intellectuals.2 Antes de
En cuanto a la forma en que lo hace, echemos un vistazo más de cerca el problema.
Falaz Autoridad y el Real Experiencia
Es un alimento básico de los cursos de la lógica de introducción que es una falacia "apelación a la autoridad",
sin embargo, la gente suele hacer más de esto que es apropiado. Estrictamente en términos de lógica, es
siempre es un error afirmar que una proposición es verdadera, porque así-y-así dice que es, pero las apelaciones
a la autoridad son más comúnmente utilizados para demostrar que tenemos una buena razón para creer que el
propuesta, a diferencia de la prueba en contrario de su verdad. Como todas las falacias participación de la pertinencia,
El problema con la mayoría de las apelaciones a la autoridad es que están invocando la autoridad de una
manera irrelevante. Por ejemplo, en los asuntos que realmente son subjetivos, como que la pizza o
refrescos debo comprar, cualquier persona que invoque lo demás es irrelevante, ya que no pueden tener el mismo
tastes.3 En otros casos, el error es de suponer que porque una persona es una autoridad sobre
una cosa, que la experiencia de la persona debe llevar el día en todas las áreas. Esto lo vemos en la celebridad
anotaciones para los productos no vinculados al campo de esa persona. Por ejemplo, Troy McClure
apoyar la cerveza Duff no constituiría un recurso válido a la autoridad, desde que un actor
no hace a nadie un experto en la cerveza. (Y la experiencia no es la misma experiencia: Barney es
no es un experto sobre la cerveza tampoco.) En otros casos, la apelación es falaz el argumento de que
algunas cuestiones no puedan resolverse mediante la apelación a los expertos, no porque son subjetivos, pero
porque se puede saber, por ejemplo, el futuro del progreso científico. El clásico
ejemplo de ello es la afirmación de Einstein en 1932 que "no hay la menor indicación de que la
[nucleares] de la energía nunca se podrá conseguir "4.
Pero después de la construcción de todo este escepticismo acerca de las apelaciones a la autoridad, vale la pena
recordar que algunas personas saben más acerca de algunas cosas que otras personas,
y en muchos casos, el hecho de que una autoridad sobre un tema nos dice algo que realmente es un buen
razón para creer. Por ejemplo, ya que no tengo conocimiento de primera mano de la Batalla de
Marathon, voy a tener que depender de lo que otras personas me dicen, y un historiador clásico
es precisamente el tipo de persona que debe ir, mientras que un médico es probablemente not.5
A menudo, lo que molesta es la aplicación de la sabiduría, sobre todo a la moral o social
ideales. La gente puede argumentar que sí, que hay tal cosa como ser un experto en la
Guerras greco-persas, pero eso no significa que esa persona puede informar a nuestra discusión sobre
la política mundial today.6 Usted puede ser un experto en la teoría moral de Aristóteles, pero que no
significa que usted puede decirme cómo debo vivir. Este tipo de resistencia se debe en parte a la experiencia
de la naturaleza de un régimen democrático, y el problema no es nuevo, pero fue identificado por la
los filósofos desde Platón. Dado que, en una democracia, hacerse oír todas las voces, esto puede conducir
las personas a la conclusión de que todas las voces tienen el mismo valor. Las democracias tienden a justificarse a sí mismos
a diferencia de las aristocracias o las oligarquías que sustituyen o resistir. En las sociedades elitistas,
algunos presumir de saber más, o de hecho a ser mejores personas, mientras que los demócratas saben
mejor: todos son iguales. Pero, por supuesto, la igualdad política no implica que nadie puede poseer
conocimiento de que otros carecen y, de hecho algunos piensan eso de la mayoría de las habilidades, por ejemplo,
plomería o reparación de automóviles. Nadie, aunque (dicen), puede saber más que nadie sobre
cómo vivir, cómo ser justo. Por lo tanto una especie de relativismo se desarrolla: desde el rechazo de la
las élites gobernantes, que de hecho pueden no haber tenido una idea mejor que nadie acerca de la justicia, que
un rechazo de la noción de normas objetivas del bien y del mal del todo. ¿Qué es el derecho es
lo que yo siento que es correcto, lo que es correcto-para-mí. Hoy en día, hay una tendencia, incluso en la academia para
nociones de diferencias de la objetividad y experiencia. Se dice que no hay historias de verdad, sólo
las diferentes interpretaciones de la historia7 No hay interpretaciones correctas de las obras literarias,
sólo diferentes interpretations.8 Incluso la ciencia física se dice que está cargado de valor y de
no objective.9
Así que tenemos todos estos factores que contribuyen a un clima en el que la noción de
experiencia se erosiona, pero al mismo tiempo, vemos que las tendencias compensatorias. Si no hay tal
cosa como la experiencia, y todas las opiniones son igualmente válidas, ¿por qué son los talk shows y best-seller
listas de población por los expertos en el amor y los ángeles? ¿Por qué ver esos espectáculos o leer libros en la
primer lugar? ¿Por qué enviar a los niños a la escuela? Claramente, la gente aún poner algo de acción en el
noción de competencia, y en muchos casos, aspiran a su orientación. La gente de hecho parece haber
algunas tendencias a la que desean que se les diga qué hacer. Algunos críticos de la religión atribuyen su
influencia a una necesidad psicológica, pero tenemos que buscar más allá de la esfera política a la
ver la evidencia de ello. La gente mira a las figuras políticas para el liderazgo de su "": Estamos teniendo un
problema con el desempleo - no alguien sabe cómo hacer algo al respecto? Esto
persona que sería un mejor presidente que debido a que uno sabe cómo reducir el crimen,
terminar con la pobreza, hacer que nuestros hijos mejor, y así sucesivamente. Sin embargo, la ambivalencia se muestra muy
claramente en estos contextos. Si el candidato Smith basa su recurso en su experiencia y capacidad para
"hacer el trabajo", candidato Jones probablemente se cargará Smith de ser una elite, una
"puntiaguda cabeza." También vemos la situación paradójica en la cual los pronunciamientos celebridades '
en asuntos políticos tomen en serio, como si ser un talentoso músico o actor dio mayor
peso a uno los puntos de vista político, mientras que al mismo tiempo, la noción de ser un experto en la
gobierno es ridiculizado. Con cuyas opiniones son la mayoría de los estadounidenses más familiar, Alec
Baldwin y Charlton Heston, o de John Rawls y Robert Nozick?
Además de la experiencia política, la gente también anhelan, y parecen menos ambivalente
sobre, los conocimientos tecnológicos. La mayoría de personas se apresuran a reconocer sus propios
la incompetencia en la plomería, reparación de automóviles, y la cirugía, y felizmente a su vez más de las tareas a
los expertos. En el caso del cirujano, vemos otra manifestación de la ambivalencia
Que tengo en mente, es decir, cuando la gente defiende la medicina alternativa o curación espiritual --
¿qué saben los médicos? Se trata de un goteo desde el momento de la tendencia de moda en la
el mundo académico, que sostiene que toda ciencia es cargadas de valores y no objetivo. Pero no
tienen los defensores de la "plomería alternativa" o "auto de la reparación espiritual", por lo que estas personas
la experiencia es más generalmente aceptados, y hacer cosas por sí mismos no son un contra-ejemplo,
ya que es más una cuestión de uno mismo como en relación con ese tipo de artesano, en vez de negar
que nadie lo es. Además, desde fontaneros y mecánicos con menor frecuencia la posición de
a sí mismos como expertos en los campos más allá de sus propias, como los cirujanos podrían posicionarse como
especialistas en ética, que son menos susceptibles de ser considerados skeptically.10
No admiramos o se ríen de Lisa?
Anti-intelectualismo de América, entonces, es omnipresente, pero no lo abarca todo. Como
lo hace con muchos otros aspectos de la sociedad moderna, Los Simpson a menudo usa este tema como
forraje para su sátira. En la familia Simpson, Lisa realmente sólo podría ser descrito como una
intelectual. Pero su retrato como tal no es inequívocamente halagador.

Los simpson (1º parte) Traducido por google traductor

Los Simpson y la Filosofía
El D'oh! de Homero
Cultura Popular y Filosofía, Tomo 02
Editado por William Irwin, Mark T. Conard, y Aeon J. Skoble
abe-book v3.0 / Notas en EOF
(Anotaciones aparecen al final de cada ensayo)
Contraportada:
Nada menos que una autoridad que Homer Simpson se ha declarado: "Dibujos animados no se
tiene un profundo significado. Son dibujos estúpido que le dan una risa barata ".
¿Todavía no tienes una vaca, hombre. Aquí viene un escuadrón de eruditos con el valor de
incluso desafiar a la visión pesimista de Homero de la difícil situación histórica de su familia.
Homer Simpson se presentan realmente las virtudes de Aristóteles? ¿Podemos aprender de
Maggie sobre el valor del silencio? Bart es el tipo de Nietzsche individuo estaba tratando de
nos advierten sobre? ¿Cómo iluminar Lisa ambivalencia norteamericana hacia los intelectuales?
Aquí se puede encontrar información sobre la ironía y el sentido de la vida, la política de la central nuclear de
de la familia, el marxismo en Springfield, la fugacidad de la felicidad, la parodia popular como una forma de
tributo, y por qué necesitamos animado programas de televisión. Como si todo esto fuera poco, este libro
en realidad contiene el ensayo peor de la filosofía nunca.
Ahora que hemos Los Simpson y la filosofía, todos podemos frotar las manos juntas
y decir, con voz pausada, siniestra, entrecortada: "Excelente..."
"La mayoría de los estudiosos del arte de masas tienen a sí mismos a una distancia de su objeto. Los autores de
este volumen realmente sumergirse en Los Simpson, y el resultado es absolutamente
libro único. Go for it! "- El profesor David Carrier, Carnegie Mellon University,
"Bill Irwin y sus colegas han hecho de nuevo: se han producido un volumen increíble. No
sólo es Los Simpson y la filosofía altamente educativa, mejora la visualización y la
Re-visión de los episodios de Los Simpson, y arroja una nueva luz sobre la serie. "- Profesor Per
Broman, Butler University, Indianápolis,
"¡Qué gran libro! Los capítulos se convierte en diversión, profunda e instructiva. Yo recomiendo
a todo el mundo, si ya es un fan Simpsons o no. Usted se sorprenderá de lo que la sabiduría
se esconde en estas páginas. "- Tom Morris, autor de Si Aristóteles Ran General Motors,
"Los Simpson y la filosofía es un gran lugar para empezar cualquier programa en los estudios de Los Simpson.
Una mirada seria a un tema gracioso. "- Mark I. Pinsky, autor de El Evangelio según
Los Simpsons
William Irwin, Mark T. Canard, y Aeon J. Skoble contribuido a Seinfeld y
Filosofía (2000), que Irwin editado. Irwin es profesor asistente de filosofía en la
King's College, Pennsylvania, y autor de Interpretación intencionalista (1999). Dr.
Conard ha publicado artículos académicos sobre Kant, Nietzsche, y Quentin Tarantino. Dr.
Skoble enseña filosofía en la Academia Militar de EE.UU. en West Point, y ha co-editado
Filosofía Política: Selecciones Essential (1999).
Cultura Popular y Filosofía
Editor General: William Irwin
Tomo 01
Seinfeld y la filosofía: Un libro de todo y nada (2000)
Editado por William Irwin
Tomo 02
The Simpsons and Philosophy: The D'oh! de Homero (2001)
Editado por William Irwin, Mark T. Conard, y Aeon J. Skoble
Tomo 03
The Matrix and Philosophy: Bienvenido al desierto de lo real (2002)
Editado por William Irwin
En preparación:
Buffy the Vampire Slayer y Filosofía (2003)
Editado por James B. Sur
El Señor de los Anillos y Filosofía (2003)
Editado por Gregory Bassham y Eric Bronson
Woody Allen y Filosofía (2004)
Editado por Mark T. Conard y Aeon J. Skoble
Tomo 2 de la serie, Cultura Popular y Filosofía
Para ordenar los libros de Open Court, llame al número gratuito 1-800-815-2280.
Capítulo 11 fue publicado originalmente en Political Theory 27 (1999),
pp. 734-749, y se reproduce aquí con permiso del autor
y Sage Publications, Inc.
Imagen de la portada de "Los Simpsons © 2001 por Bongo Entertainment, Inc.
Todos los derechos reservados. Los Simpsons y ® © Twentieth Century Fox
Film Corporation. Todos los derechos reservados.
Open Court Publishing Company es una división de Carus Publishing Company.
Copyright © 2001 por Carus Publishing Company
Impresión Decimocuarta 2002
Decimoquinta impresión 2002
Impresión Decimosexta 2003
Decimoséptima de impresión 2003
Impresión Decimoctava 2003
Impresión XIX 2003
Todos los derechos reservados. Ninguna parte de esta publicación puede ser reproducida,
almacenada en un sistema de recuperación o transmitida en cualquier forma o por cualquier
medio, sea electrónico, mecánico, fotocopia, grabación, o de lo contrario,
sin la previa autorización por escrito de la editorial Open Court
Publishing Company, una división de Carus Publishing Company, 315
Fifth Street, PO Box 300, Perú, Illinois, 61354-0300.
Impreso y encuadernado en los Estados Unidos de América
Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Los Simpson y la filosofía: el D'oh! de Homero /
editado por William Irwin, Mark Conard, y Aeon Skoble.
p. cm. - (La cultura popular y la filosofía; v.2)
Incluye bibliografía e índice.
ISBN 0-8126-9433-3 (pbk.)
1. Filosofía - Miscellanea. 2. Simpson. (Programa de televisión) --
Miscellanea. I. Irwin, William, 1970 - II. Conard, Mark, 1965 --
III. Skoble, Aeon J. Serie IV
. B68 S55 2001
100 - dc21 00-069897
Dedicado a Lionel Hutz y Troy McClure
(a quien usted puede recordar de programas de televisión como The Simpsons)
Contenidos
Agradecimientos
Introducción: Meditaciones sobre Springfield?
Parte I - Los personajes
1. Homero y Aristóteles
RAJA Halwani
2. Lisa y American Anti-intelectualismo
AEON J. Skoble
3. ¿Por qué Maggie materia: Sonidos del Silencio, Este y Oeste
ERIC BRONSON
4. Moral de Marge Motivación
Gerald J. Erion y Joseph A. ZECCARDI
5. Así habló Bart: sobre Nietzsche y las virtudes de ser malo
Mark T. Conard
Parte II - Temas Simpsonian
6. Los Simpson y la alusión: "Lo peor Ensayo Ever"
William Irwin y JR LOMBARDO
7. Popular Parody: The Simpsons Meets The Deborah Cine Delito
KNIGHT
8. Los Simpson, la tecnología Hyper-ironía y el sentido de la vida
CARL MATHESON
9. Simpsonian Política sexual
DALE E. Snow y James J. NIEVE
Parte III - I Didn't Do It: Ética y Los Simpson
10. El mundo moral de la familia Simpson: una perspectiva kantiana
JAMES LAWLER
11. Los Simpson: Política atomista y la familia nuclear
PAUL A. CANTOR
12. La hipocresía de Springfield
Jason Holt
13. Disfrutar de la llamada "helado con nata", el Sr. Burns, Satanás, y Felicidad
DANIEL Barwick
14. -Hey-ho, Diddily, Neighboreenos: Ned Flanders y el amor al prójimo
DAVID VESSEY
15. La función de la ficción: el valor heurístico de Homero JENNIFER L.
MCMAHON
Parte IV - Los Simpson y los filósofos
16. Un (Karl, no Groucho) marxista en Springfield,
JAMES M. Wallace
17. ¿Y el resto se escribe: Roland Barthes Relojes de Los Simpson
DAVID LG ARNOLD
18. Lo que llama Bart Pensamiento
Kelly Dean Jolley
Lista de episodios
Basado en las ideas por
Con las voces de
Índice
Agradecimientos
La redacción, edición, y otras tareas de diversos involucrados en la producción de
Simpson y la filosofía equivale a una experiencia divertida y estimulante. Nos gustaría
gracias a los contribuyentes para mantener tanto un sentido de profesionalismo y sentido del humor
todo el proyecto. Sinceramente, quisiera dar las gracias a la buena gente en el Open de tenis,
sobre todo a David y Jennifer Ramsay Steele Asmuth por su asesoramiento y asistencia. Y,
por último pero no menos importante, nos gustaría agradecer a nuestros amigos, colegas y estudiantes con los cuales
hablamos de Los Simpson y la filosofía, que ayudó a hacer el trabajo posible, y que
ofrece información muy valiosa sobre el trabajo en curso. Una lista como esta es casi inevitable
incompleto, pero entre aquellos a quienes estamos en deuda son: Trisha Allen, Lisa Bahnemann,
Anthony Hartle, Megan Lloyd, Jennifer O'Neill, y Peter Stromberg.
Introducción:
Meditaciones sobre Springfield?
Como muchos filósofos se tarda en escribir un libro acerca de Los Simpson?
Al parecer, alrededor de 20 a escribirlo y 3 para editar. Pero eso no es tan malo, teniendo en cuenta que se necesita 300
los 8 meses, a un costo de 1,5 millones de dólares, para hacer un solo episodio de Los Simpson.
Hablando en serio, sin embargo, no tenemos otras cosas que hacer además de escribir acerca de programas de televisión? El
respuesta corta es sí, sí, pero nos gustaba escribir estos ensayos, y esperamos que usted disfrutará de
su lectura.
Las semillas de este volumen fueron sembradas hace unos años. Cuando la comedia popular
Seinfeld iba a salir del aire, William Irwin tenía una idea extravagante - una colección de
ensayos filosóficos en el show de "de nada". Él y sus amigos filósofo disfrutado de la
Mostrar y participó en muchas discusiones humorística y estimulante de ello, ¿por qué no
compartir la diversión en la forma de un libro? La gente de Open Court tuvo la visión, la fortaleza y la
sentido del humor para asumir el proyecto, por lo que Irwin se encontraba edición Seinfeld y
La filosofía: un libro sobre todo y nada. El libro fue un verdadero éxito, no sólo
entre los académicos, pero entre el público en general.
Otro programa de televisión de Irwin y sus amigos disfrutan y se había discutido la
Simpson, agradecieron su ironía, su irreverencia, y se dieron cuenta de que - como Seinfeld
- Era una tierra rica y fértil para la investigación filosófica y el debate. Así que Irwin
decidió formar un segundo volumen, esta vez en Los Simpson, y le pidió a dos de los
contribuyentes con el libro de Seinfeld, Mark Conard y Aeon Skoble, para co-editar la obra.
Una vez más, Open Court aplaudió la idea, y si estás leyendo esto, obviamente estás en
lo menos un poco interesa ni la filosofía, Los Simpson, o ambos. El concepto es el mismo:
el programa tiene suficiente inteligencia y profundidad para garantizar un debate filosófico, y
como un programa popular, también puede servir como un vehículo para explorar una variedad de filosofía
temas para el público en general.
Los Simpson es rica en sátira. Sin lugar a dudas es uno de los más inteligentes y
leer y escribir comedias en la televisión hoy en día. (Sabemos que no es decir mucho, pero...) Es posible
parece incongruente a quienes lo tomaron como un simple dibujo animado sobre un patán y su
de la familia (y hemos visto muchos de esos) para decir que el programa es inteligente y leer y escribir, pero
Quienes han visitado la atenta revela los niveles de la comedia más allá de la farsa. Vemos capa sobre capa de
la sátira, doble sentido, las alusiones a la alta, así como la cultura popular, gags visuales, la parodia,
humor y auto-referencial. En respuesta a las críticas de Homero, de una caricatura que sus hijos son
ver, Lisa responde: "Si caricaturas eran para adultos, que estarían en en el prime time!"
A pesar de las palabras de Lisa, Los Simpsons es claramente para adultos, y es superficial, para descartar el
Mostrar sólo porque es popular y animada.
Matt Groening estudió filosofía en la universidad, pero ninguno de los colaboradores de este
libro cree que hay una filosofía profunda de dibujos animados de Groening. Esto no es "la
la filosofía de "Los Simpsons" o "Los Simpson como la filosofía", sino de Los Simpson y
Filosofía. No estamos tratando de transmitir el significado deseado de Groening y de la
legión de escritores y artistas que trabajan en el programa. Más bien, estamos destacando el
importancia filosófica de Los Simpson como la vemos. Algunos de los ensayos en este libro son
de las reflexiones de los académicos en un programa que les gusta y que creen que dice algo
sobre un aspecto de la filosofía. Por ejemplo, Daniel Barwick mira al avaro
cascarrabias, el Sr. Burns, para determinar si podemos aprender algo sobre la naturaleza de la
la felicidad de la infelicidad de Burns. Otros exploran la idea de un filósofo de
haciendo uso de uno de los personajes. Por ejemplo, Mark Conard plantea la cuestión, se puede
El rechazo de Nietzsche de la moral tradicional justificar el mal comportamiento de Bart? Sin embargo otros utilizan el
muestran como un vehículo para el desarrollo de temas filosóficos en una forma que sea accesible a la
no especialista (una persona inteligente que tiene algún interés en la reflexión filosófica, sino
que no se ganan la vida en ello). Por ejemplo, Jason Holt explora "Springfield hipocresía"
para determinar si la hipocresía es siempre inmoral.
Este libro no es un intento de reducir la filosofía al mínimo común
denominador, no tenemos ninguna "prueba de tontos-down" del programa. Por el contrario, esperamos que para conseguir nuestros
los lectores no especializados para leer más filosofía, de las que no se trata de televisión
muestra. También esperamos que nuestros colegas que leer estos ensayos se encuentran a ambos
la reflexión y entretenimiento.
¿Es legítimo escribir ensayos filosóficos sobre la cultura popular? La norma
respuesta a esa pregunta es para señalar que Sófocles y Shakespeare eran populares
la cultura en su día, y nadie pone en duda la validez de las reflexiones filosóficas sobre su
trabajo. Pero eso no va a hacer en el caso de Los Simpson. (D'oh!) Hacer que la respuesta invita a
la percepción errónea de que creemos que Los Simpson es el equivalente de las mejores obras de la historia de la
la literatura, muy profundo en una forma que ilumina la condición humana como nunca antes.
Nosotros no. Pero, no obstante, es lo suficientemente profunda, y sin duda lo suficientemente divertido, como para justificar
seria atención. Además, su popularidad significa que podemos utilizar Los Simpson como
medio para ilustrar las cuestiones filosóficas tradicionales para llegar efectivamente a los lectores de fuera de
la academia.
Y por favor, tenga en cuenta que, aunque en ocasiones se nos acusados de
impiedad y ejecutados, los filósofos son gente también. ¿Todavía no tienes una vaca, hombre.
Parte I
Los personajes
1
Homero y Aristóteles
RAJA Halwani
[M] es, a pesar de su aspecto, dejar de ver lo que es el bienestar, ¿qué es el bien en la vida. - Aristóteles, Eudemo
Ética, 1216a10
No puedo vivir en el botón de abajo la vida como tú. I want it all! Los mínimos aterradora, los máximos de vértigo, la
centros que crema! Claro, yo podría ofender a algunos de los azul-la nariz con mi paso arrogante y almizclado olores
- Oh, nunca seré el favorito de los llamados "padres de la ciudad" que cacarean sus lenguas, sus tiempos
las barbas, y hablar acerca de "¿Qué se puede hacer con ese Homero Simpson?" - Homer Simpson ", Lisa
Rival "
Homer Simpson no le va bien cuando se evalúa moralmente. Esto es especialmente cierto
si el foco está en su carácter más que en sus actos (aunque no exactamente brillar en
esta última categoría tampoco). Sin embargo, de alguna manera, hay algo que es éticamente admirable,
sobre Homero. Esto plantea el siguiente acertijo: Si Homer Simpson tarifas mal moralmente, en el
¿De qué manera es lo admirable? Vamos a investigar esto.
Tipos de caracteres de Aristóteles
Aristóteles nos da una categorización lógica de los cuatro tipos de character.1 Aproximadamente
hablando, y dejando de lado los dos tipos extremos de lo sobrehumano y lo bestial
personajes, tenemos el virtuoso, el continente, la incontinencia, y el carácter vicioso.
Para entender mejor cada tipo, quiero contrastar unos con otros en términos de cómo cada uno
el carácter se manifiesta en las acciones, decisiones y deseos. Vamos a considerar también una situación
como un ejemplo y ver cómo cada personaje para responder a ellas.
Supongamos que alguien, vamos a llamarla "Lisa", estaban caminando por la calle y encontré un
cartera con una cantidad sustancial de dinero en ella. Ahora bien, si Lisa fueron virtuosos, que no se
sólo tomar la decisión de convertir en la cartera a las autoridades competentes, se haría con gusto
tan. Deseos de Lisa estaría en consonancia con su decisión de derecho y la acción. Consideremos ahora
Lenny, que es el continente: si Lenny se para encontrar el monedero, él sería capaz de hacer que el
decisión correcta - para devolver la billetera intacta - y que sería capaz de actuar sobre su decisión de
de hacerlo, pero tendría que ir en contra de sus deseos de no hacerlo. Esta es la marca de la
persona continente: tiene que luchar contra sus deseos de poder hacer lo correcto.
Con la incontinencia urinaria y los tipos vicioso, las cosas empeoran. La incontinencia
persona es capaz de llegar a la decisión correcta sobre qué hacer, sino que sufren de debilidad
de la voluntad. En el caso de la cartera, y suponiendo que Bart es nuestro carácter de incontinencia, le
sucumbir a su deseo de mantener la cartera y así dejar de actuar correctamente, a pesar de que sabe
que el mantenimiento no es correcto. Con la persona vicioso, no hay lucha contra los deseos de uno
y no hay debilidad de la voluntad. La razón, sin embargo, es que la decisión de la persona de Vicious
es moralmente incorrecto, y sus deseos son completamente cooperativa con él. Si Nelson se vicioso, que
decidiera quedarse con el dinero (y, o bien desechar el resto de la cartera, o devolverlo
pero mentir acerca de su contenido original), sería totalmente el deseo de hacerlo, y de hecho así lo haría.
Echemos un vistazo a qué es lo que constituye un carácter virtuoso. Un virtuoso
es una persona que tiene y ejerce las virtudes. Las virtudes, además, son los estados (o rasgos)
de carácter que disponen a su poseedor para actuar en la forma correcta y de reaccionar emocionalmente en
de la forma correcta también. Teniendo en cuenta esto, vemos por qué Aristóteles insistía en que las virtudes son los estados de
personaje en cuestión con la acción y la sensación (Ética, libro II, especialmente 1106b15-35).
Por ejemplo, si uno tiene la virtud de la benevolencia, entonces estará dispuesto a ser
de beneficencia a las personas adecuadas en las circunstancias adecuadas. Uno no debería dar dinero a
cualquiera que se lo pidió. La persona virtuosa debe percibir que su receptor está en la necesidad
del dinero, y que se la usa correctamente. Además, la persona virtuosa emocional
la reacción es adecuada a la situación. Esto significa que la persona benevolente en nuestra
ejemplo sería darle el dinero de buena gana, no se arrepiente de darle, y se trasladó a darle
por la difícil situación de su destinatario. Por el contrario, una persona continente que no es fácil separarse de su
de dinero, y esto es así no porque lo necesita y no puede prescindir de ella, sino porque se dispone que
a ser avaros, o para estimar el exceso de lo mucho que puede necesitar el dinero en el futuro.
Pero nótese que, dado el relato anterior, la razón tiene un papel crucial que desempeñar. Porque, si a
ser virtuoso debe tener capacidad de percepción sobre la situación se enfrenta,
a continuación, la persona virtuosa no puede ser estúpido o ingenuo. Se debe tener la capacidad de razonamiento crítico
que le permitiría a notar las diferencias en las situaciones y así ser capaces de responder
en consecuencia. De hecho, esta es una razón por qué Aristóteles hizo hincapié en la idea de que la
objeto de la ética no admite rigurosa precisión (Ética, 1094b13-19). El
papel de la razón práctica (phrónesis) es algo que Aristóteles insistía: si uno se
virtuoso, por así decirlo, el impulso, no se poseen "completo" en la virtud, sino más "natural"
(virtud ética, 1144b3-15), y poseer la virtud natural es que se inclina a hacer la derecha
algo por accidente, por decirlo de loosely.2
Si ahora nos traen en condiciones de Aristóteles para la acción correcta, estaremos en condiciones de
completar nuestra cuenta. Aristóteles afirma, "En primer lugar [el agente] debe saber que él está haciendo
acciones virtuosas, en segundo lugar, debe decidir sobre ellos, y decidir por sí mismos, y,
En tercer lugar, también debe hacer desde un carácter firme e inalterable "(Ética,
1105a30-1105b). En pocas palabras, lo que Aristóteles tenía en mente aquí es la siguiente. En primer lugar, el agente
debe, al actuar bien sabe que su acción es virtuoso, que actúa bajo la denominación
que "tal y tal acción es justo (o generoso, honesto o)." La segunda condición parece
para incluir dos, y no uno, las condiciones. El agente debe actuar de forma voluntaria, y deberá hacerlo
porque la acción es virtuosa. Así que incluso si uno fuera a actuar conforme a la descripción que "este
la acción es justo ", la acción de uno no sería virtuosa a menos que uno también lo hizo porque la acción es
justo. La tercera condición establecida es crucial, y nos lleva al inicio de este debate: una
persona virtuosa actúa virtuosamente, no sólo cuando la acción es justo y porque es así, pero
actúa virtuosamente, porque es una persona leal. Él es el tipo de persona que esté dispuesta a
comportarse moralmente correcta cuando la situación lo requiere. Esto es (parte de) lo que significa que
tienen un "firme e inalterable" de carácter.
De caracteres de Homero:
D'oh!, D'oh!, Y Double D'oh!
Habida cuenta de la cuenta de Aristóteles de la virtud, las cosas se ven bastante tenue de Homer Simpson (y de
Yo no más tarde rescindir la presente sentencia, así que no esperes una distinción ingeniosa que se
revisión de esta afirmación). Consideremos, como un comienzo, la virtud de la templanza (moderación), que,
básicamente, aunque un tanto discutible, abarca la capacidad de moderar nuestro cuerpo
apetitos. No requiere la observación sagaz para darse cuenta de que Homer está lejos de ser un
hombre templado. No sólo no es virtuoso con respecto a sus apetitos corporales, pero es
muy vicioso. Esto es particularmente cierto con respecto al consumo de Homero y de los alimentos
la bebida, en lugar de la actividad sexual. Sus deseos le empujan constantemente a hartarse, y
sucumbe de buena gana a estos deseos. Por ejemplo, en "Homer's Enemy" 3, que
de todo corazón se comió la mitad de un sándwich que pertenecía a sus compañeros de trabajo temporal Frank
Grimes - o "Grimey" - a pesar de que la bolsa de sandwich estaba claramente marcado en el sentido de
que pertenecía a este último. Peor aún, incluso después de Grimes lo señaló a él, Homero
lograron tomar dos bocados extra fuera del bocadillo antes de volver a colocarlo en la bolsa.
El deseo de Homero de los alimentos también le lleva a crear algunas recetas interesantes. Veamos, por
ejemplo, su envolver un medio cocer waffle alrededor de un palo toda la mantequilla y, por supuesto,
comiendo ( "Homer the Heretic"). De la salud de Homero se ve amenazada por los malos hábitos alimenticios, para
el punto de que tuvo que someterse a una operación de bypass ( "Homer's Triple Bypass"), pero que
no ha cedido. De hecho, aun cuando soportar el dolor físico inmediato y obvio, Homero
no cede. Testigo de su consumo de carne mal en el Kwik-E-Mart, enfermarse, y de ser
de urgencia al hospital. En lugar de perseguir su denuncia contra Apu, fue inmediatamente
apaciguado ( "Woo-hoo!") por la oferta de Apu de diez libras de camarón libre de rancio. Homero sabía
de que el camarón olía "divertido", se lo comió de todas maneras, y luego se lanzó de nuevo al hospital,
( "Homero y Apu"). La gula de Homero es una parte tan importante de su carácter, que consume
alimentos, incluso mientras medio dormido. En "Rosebud", de Homero, medio dormido, entra en la cocina,
abre la puerta de la nevera, comentó: "Mmm... 64 lonchas de queso americano", y la
procede a comer por la duración de la noche. El punto sobre la intemperancia de Homero
no necesita mayor explicación, su nombre ha llegado a ser sinónimo de su amor por la comida
y (Duff) de cerveza.
Homer es también un mentiroso habitual; que carece de honestidad. En "Duffless", mintió a su familia
sobre sus planes para el día, diciéndoles que él iba a trabajar cuando era en realidad
planeando ir a tomar el tour fábrica de cerveza Duff. Para Catálogo de algunos de los demás mentiras de Homero: El
mintió a Marge sobre el hecho de que nunca se graduó de la escuela secundaria ( "El Frente"), mintió
con ella acerca de sus pérdidas financieras en las inversiones ( "Homer contra Patty y Selma"), y
mintiendo al Marge de deshacerse de la pistola que compró ( "The Cartridge Family").
Homero también Apu una vez involucrados en una gran red de mentiras a la madre de éste, diciéndole que
que ya estaba casado con Marge, lo que también obliga a Marge para ir junto con el régimen
( "The Two Mrs. Nahasapeemapetilons").
Homero también carece de sensibilidad a las necesidades y demandas de los demás, parece que falta
tanto en la benevolencia y la justicia. En "When Flanders Failed", que continuamente empujado Ned
De Flandes que le vendan sus muebles para la suciedad de los precios baratos, a pesar de que sabía que era Ned
se rompió y necesitaba desesperadamente dinero. En "Bart, el amante", le aconsejó a Bart, en su alias como
Pluma secreto Woodrow (Sra. Krabappel de amante), para romper con la Sra. Krabappel por escrito
ella una nota que decía: "Querido bebé, Bienvenido a tontolandia. Población: vosotros" (que prologa este
diciendo a Bart que las cartas de amor sensibles son su especialidad). No está inclinado hacia
la generosidad, o bien, él dijo una vez a Bart: "Usted dio a ambos perros fuera? ¿Sabes cómo me siento
trata de dar! "(" The Canine Mutiny "). Y Homero decidió no votar culpable de Freddy
Cargos de asalto de Quimby, no porque pensaba que Quimby era inocente, sino porque
se dio cuenta de que si lo hacía, el jurado va a ser un punto muerto y se llegaría a gratis
en el Hotel Palace de Springfield ( "The Boy Who Knew Too Much").
Homer tiene una serie de amigos, pero él no tiene amigos. Aristóteles hizo hincapié en
la importancia de la amistad debido a sus creencias que sin amigos no podemos ejercer
la virtud y que sin amigos no se puede llevar una vida plena y próspera. Homero no tiene
un verdadero amigo único. En la mayoría de los que ha estado bebiendo amigos (Barney, Lenny y Carl), pero
no tiene a nadie con quien comparte sus objetivos, actividades, alegrías y sorrows.4 De hecho, es
algo de un problema incluso a afirmar que Homero tiene metas y actividades, que no
potable, lo que es.
Habilidades de crianza de los hijos matrimoniales y de Homero también dejan mucho que desear (Aristóteles
parecía haber incluido los cónyuges e hijos en el ámbito de la amistad; ver la ética
1158b9-16). Vamos a considerar algunas de meteduras de pata de Homer. Trató de ganar el amor de Lisa por el
comprarle un pony ( "El pony de Lisa"). Le molestaba Bart para conseguir un "hermano mayor", y así
se convirtió en un hermano mayor a sí mismo Pepi (a quien llamó "Pepsi") ( "el hermano de la
Mismo planeta "). Envió a Bart a trabajar en un salón de burlesque como una forma de castigo (" Bart
After Dark "). Homer alimentado el fuego de la rivalidad entre hermanos cuando Lisa descubrió que tenía un don
para el hockey sobre hielo: "Este equipo de Lisa del viernes está jugando el equipo de Bart. Estás en directo
la competencia. Y no va fácil en sí, sólo porque eres hermano y hermana. Quiero
a ver que ambos luchan por el amor de sus padres "(" Lisa on Ice "). No olvidemos su
estrangulaciones numerosas de Bart, precedido por "¿Por qué usted poco...!" (aunque una vez, en
"Mother Simpson", que era, "Voy a Kwanza usted...!"). Por último, pero ciertamente no menos importante, Homero
continuamente se olvida de que Maggie exists.5
Habilidades civil de Homero no son mejores. Está bien no apoyan o indiferente a
Proyectos de Marge, que profesaba tanto a Marge en "A Streetcar Named Marge". Su
la negativa a ir a espectáculos artísticos y exposiciones, una vez llevado a Marge a buscar la compañía de
Ruth Powers, su amistad aterrizó a las mujeres en una persecución policial à la Thelma y Louise.
Homero disculpas a Marge, pero su disculpa es bastante reveladora: "Mira, Marge, lo siento
No he sido un mejor esposo, lo siento por el tiempo intenté hacer salsa en la bañera,
Lo siento usado su vestido de novia a la cera del coche, y lo siento - Oh, bueno, digamos que
Lo siento por el matrimonio todo hasta este punto "(" Marge on the Lam "). En" Secretos de un
El matrimonio con éxito ", de Homero alcanzó un nuevo máximo. Se dio cuenta de qué era lo que podía
única oferta Marge, y que es "total y absoluta dependencia". De hecho, incluso cuando
trata de ser de apoyo, termina chapucería cosas: Homer, una vez trató de ayudar a pretzel de Marge
comerciales por ir a la mafia de Springfield para ayudar, con lo que Marge aterrizaje en la posición de la
tener que tratar con Tony el Gordo y sus secuaces ( "El retorcido mundo de Marge Simpson").
Además, cualquier esperanza de Homero que podría adquirir las virtudes morales se
frustradas por el reconocimiento de que carece de una virtud intelectual necesarios para la ética
carácter, a saber, el de la sabiduría práctica (phrónesis). Phronesis no es teórica
conocimiento, aunque Homero duda carece de esta, también. Tampoco es el conocimiento de los hechos,
Homero aunque ciertamente carece de esto también. La sabiduría práctica es la capacidad de dirigir la propia
camino por el mundo de manera inteligente, moralmente, y en un objetivo de forma orientada. Algunos ejemplos
será suficiente. En primer lugar, Homero se adhiere a algunas pepitas de muy dudosa de la sabiduría. En
"There's No Disgrace Like Home", afirma, "Cuando voy a aprender? Las respuestas a la vida,
problemas no están en la parte inferior de una botella. Están en la TV! ", Y -, mientras que en el tema de la
botellas - que una vez famoso, tostado, "con el alcohol! La causa de la - y la solución a - todos
problemas de la vida "(" Homer contra la decimoctava enmienda "). En" El Show de Otto ", dijo
Bart que "Si algo es difícil de hacer, entonces no vale la pena hacerlo". Y en "Realty Bites", que
Marge le dijo que "Intentar es el primer paso hacia el fracaso."
En segundo lugar, Homero parece carecer de competencias mínimas de la inferencia. Una vez deducido que
Timmy O'Toole (el niño ficticio que Bart afirma cayó en un pozo) fue un verdadero héroe
desde el simple "hecho" de que había caído en un pozo y no podía salir ( "Radio Bart"). Él
una vez deducido que la política de alcalde Quimby de tener una Patrulla Oso fue un éxito de la
El simple hecho de que no había osos por las calles de Springfield! Cuando Lisa señaló
Apu que su razonamiento era engañosa, pensaba que estaba felicitando a él ( "Mucho
About Nothing "). Homer, una vez motivado contra la pretensión de Lisa que el cable robar es malo por el
", argumentando" que Lisa es un ladrón, ya que ella misma no pagar por sus comidas en el hogar y
para la ropa que usa ( "Homer vs Lisa and the 8th Commandment").
En tercer lugar, Homero le falta uno de los aspectos más cruciales del razonamiento práctico: el
capacidad para organizar su vida en torno a objetivos importantes y dignos, y para su consecución
responsable y moralmente. Él tiene la vida de muchos sueños de largo, como convertirse en un
conductor del monorraíl ( "Marge vs the Monorail") y ser dueño de los Vaqueros de Dallas ( "Usted
Sólo se muda dos veces "), pero los sueños no son objetivos, y Homer no tiene ningún tipo de estos últimos.
En cualquier caso, desde luego, no tiene ningún tipo de objetivos que son dignos de persecución. Parece
que contentarse con ser un inspector de seguridad de incompetentes, que trabajan en el sector 7G en Burns
planta de energía, ver a algunos de sus subordinados se promueve por delante de él. De hecho, él
estaba dispuesto ( "King-Size Homer") para engordar a sí mismo de modo que pudiera ser en la discapacidad y
trabajar desde casa. Si Homero tiene un único objetivo en la vida, es el de la vida inútil de comer,
potable, y la pereza. Añadir a la totalidad de la credulidad de este supremo de Homero (sólo considerar cómo
muchas veces es capaz de Bart con él), y salir con alguien que tiene un mínimo
la capacidad de razonamiento.
De caracteres de Homero:
El brillo de una Woo Pocos hoos
No debemos, sin embargo, ser demasiado duro con Homero, por lo que hace a veces actuar
admirable. Paradójicamente, por ejemplo, a pesar de que Maggie se olvida de que existe, su trabajo
estación está cubierta con fotos de ella, las imágenes que él mismo se colgó por amor de
ella ( "Y con Maggie son tres"). Homero también a sabiendas, nunca ha cometido adulterio,
a pesar de que podría haber en algunas ocasiones ( "El coronel Homero" y "La Última
Tentación de Homero ") .6 Además, a menudo es cariñoso y amable con Marge: él
re-casado con ella (después de divorciarse de ella) con el fin de compensar su original de mala muerte ","
boda ( "A Milhouse Divided"). Homero también tiene algunos enlaces éxito con Lisa.
Considere lo siguiente: su apoyo a su plan para dar a conocer la red de mentiras que rodean
Orígenes Jebediah Springfield ( "Lisa the Iconclast"), apoyando su confianza entrando
ella en el Little Miss Springfield Pageant ( "Lisa, la reina de la belleza"), dos veces sacrificar
compra de un acondicionador de aire con el fin de conseguirle un saxofón - dos veces ( "Lisa's Sax"), y teniendo en
su sigilosamente en el Museo Springsonian para que finalmente puede llegar a ver el
"Tesoros de la exposición Isis" ( "Lost Our Lisa").
En algunas ocasiones Homer demuestra valentía. Considere lo siguiente: atacó a Mr.
Quemaduras por exigir demasiado de él ( "Homer the Smithers") y para no recordar
su nombre ( "Who Shot Mr. Burns?"), y golpeado, George W. Bush (sus verdaderas razones para
hacerlo no son claras; no son causa de lealtades de partido, ya que se hace amigo de Gerald
Ford, que también es un republicano) ( "Dos malos vecinos"). Homero también muestra los actos de
la bondad, incluso para las personas que generalmente odia. En "When Flanders Failed", que ayudó a Ned por
aumentar las ventas en Leftorium de este último, en "Homer Loves Flanders", se puso de pie para Ned en
la iglesia ( "... este hombre se ha vuelto cada mejilla en su cuerpo"), y en "Homer contra Patty y
Selma ", que pretendía que él era el hábito de fumar para que Patty y Selma no recibe
despedido por fumar en su lugar de trabajo.
Homero a veces incluso se muestra la inteligencia y la sabiduría teórica. Como ejemplos
del régimen anterior, se inventó un elaborado para llevar de contrabando de alcohol a Springfield y
se convirtió en el famoso "Barón Beer" ( "Homer contra la decimoctava enmienda"), y se
ideó un plan para hacer dinero con el esqueleto de un "ángel" ( "Lisa the Skeptic"). Ya que
un ejemplo de este último, Homero muestra una visión inesperada sobre la naturaleza de la religión por la
la decisión de dejar de ir a la iglesia, ya que - como él motivado - Dios está en todas partes.

Los simpson

He even cited, though without remembering his name, Jesus as someone who went against orthodox
practices and yet was right to do so ("Homer the Heretic"). Homer even displays rare
moments in which he seems to know his own limitations. He once asked Marge, "You're
here to see me, right?" when she showed up at the plant, thus revealing his belief that since
he was a man of humble properties, he needed to make sure that Marge was there to see him
("Life on the Fast Lane"). And he double -- and triple -- checked Lurleen Lumpkin's flirting
with him to make sure that she really was sexually interested in him ("Colonel Homer").
Assessment: Judging Homer
What are we to make of all of this? How exactly does Homer stand up to ethical
evaluation? Homer is not an evil person. While he is not a paradigm of virtue, he certainly
is not malicious. The harshest reaction we can have towards him is pity. There are at least
two reasons for this. The first reason is that Homer's upbringing leaves much to be desired.
To begin with, he grew up mostly in Springfield, a town whose inhabitants -- with the rare
exception of Lisa -- have serious and severe character flaws, ranging from stupidity to
malice, to being simply incompetent and clueless in the ways of the world (even Marge,
who is a good candidate for being another exception to the inhabitants of Springfield, is
very conventional and often lacks critical abilities7). Consider that even when the members
of the Springfield chapter of Mensa governed the town (after Mayor Quimby fled), they
managed to propose unfair, restrictive, and highly idealistic rules. Needless to say, chaos
ensued ("They Saved Lisa's Brain").8
The effect of being raised in such an environment could be detrimental to one's
future character formation and intellectual abilities. Furthermore, being raised in a healthy
environment is one of the main claims that grounds Aristotle's project in the Politics: "Our
purpose is to consider what form of political community is best of all for those who are
most able to realize their ideal of life" (1260b25). Indeed, Aristotle's Ethics is also aimed at
the statesman who is to think of what the best ethical character is, so as to design a political
community able to produce such a character. If this is correct, then one reason why we tend
to pity Homer is because we think that this aspect of his upbringing, namely, Springfield, is
beyond his control.
In addition, Homer's rearing at home leaves much to be desired. His mother left him
when he was young, and his father never encouraged him to become anything of worth;
when Homer did have some aspirations, his father shot them down ("Mother Simpson" and
"Bart Star"). Moreover, one quality about Homer that he certainly could not control is the
Simpson gene, which apparently causes a Simpson to grow more stupid as he ages. It "is
defective only on the Y-chromosome" and not on the X one, and that is why Lisa and other
Simpson women have been smart and successful ("Lisa the Simpson"). If so, then there is
little that Homer could do to better himself. And these factors explain why we tend to look
at Homer with pity rather than with disdain or hatred.
The second reason why our judgment of Homer's character is not harsh, even
though he is not virtuous, is that he is not generally a malicious person. He is selfish, he is
a glutton, he is greedy, and he can be quite dumb, but he is rarely one of those people who
are envious of others and who wish them ill-will. It is true that he often acts with deliberate
intent to harm some people, but we think that these people somehow are not worthy of
better treatment. The scorn, for example, which Homer heaps on Selma and Patty seems to
be appropriate, given the way they treat him and given their scornful attitude towards him.
Homer also dislikes (though he also fears) Mr. Burns. And whatever else can be said about
Burns, he is the paradigm case of a greedy, evil, and ruthless capitalist who is willing to
walk on a path of corpses to attain his ends.9 Lastly, Homer treats Flanders in indecent
ways, ranging from indifference to disdain. But then again, Flanders is an over-bearing,
naive, ever-preaching person.10 This is not to say that Homer's treatment of him is justified,
but it is to say that it is understandable. With these exceptions in mind, Homer is generally
not an evil person and he does not treat people with malice. This is another reason why,
though he falls short of having an ethical character, Homer does not provoke negative
reactions in us.
We can, then, make a qualified judgment to the effect that Homer is not a vicious
person in the sense of being ruled by vice. I say "qualified" because there is one exception
to this judgment: when it comes to bodily appetites for food and drink, Homer is vicious.
He does not take pleasure in eating and drinking moderately, and this rules out virtue in this
domain. He rarely, if ever, has the belief to the effect that he should refrain from excessive
eating and drinking, and this rules out continence and incontinence. In addition, he does not
seem to think there's anything wrong (other than occasional immediate health
considerations) with indulging in food and drink, even in inappropriate venues; thus he
once said to Marge, "If God didn't want us to eat in church, He would've made gluttony a
sin" ("King of the Hill"). These considerations should allow us to safely conclude that
Homer exhibits vice in the domain of bodily appetites for food and drink.
Given the abundance of evidence and examples, we can arrive at the following
judgment: Homer is not a virtuous person. A number of factors allow us to reach this
conclusion, but perhaps the most salient one is that Homer does not have the stability of
character that marks the virtuous person. One simply cannot count on him to do the right
thing, not even with respect to actions towards his family members. Furthermore, the
judgment that Homer is not virtuous is, unlike the one that he is not vicious, not qualified.
For even though Homer sometimes acts correctly, his reasons for doing so are usually
skewed, or at best ambiguous (his acts of courage are a prime example of this). And, as far
as his family is concerned, even when Homer does what we think a good father or husband
would do, there are simply too many examples which illustrate otherwise. Homer simply
lacks the kind of stable character that is necessary for being virtuous.
We must also remember that in many of the cases in which Homer does do the right
thing, especially as far as his family is concerned, he has to struggle against his desires to
not do otherwise. Both times when he bought Lisa her saxophones, he had to struggle
against his desire to buy an air-conditioner ("Lisa's Sax"). Sometimes, despite his
knowledge of what ought to be done, he chooses to do the wrong thing, thus exhibiting
what the Greeks called akrasia, or "weakness of will." For example, in "The War of the
Simpsons," he chooses to go fishing during his retreat at Catfish Lake even though he knew
that his attention should be focused on Marge and on their marriage.
Homer is not a virtuous person. He exhibits vice when it comes to appetites for food
and drink, and as for the other spheres of life, he shuttles back and forth between
continence and incontinence. This, of course, does not show that Aristotle's division of
character types was too tidy or unrealistic or simplistic, because Aristotle's division was a
logical one, not a description of what types of people there actually are. Homer instantiates
different character types, depending on the area of life with respect to which the question is
raised.
Conclusion:
The Importance of Being Homer
At the beginning of this essay, I claimed that there is something ethically admirable
about Homer Simpson. But this claim poses a problem: How can it be true if Homer is not
virtuous? For if the paradigm of an ethically admirable character is being virtuous, and if
Homer falls short of this standard, then the claim that he is ethically admirable seems
patently false. Furthermore, even if we do not think that Homer is malicious, and even if
we think that his character formation was -- at least mostly -- beyond his control, these
factors are not enough to make him ethically admirable. For this last claim to be at least
plausible, something else must be at work. And this something else cannot be the fact that
Homer sometimes does the right thing, because the claim is about him, his character, and
not about a subset of his actions.
In "Scenes from the Class Struggle in Springfield," Marge realizes her error in
trying to pressure her family to conform to an elitist social circle she has recently joined. In
accepting her family members for who they are, she enumerates the qualities that she likes
about them (she couldn't, though, find one for Bart). The quality she mentions of Homer is
his "in-your-face humanity," and this quality, if understood broadly enough, is not only
true of him, but also goes a long way in explaining in what ways he is ethically admirable.
This quality does not just encompass those traits that lead Homer to do things in
public that many of us would, to different degrees, shy away from doing, such as belching,
releasing flatulence, scratching our behinds, and eating and drinking to the point of losing
our senses. If it were just that, Homer would simply be a boor. Rather, it covers Homer's
love and enjoyment of life, in its most basic elements, while at the same time not giving
much, if any, attention to what people think. Homer generally does not care about etiquette
or about what people think of him. He is set on enjoying life -- or his version of it -- to the
fullest. This zest for life is not calculated on his part, nor is he even necessarily conscious
of it. But it manifests itself in his actions, in his attitudes, in his lack of malice, and in his
childlike (maybe even childish) behavior, and, indeed, it can be found in most of the
examples cited in this essay. When we add to this the fact that Homer is a struggling,
"upper-lower-middle-class" citizen, working in a factory under the tyranny of a ruthless
capitalist, and when we also add the fact that Homer lives in Springfield, a town which
should make one stop and think before one decides that life is worth being loved, we arrive
at a person who has much to be admired.
This quality that explains Homer's admirability -- let's call it "love of life,"
following Ned Flanders's labeling of it as Homer's "intoxicating lust for life" ("Viva Ned
Flanders") -- is not a virtue as such. This is so not because it does not appear on Aristotle's
list, but because, as we well know, such a quality, if unharnessed, can be dangerous both to
others and to its possessor (as, I think, it is in Homer's case). Much like ambition, it is a
positive quality, and an admirable one at that. It is also an ethical quality. It enhances, if
properly possessed, the life of the person who has it by making his life more pleasurable,
and it makes the rest of us want to be in this person's company, not just so that some of it
may rub off on us, but also because it is simply pleasurable to be around such people. If
those qualities which contribute to a person's happiness and overall flourishing are
plausibly construed as ethical, then a quality such as love of life would fit this bill, if used
and regulated by practical reason. In Homer's case, the quality does not come harnessed by
reason and it does come with other traits that make its possession dangerous. But we
nevertheless do admire Homer for having it, and for having it against all of his odds.11
In addition, this quality, and especially because it comes unharnessed in Homer,
leads him to be bluntly honest about his desires and his wants -- even to a fault. Where
others scheme and connive while also pretending to be socially conformist, Homer is open,
honest, and even blunt about who he is, what he wants, and what he thinks of others. He
knows his limitations, he loves his family -- in his own morally attenuated ways -- and he is
an in-your-face type of person.
However, I do not wish to be misunderstood. I am not arguing that Homer is, as
such, an admirable person, but only that he has an admirable trait. It is tempting to slide
from the latter claim to the former one, because, first, while Homer is not virtuous, he is
also neither malicious nor, except for bodily appetites, vicious; second, the fact that Homer
loves life despite his financially and economically modest means, and despite his growing
up and living in a town such as Springfield (which is not conducive to a good life), might
make us think that he is admirable for retaining his love of life in the face of these difficult
situations. But the temptation must be resisted, and this is so for three reasons.
First, and as I already emphasized, the quality of love of life in Homer's case is
unregulated by reason, and this could make having it morally dangerous. Second, enjoying
life is not the same as living a flourishing one. A person could indeed enjoy life to the
fullest yet not lead a flourishing life. Think of someone who is fully happy spending his life
counting blades of grass or collecting bottle-caps, yet who is capable of pursuing worthier
goals. No matter how happy that person is, no matter how much he is enjoying his life, we
surely do not want to say of his life that it is well-lived. Given the examples mentioned in
the third section above, Homer is clearly capable of living a better life than the one he leads.
Third, there is a logical reason: having an admirable trait does not, as such, entail that its
possessor is admirable. Villains often have the trait of overcoming fear in the face of risk,
and while this trait is admirable, we do not usually think of villains as admirable. Indeed,
that is why we sometimes say of a ruthless person, "Well, at least he's being consistent,"
thus recognizing consistency as an admirable trait while also recognizing that it is not
sufficient to make its possessor an admirable person.
Furthermore, a moment's reflection should tell us that Homer is, indeed, not an
admirable person as such. He is not virtuous, and this fact alone is enough to undermine
any serious attempt to ascribe admirability to him as an overall judgment. However,
sometimes non-virtuous people are nevertheless called admirable if they compensate for
their lack of virtue, by, for example, giving the world artistic masterpieces. The traditional
example given in this regard is of the artist Gauguin, who left his family to fend for itself
while he pursued making art in Tahiti. Such extenuating factors, however, do not apply to
Homer: What lasting contribution has he given the world by way of compensating for his
lack of virtue so as to deserve the description "admirable"?
But Homer's love of life is nevertheless a highly admirable trait, and this conclusion
is not trivial, for many people are tempted to see in Homer nothing but buffoonery and
immorality. Moreover, Homer's love of life stands out as an important quality especially in
our age, an age in which political correctness, over-politeness, lack of willingness to judge
others, inflated obsession with physical health, and pessimism about what is good and
enjoyable about life reign more or less supreme. In this age, Homer Simpson -- whose
bumper sticker says "Single 'n' Sassy" -- shines as someone who flouts these "truths." He is
not politically correct, he is more than happy to judge others, and he certainly does not
seem to be obsessed with his health. These qualities might not make Homer an admirable
person, but they do make him admirable in some ways, and, more importantly, make us
crave him and the Homer Simpsons of this world.12
1 My remarks on Aristotle are primarily derived from his Nichomachean Ethics, Books I, II, V, and
VIII, translated by Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985) and his Politics (translated by B. Jowett, in
Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, volume 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1984). Specific references are in the body of the paper. Needless to say, much of what I say on Aristotle is
subject to debate.
2 One must resist the temptation to think that the vicious person also has practical wisdom. The
vicious person, according to Aristotle, does not have phronesis; rather, he has cleverness. To Aristotle,
practical reason has normative force and does not just play a means-end role. Phronesis allows us to know
what things are important and ethical in life. That is why Aristotle says repeatedly that what is right is what
appears to be so to the virtuous agent (see for example Ethics 1176a16-19).
3 See the Episode Guide at the end of this book for an ordered list of the episodes. Many of the
quotations and all of the episode titles in my paper are from The Simpsons: A Complete Guide to Our
Favorite Family, edited by Ray Richmond (New York: Harper Collins, 1997), and The Simpsons Forever,
edited by Scott M. Gimple (New York: Harper Collins, 1999).
4 Marge might be thought to fit this description, given Homer's conclusion that she is his soul mate
("The Mysterious Voyage of Homer"), but most other episodes of the show actually indicate how much the
two diverge in terms of their goals, interests, and activities.
5 See Chapter 3 of this volume.
6 I say "knowingly" because in "Viva Ned Flanders" Homer wakes up in a hotel in Las Vegas to
discover that he had, during the drunkenness of the past evening, married a cocktail waitress, and it is left
unclear whether he actually had sex with her.
7 For an Aristotelian view of Marge's character, see Chapter 4 of this volume.
8 For the vices of Springfield, see Chapter 12 of this volume.
9 And he'll never be happy either. See Chapter 13 of this volume.
10 On Flanders's character, see Chapter 14 of this volume.
11 The odds here include being of moderate intellectual and financial means and of living among the
inhabitants of Springfield. We should keep in mind also that we might admire Homer's character for other
reasons. It is, most obviously, quite humorous. We might also admire him because we see an exaggerated
sense of who we -- or some of us -- are in him.
12 I wish to thank the following: the editors of this volume for very helpful comments, especially Bill
Irwin for also giving me constant support and encouragement; Steve Jones for engaging me in excellent
conversations about Homer Simpson and for tolerating (and sometimes enjoying) my constant use of
Homeric quotes in my regular speech; my brilliant students at the School of the Art Institute of Chicago for
discussing the topic of this paper with me on numerous occasions (involving much intemperate indulgence in
food and drink), for using examples from The Simpsons show in their philosophy papers, and for their
infectious joy at simply knowing that I was writing this paper: Annika Connor, Ted Dumitrescu, Christopher
Koch, Cory Poole, Sara Puzey, Austin Stewart, and Dahlia Tulett (this paper is dedicated to them).
2
Lisa and American Anti-intellectualism
AEON J. SKOBLE
American society has generally had a love-hate relationship with the notion of the
intellectual. On the one hand, there is a sense of respect for the professor or the scientist,
but at the same time there is great resentment of the "ivory tower" or the "bookish"; a
defensiveness about intelligent or learned people. The republican ideals of the Founders
presuppose an enlightened citizenry, yet today, the introduction of even remotely
sophisticated analysis of political topics is decried as "elitism." Everyone respects a
historian, yet a historian's opinion may be disregarded on the grounds that it is "no more
valid" than that of the "working man." Populist commentators and politicians frequently
exploit this resentment of expertise while relying on it as it suits them, for example when a
candidate attacks his opponent for being an "Ivy League elitist" while in fact being a
product of (or relying on advisers from) a similar educational background.
Similarly, a hospital may consult a bioethicist, or it may reject the counsel of
bioethicists, on the grounds that they are too abstract and unconnected to the realities of
medicine. Indeed, it seems as though most people like being able to support their positions
by citing experts, but then invoke populist sentiment when the experts don't support their
view. For instance, I may lend support to my argument by citing an expert who agrees with
me, but if an expert disagrees, I may respond "what does he know?" or "I'm entitled to my
opinion too." Oddly, we see anti-intellectualism even among intellectuals. For example, at
many universities today, both among the student body and the faculty, the role of the
classics, and humanities generally, has been greatly diminished. The trend has clearly been
to develop pre-professional programs and emphasize "relevance"; whereas traditional
humanities classes are regarded as a luxury or an enhancement, but not truly necessary
features of a college education. At best they are seen as vehicles for developing
"transferable skills" such as composition or critical thinking.
There seem to be periodic pendulum swings: in the 1950s and early 1960s, there
was tremendous respect for scientists, as the nation found itself competing against the
Soviets in such areas as space exploration. Today, it seems the pendulum has reversed
swing, as the current Zeitgeist holds all opinions to be equally valid. But at the same time,
people still seem interested in what alleged experts have to say. A cursory review of TV
talk shows or newspaper letters-to-the-editor reveals this ambivalence. The talk show will
book an expert because, presumably, people will be interested in that person's analysis or
opinion. But the panelists or audience members who disagree with the expert will argue
that their opinions, their perspectives, are just as worthwhile. A newspaper will run an
opinion column by a specialist, whose analysis on a situation may be better informed than
the average person's, but the letters from people who disagree will often be based on the
underlying (if unstated) premise that "No one really knows anything" or "It's all a matter of
opinion, and mine counts too." This last rationale is particularly insidious: in fact, if it were
true that everything were merely a matter of opinion, then it actually would follow that
mine is as relevant as the expert's; indeed there would be no such thing as expertise.
So, it is fair to say that American society is conflicted about intellectuals. Respect
for them seems virtually to go hand in hand with resentment. This is a puzzling social
problem, and also one of great importance, for we seem to be on the verge of a new "dark
ages," where not only the notion of expertise, but all standards of rationality are being
challenged. This clearly has significant social consequences. As a vehicle for exploring
this issue, it may be surprising to choose a TV show which, at first glance, seems devoted
to the idea that dumber is better; but actually, of the many things that The Simpsons
skillfully illustrates about society, the American ambivalence about expertise and
rationality is clearly one of them.1
On The Simpsons, Homer is a classic example of an anti-intellectual dolt, as are
most of his acquaintances, and his son. But his daughter, Lisa, is not only pro-intellectual,
she is smart beyond her years. She is extremely intelligent and sophisticated, and is often
seen out-thinking those around her. Naturally, for this she is mocked by the other children
at school and generally ignored by the adults. On the other hand, her favorite TV show is
the same one as her brother's: a mindlessly violent cartoon. Her treatment on the show, I
argue, captures the love-hate relationship American society has with intellectuals.2 Before
turning to the ways in which it does this, let's have a closer look at the problem.
Fallacious Authority and Real Expertise
It is a staple of introductory logic courses that it is a fallacy to "appeal to authority,"
yet people typically make more out of this than is appropriate. Strictly in terms of logic, it's
always a mistake to argue that a proposition is true because so-and-so says it is, but appeals
to authority are more commonly used to show that we have good reason to believe the
proposition, as opposed to being proof of its truth. Like all fallacies involving relevance,
the problem with most appeals to authority is that they are invoking the authority in an
irrelevant way. For example, in matters which really are subjective, such as which pizza or
soft drink I should buy, invoking anyone else is irrelevant, since I may not have the same
tastes.3 In other cases, the error is in assuming that because a person is an authority about
one thing, that person's expertise should carry the day in all areas. We see this in celebrity
endorsements for products unrelated to that person's field. For example, Troy McClure
endorsing Duff Beer would not constitute a valid appeal to authority, since being an actor
doesn't make one an expert on beer. (And experience is not the same as expertise: Barney is
not an expert on beer either.) In other cases, the appeal is fallacious on the grounds that
some matters cannot be settled by appeal to experts, not because they are subjective, but
because they are unknowable, for instance the future of scientific progress. The classic
example here is Einstein's claim in 1932 that "there is not the slightest indication that
[nuclear] energy will ever be obtainable."4
But after building up all this skepticism about appeals to authority, it's worth
remembering that some people actually do know more about some things than other people,
and in many cases, the fact that an authority on a subject tells us something really is a good
reason to believe it. For example, since I have no first-hand knowledge of the Battle of
Marathon, I am going to have to rely on what other people tell me, and a classical historian
is precisely the sort of person I should go to, whereas a physician probably is not.5
Often what people resent is the application of wisdom, especially to moral or social
ideals. People may argue that yes, there is such a thing as being an expert on the
Greco-Persian Wars, but that doesn't mean that person can inform our discussion about
world politics today.6 You may be an expert on Aristotle's moral theory, but that doesn't
mean you can tell me how I should live. This sort of resistance to expertise stems partly
from the nature of a democratic regime, and the problem is not new, but was identified by
philosophers as early as Plato. Since, in a democracy, all voices get heard, this can lead
people to conclude that all voices have equal value. Democracies tend to justify themselves
by contrast to the aristocracies or oligarchies they replace or resist. In those elitist societies,
some presume to know more, or actually to be better people; whereas we democrats know
better: all are equal. But of course, political equality doesn't imply that no one can possess
knowledge that others lack, and indeed few people think this about most skills, for example
plumbing or auto repair. No one, though (they say), can know more than anyone else about
how to live, how to be just. Hence a kind of relativism develops: from the rejection of
ruling elites, who in fact may not have had any better idea than anyone else about justice, to
a rejection of the notion of objective standards of right and wrong entirely. What is right is
what I feel is right, what is right-for-me. Today, there is a trend even in the academy to
dispute notions of objectivity and expertise. There are said to be no true histories, only
different interpretations of history.7 There are no correct interpretations of literary works,
only different interpretations.8 Even physical science is said to be value-laden and
non-objective.9
So we have all these factors contributing to a climate in which the notion of
expertise is eroded, yet at the same time we see countervailing trends. If there's no such
thing as expertise, and all opinions are equally valid, why are the talk shows and bestseller
lists populated by experts on love and angels? Why watch those shows or read books in the
first place? Why send the kids to school? Clearly, people do still put some stock in the
notion of expertise, and in many cases, yearn for its guidance. People actually seem to have
some tendencies towards wanting to be told what to do. Some critics of religion ascribe its
influence to this psychological need, but we need look no further than the political realm to
see evidence of it. People look to political figures for their "leadership": we're having a
problem with unemployment -- doesn't anyone know how to do something about that? This
person would make a better president than that one because he knows how to reduce crime,
end poverty, make our children better, and so on. But the ambivalence shows itself very
clearly in these contexts. If candidate Smith bases his appeal on his expertise and ability to
"get the job done," candidate Jones will likely charge Smith with being an elite, a
"pointy-head." We also see the paradoxical situation wherein celebrities' pronouncements
on political matters taken seriously, as if being a talented musician or actor gave greater
weight to one's political views, while at the same time the notion of being an expert on
government is derided. With whose views are most Americans more familiar, Alec
Baldwin and Charlton Heston, or John Rawls and Robert Nozick?
In addition to political expertise, people also yearn for, and seem least ambivalent
about, technological expertise. Most people are quick to acknowledge their own
incompetence at plumbing, auto repair, and surgery, and happily turn those tasks over to
the experts. In the case of the surgeon, we do see another manifestation of the ambivalence
I have in mind, namely when people defend alternative medicine or spiritual healing --
what do doctors know? This is a trickle-down from the currently-fashionable trend in
academia which maintains that all science is value-laden and non-objective. But we don't
have any advocates of "alternative plumbing" or "spiritual auto repair," so these people's
expertise is more generally accepted; and do-it-yourselfers are not a counter-example,
since that's more a matter of regarding oneself as that sort of craftsman, rather than denying
that anyone else is. Also, since plumbers and mechanics less frequently position
themselves as experts in fields beyond their own, as surgeons might position themselves as
ethicists, they are less susceptible to being regarded skeptically.10
Do We Admire or Laugh at Lisa?
American anti-intellectualism, then, is pervasive but not all-encompassing. As it
does with many other aspects of modern society, The Simpsons often uses this theme as
fodder for its satire. In the Simpson family, only Lisa could really be described as an
intellectual. But her portrayal as such is not unequivocally flattering. In contrast to her
relentlessly ignorant father, she is often shown having the right answer to a problem or a
more perceptive analysis of a situation, for example when she exposes political
corruption11 or when she gives up her dream of owning a pony so that Homer won't have to
work three jobs.12 When Lisa discovers the truth behind the myth of Jebediah Springfield,
many people are unconvinced, but Homer says, "you're always right about this sort of
thing."13 In "Homer's Triple Bypass," Lisa actually talks Dr. Nick through a heart operation
and saves her father's life. But other times, her intellectualism is itself used as the butt of
the joke, as if she were "too" smart, or merely preachy. For instance, her principled
vegetarianism is revealed as dogmatic and inconsistent,14 and she uses Bart in a science
experiment without his knowledge,15 evoking examples of the worst sort of arrogance,
such as the infamous Tuskegee study.16 She agitates to join the football team, but it turns
out she is more interested in making a point than in playing.17 So although her wisdom is
sometimes presented as valuable, other times it is presented as a case of being
sanctimonious or condescending.
One common populist criticism of the intellectual is that "you're no better than the
rest of us." The point of this attack seems to be that if I can show that the alleged sage is
"really" a regular person, then maybe I don't have to be as impressed with his opinion. Thus
the expression "Hey, he puts his pants on one leg at a time just like the rest of us." The
implication of this non-sequitur is clearly "he is just a regular person like you and me, so
why should we be awed by his alleged expertise?" In Lisa's case, we are shown that she has
many of the same foibles as many kids: she joins her non-intellectual brother in revelry as
they watch the mindlessly violent Itchy and Scratchy cartoon, she worships the teen idol
Corey, she plays with Springfield's analogue to the Barbie Doll, Malibu Stacy. So we are
given ample opportunity to see Lisa as "no better" in many respects, thus giving us another
window for not taking her smarts seriously. Of course, it is true that she is a young girl, and
one might argue that this is merely typical young girl behavior, but since in so many other
cases she is presented not simply as a prodigy but as preternaturally wise, the fondness for
Itchy and Scratchy and Corey seem to be highlighted, taking on greater significance. Lisa
is portrayed as the avatar of logic and wisdom, but then she also worships Corey, so she's
"no better." In "Lisa the Skeptic," Lisa is the sole voice of reason when the town becomes
convinced that "the skeleton of an angel" has been found (it's a hoax), but when it seems to
speak, Lisa is as afraid as everyone else.
Lisa's relationship with the Malibu Stacy doll actually takes center stage in one
episode,18 and even this highlights an ambivalence in society about rationalism. It
gradually occurs to Lisa that the Malibu Stacy doll does not offer a positive role model for
young girls, and she presses for (and actually contributes to) the development of a different
doll which encourages girls to achieve and learn. But the makers of Malibu Stacy counter
with a new version of their doll, which triumphs on the toy market. The fact that the "less
intellectual" doll is vastly preferred over Lisa's doll, even though all of Lisa's objections are
reasonable, demonstrates the ways in which reasonable ideas can be made to take a back
seat to "having fun" and "going with the flow." This debate is often played out in the real
world, of course: Barbie is the subject of perennial criticism along the lines of Lisa's
critique of Malibu Stacy, yet remains immensely popular, and in general, we often see
intellectual critiques of toys dismissed as "out of touch" or elitist.19
Philosopher Kings? D'Oh!
A more specific instance of the way The Simpsons reflects American ambivalence
towards the intellectual is found in the episode "They Saved Lisa's Brain."20 In this episode,
Lisa joins the local chapter of Mensa, which already includes Professor Frink, Dr. Hibbert,
and the Comic Book Guy. Together they end up in charge of Springfield. Lisa rhapsodizes
about the rule of the intellectuals, a true rationalist Utopia, but too many of their programs
alienate the regular citizens of the town (including, of course, Homer, who leads the charge
of the idiot brigade). It would be easy enough to see this sequence of events as a satire on
the way the average person is too stupid to recognize the rule of the wise, but more than
that is being satirized here. Also under attack is the very notion of rule of the wise -- the
Mensans have some legitimately good ideas (more rational traffic patterns), but also some
ridiculous ones (censorship, mating rituals inspired by Star Trek), and they squabble
amongst themselves. The Mensans offer something of value, especially in contrast to the
corrupt regime of Mayor Quimby or the reign of idiocy that Homer represents, and Lisa's
intentions are good, but it is impossible to see this episode as unequivocally
pro-intellectual, since one theme is clearly that Utopian schemes by elites are unstable,
inevitably unpopular, and sometimes foolish. As Paul Cantor argues, "the Utopia episode
embodies the strange mixture of intellectualism and anti-intellectualism characteristic of
The Simpsons. In Lisa's challenge to Springfield, the show calls attention to the cultural
limitations of small-town America, but it also reminds us that intellectual disdain for the
common man can be carried too far and that theory can all too easily lose touch with
common sense."21
It is actually true, however, that Utopian schemes by elites tend to be ill-conceived,
or are power-grabbing schemes masquerading as the common good. But is the only
alternative Homer's mob or Quimby's oligarchy? The framers of the United States
Constitution hoped to combine democratic principles (a Congress) with some of the
benefits of an undemocratic elite rule (a Senate, a Supreme Court, a Bill of Rights). This
has had mixed results, but in contrast to other alternatives seems to have fared well. Is all of
our society's ambivalence about intellectuals due to this constitutional tension? Surely not.
That is part of it, but, more likely than not, this ambivalence is a manifestation of deeper
psychological conflicts. We want to have authoritative guidance, but we also want
autonomy. We don't like feeling stupid, yet when we are honest we realize we need to learn
some things. We respect the accomplishments of others, but sometimes feel threatened and
resentful. We have a respect for authorities when it suits us, and embrace relativism in
other cases. The "we" here is, of course, a generalization: some people manifest this
conflict less than others (or in a few cases not at all), but it seems an apt description of a
general social outlook. Unsurprisingly, The Simpsons, our most profoundly satirical TV
show, both illustrates and instantiates it.
The ambivalence in American society towards the intellectual, if it is indeed a
deep-rooted psychological phenomenon, is not likely to go away any time soon. But no one
is better off for encouraging or promoting anti-intellectualism. Those who wish to save the
republic from the tyranny of Professor Frink and The Comic Book Guy need to find ways
to argue against it that do not entail a wholesale attack on the ideal of intellectual
development. Those who champion the common man ought not do so in ways that belittle
the achievements of the learned. That approach is tantamount to defending Homer's right to
live as a stupid person by criticizing Lisa for being smart.22 That's not a sound idea for the
development of the nation or of any individual.23
1 Is it anti-intellectual for a Ph.D. in philosophy to write an essay about a TV show? As we argued in
the Introduction, not necessarily: it depends on whether or not the show can illuminate some philosophical
problem, or serve as an accessible example when explaining a point. If we wanted to adopt an
anti-intellectual approach, we could argue that all one needs to know about life can be learned from watching
TV, but that's clearly not what we are saying; indeed, we're trying to use people's interest in the show as a way
to get them to read more philosophy.
2 Intellectuals and experts are not the same thing, of course: many intellectuals are not experts in
anything. But I suspect that the antipathy towards both is similarly rooted, and that the distinction is lost on
those who would be inclined to reject or scorn both.
3 This is not to address the arguments concerning whether or not there can be objective criteria for
judging food, but simply to distinguish between the way in which Smith's preference for chocolate over
vanilla is really different from Jones's preference for murder over counseling.
4 Quoted in Christopher Cerf and Victor Navasky, The Experts Speak (New York: Pantheon Books,
1984), p. 215.
5 Of course, there are the odd cases where the physician in question is, say, as a hobby, also an expert
on the Battle of Marathon, but I am speaking here of the physician qua physician.
6 In case you're wondering, see Peter Green's The Greco-Persian Wars (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1996).
7 See for example, Mary Lefkowitz's book Not Out of Africa. (New York: Basic Books, 1996), in
which she recounts her experiences as a classicist trying to maintain standards of rational inquiry in the
heated area of race-based archeology.
8 For a rare objective account of artistic interpretation, see William Irwin's Intentionalist
Interpetation: A Philosophical Explanation and Defense (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1999). Ironically,
at the same time the notion of truth and expertise is being challenged within the academy -- there are no such
things as experts on morality -- the talk shows and bestseller lists are populated with experts on such things as
relationships, horoscopes, and angels. But these experts are heeded, I think, only to the extent that they
confirm a person's predispositions, and rejected on grounds I have outlined when they do not. To be sure, the
rejection of knowledge claims in the realm of values is different from the rejection of knowledge claims in
physical matters, but what is interesting is that we do see both, and at the same time we also see bogus claims
of expertise on a host of inappropriate matters.
9 See, for example, Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont, Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern
Intellectuals' Abuse of Science (New York: Picador, 1998). The springboard for this book was Sokal's
now-famous hoax, in which he submitted a bogus essay based on this theme, which was readily accepted by
scientifically challenged journal editors as a fine work. That essay was "Transgressing the Boundaries:
Toward a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity," originally published in Social Text 46-47,
(1996), pp. 217-252.
10 This also highlights ways in which popular attitudes towards "authorities" and "intellectuals" are
not exactly the same. People are less resistant to an authority or expert when the area seems not to be an
intellectual one, as for example we all recognize the plumber's expertise; but of course being an expert in
anything requires a degree of intellectualism, so the distinction is a fallacious one, and is more a reflection of
people's attitudes than a statement about the intellectual level of expert craftsmen. Expert craftsmen
obviously do possess wisdom, but are often seen as less threatening to those who don't possess the wisdom.
This might be due to the fact that when we speak of "intellectuals" or "smart people," we are describing a
general characteristic which sets the person apart, whereas when we speak of an "expert," we are only
describing an attribute which we may regard as isolated, and thus feel less threatened. Lisa is an intellectual
(valuing the pursuit of wisdom) and very smart, while not specifically an "expert" on anything.
11 "Mr. Lisa Goes to Washington."
12 "Lisa's Pony."
13 "Lisa the Iconoclast."
14 "Lisa the Vegetarian."
15 "Duffless."
16 This was a case in which the doctors experimented without consent, and with little regard for the
well-being of the "participants," who were infected with syphilis.
17 "Bart Star."
18 "Lisa vs. Malibu Stacy."
19 GI Joe, for example, is criticized for promoting militarism and violence, as do all "gun" toys, yet
parents overwhelmingly reject the calls of some intellectuals that kids should be guided towards different
play.
20 For further discussion of this episode, see Chapter 11 of this volume.
21 Ibid., p. 178
22 Some argue that, indeed, Homer does not have the right to live as a stupid person. There may be
something to this, but it's neither here nor there with respect to the narrower argument I am making here.
23 I am grateful to Mark Conard and William Irwin for helping me clarify several of my points and
reminding me of several useful examples.
3
Why Maggie Matters:
Sounds of Silence, East and West
ERIC BRONSON
Nobody even considered Maggie Simpson. And why should they? The signs
pointed to someone like Smithers, the brown-nosing admirer, scorned more times than any
other man could endure. Or more likely was Homer Simpson, the oafish safety inspector
who once threw his boss out of the office window in a fit of rage. It could have been anyone,
really.
When the demonic Mr. Burns hatched his most diabolical scheme, when the evil
old founder of the nuclear power plant finally figured out how to block the sun from
shining on the innocent town of Springfield, everybody had plausible motives for shooting
him. That's why when word got around that Mr. Burns was lying in a hospital in critical
condition, all of Springfield wanted to know who to blame (or congratulate, as the case
might be). The shifty-eyed adults all had dubious alibis and the school children were quick
to point fingers at each other. Finally Mr. Burns himself improved enough to set the matter
straight. It was little Maggie Simpson who pulled the trigger at point blank range, nearly
killing the old man while he "wallowed in his own crapulence" ("Who Shot Mr. Burns?
Part Two").
Maggie Simpson shot Mr. Burns. The infant, still too young to walk, protected her
lollipop from falling into groping, miserly hands. Was it self-defense? An accident perhaps?
After all, the gun did belong to Mr. Burns and only ended up in Maggie's hands due to his
own carelessness. Still, the two-part episode ends on an interrogative note. Just what were
the intentions of this young and seemingly innocent girl? Could she knowingly commit
such a crime? The answers, or lack thereof, are less than comforting. The camera zooms in
on Maggie's mouth, her pacifier blocking any articulation or explanation as the credits
begin to roll. The child tries to speak but cannot. It seems as though we'll never know why
Maggie shot the most powerful man in Springfield. We'll never get the answers we want,
unless of course, her stunted speech is actually all the answer we need.
Is Maggie an Idiot?
The Western world has long had a special fascination with the spoken word. The
terrific success of talk shows like Oprah and The Jerry Springer Show are just the latest,
though not the greatest, phenomena to attest to just how much we love to hear people speak
about themselves. The more revealing the speech, the more likely we are to hoot our
approval. Spoken words carry a certain power that can quickly move us to action. The
nineteenth century English poet Emily Dickinson writes:
A word is dead
When it is said,
Some say.
I say it just
Begins to live
That day.1
Words can take on new meanings and open up whole new lines of thoughts once
they are spoken and set free in the public domain.
Why do we take words so seriously? Beginning with the Greek philosopher
Socrates, Western philosophy has tended to emphasize discussion and argument as the
means for attaining higher truths. For Socrates, it was never enough to refute the unsound,
unsupported arguments of his day. Words had to be carefully chosen and properly spoken
for the light of reason to shine most forcefully. Socrates frequently likens philosophy to
music in its ability to transform the souls of its listeners. In Plato's Symposium, Socrates's
eloquent defense of erotic love has just ended when Alcibiades, the heralded warrior of
Ancient Greece, crashes the party and says, "[Y]ou're a flute-player, aren't you? In fact,
you're a more amazing one than Marsayas. . .2 The only way you differ from him is that,
while you do the same thing he does, you do it using plain words without instruments."3
Words are like music. Well-reasoned thoughts, conveyed with well-chosen words, can
touch us as deeply as a moving symphony or a driving drum beat.
Maggie Simpson doesn't possess language and doesn't speak. In the twentieth
century, philosophers concerned with humanity's place in the universe have returned to the
relationship between words and thoughts. How do we think, if not in words? Ludwig
Wittgenstein tells us, "The limits of my language mean the limits of my world" (Tractatus
5.6). For those of us lucky enough to speak freely, our words are inexorably linked to our
thoughts. What should I eat for breakfast? Should I go to class today? Why is he acting like
such a jerk? Questions like these are continuously asked, discussed, and pondered.
Through such internal debate we arrive at conclusions. I will skip breakfast and go to class.
Because he is being a jerk, I'm not going to waste my time. Finally, we're ready to act on
our conclusions. Our entire thought process seems to be intimately related to a
never-ending stream of words.
Now what would happen if the words were taken away? What tools would we have
to make even the smallest decisions? Which comes first, the language or the thoughts? In
"Brother, Can You Spare Two Dimes?" Homer's brother, played by Danny DeVito, invents
a baby-translating device. The idea is that Maggie is capable of everyday thoughts even
though she doesn't have the ability to express these thoughts in language. Of course, her
ideas are hardly profound (one of her thoughts is that she wants to eat dog food) but the
translating machine makes Homer's brother wealthy again. And well it should. Such a
machine would go a long way in solving many philosophical questions about the origins of
language and its relation to the human thought process.
Words is the title of the twentieth-century French existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre's
autobiography. According to Sartre, a person's life is characterized by his or her
interactions with other people and such interactions are established largely through words.
Therefore, to understand Sartre or any other human being, one has to examine the words. In
The Family Idiot, a five-volume, 3,000-plus page investigation into the life and times of
French novelist Gustave Flaubert, Sartre shows us what happens when words are taken
away. The biography was Sartre's last major philosophical work, and one that was never
finished despite the incredible volume of material written. In this final work, Sartre
practices his existential psychology by examining the author's life's project in light of his
childhood upbringing. Flaubert's upbringing, according to Sartre, was characterized by
speechlessness and idiocy. Flaubert's childhood development was marked by the late
acquisition of speech. Moreover, he had difficulty surmounting his mental infancy because
of a speech impediment. Of Flaubert, Sartre writes, "He would sit for hours, a finger in his
mouth, looking almost stupid; this calm child who reacts badly when spoken to, feels less
than others the need to speak -- words, as we say, do not come to him, nor the desire to use
them."4 Speech, Sartre argues, is how human beings first become integrated into human
society. Flaubert, already from age six, was set adrift on a sea of isolation due to his speech
deficiency and could not articulate his childish emotions and fears. Sartre's argument is not
that Flaubert was an idiot, we know he went on to write such enduring classics as Madame
Bovary, but that his life in writing can be seen as a desperate attempt to overcome his
childhood insufficiencies.
According to Sartre, self-worth is partially instilled in us by the words of others.
Those who are closest to us naturally have a greater say. Like most children, Flaubert's first
connection to the world was through his parents. It was on the surface a loving relationship,
but Sartre observes that a child needs more. A growing child needs to know that his
existence is justified and important. His projects, however small, must be nurtured and
criticized, examined and approved through the loving use of language. In this way, the
child has guardrails to hold on to, knowing that he is not alone in the universe. "This is not
a conjecture," Sartre writes. "A child must have a mandate to live, the parents are the
authorities who issue the mandate."5 One way a parent can communicate this mandate is by
constant communication, reinforced by loving words and caring actions. Flaubert seems to
have missed out on such parental valorization. Without this attention, the future novelist
frustrated easily, turned within, and stayed quiet far longer than the happier children his
age.
Though the fictional Springfield is a far cry from the French countryside (as Bart
discovered on his miserable study abroad in "The Crepes of Wrath"), Maggie's upbringing
does share some similarity with that of Flaubert. Sartre tells us how Flaubert's mother cared
for her child's body but never took the time to attend to his innermost needs. Mme. Flaubert
is portrayed as "an excellent mother but not a delightful one; punctual, assiduous, adept.
Nothing more."6 How is Maggie loved by her mother? The answer is not so clear. It does
seem that Marge Simpson has a deep love for her youngest daughter, but, like Mme.
Flaubert, her love is practical, involving little more than feeding, cleaning, dressing, and
tucking in to bed. Sometimes it seems as if mother Marge treats her vacuum cleaner with
the same care that she lavishes on her children. In the show's weekly opening montage,
Maggie is taken out of the grocery cart by the check-out clerk and priced along with all the
other items. Marge is relieved to discover that her youngest child, no longer missing, is
securely packed into one of her many shopping bags. It is as if getting the groceries and
children safely home will adequately fulfill her duty as a mother.
Of course, if Maggie grows up with a low self-esteem Marge will not be entirely to
blame. Homer is certainly not the paradigm of the nurturing dad; there's only so much
intimacy you can expect from someone who sings "I'd rather drink a beer, than win Father
of the Year" ("Simpsoncalifragilisticexpiala-D'oh-cious"). True, it is Homer who
convinces Mr. Burns to accept his long lost son Larry (given voice by Rodney Dangerfield
in "Burns, Baby Burns"). Homer insists that "although kids can be obnoxious and stinky
the one thing they can always count on is a father's love." It's also true that Homer finally
comes to terms with Maggie's existence, and lines his office with her baby pictures ("And
Maggie Makes Three"), but such momentary bursts of emotions hardly fulfill the
requirements for "Sartre's guide to good parenting."
It's revealing that in "Home Sweet Homediddly-Dum-Doodily," in which the
Simpsons lose custody of their children to their upstanding neighbors, the Flanderses, it is
Maggie who begins to flower under the lavish attention.7 Surrounded by constant care and
renewed interest, the silent Maggie suddenly feels like speaking and, to the surprise of
everyone, blurts out "daddily-doodily" in Ned Flanders's car. Earlier in the episode
Maggie's older siblings comment on her positive change after the child welfare department
takes her out of her parents' home.
BART: I've never seen Maggie laugh like that.
LISA: Well, when was the last time Dad gave her so much attention?
BART: When she swallowed a quarter, he stayed with her all day.
In this episode, Sartre's point is acted out. Through familial love and attention, a
person begins to express herself through words. Without this early attention she slips into
silence. Without words she is likely to have a limited concept of her own self-worth. Such
children may or may not be considered inferior, but as Mr. Burns learned the hard way,
they rarely appreciate people messing with their lollipops.
Is Maggie Enlightened?
Maggie doesn't speak, but, unlike Sartre's Flaubert, she does seem to exhibit at least
a rudimentary thought process. She does, after all, help Bart and Lisa overcome the
"babysitting bandit," in "Some Enchanted Evening," and again comes to the rescue when
the monstrous Grounds Keeper Willie seeks vengeance in one of The Simpsons'
nightmarish Halloween specials ("Treehouse of Horror VI"). She even shows flashes of
genius as she casually plays Tchaikovsky's "Dance of the Sugar Plum Fairies" on her toy
xylophone ("A Streetcar Named Marge"). But what, if anything, really goes through her
mind is a mystery to the viewers because she cannot speak to us.
Let's leave the West behind for a moment. In Ancient China, philosophers rarely
shared our enthusiasm for the spoken word. As the great Chinese philosopher Confucius
says, "Hear much, but maintain silence."8 More forcefully, the Chinese Tao te Ching
insists,
Those who know don't talk.
Those who talk don't know.9
Throughout much of the Eastern tradition, words are used merely as signposts for
the mystery of life which is forever shrouded in silence. Unlike much of Western Scripture,
many Eastern texts long ago claimed silence was the foundation on which our world
originated. In the Bhagavad-Gita, for example, the Creator of the world is shrouded in
mystery and mysticism. The Creator cannot be spoken of, nor grasped intellectually.
Rarely someone
sees it,
rarely another
speaks it,
rarely anyone
hears it --
even hearing it,
no one really knows it.10
Western religions also have their own mystical interpretations of the almighty,
though nowhere is silence more rooted in philosophy than in the East.
To be enlightened, then, is to return to our origins, to rid ourselves of worldly
attachments and return to the infinite quiet of the world. In the Hindu religion (and later
developed by Buddhist sects), the Sanskrit word "Nirvana" often implies a "cooling," a
detachment from passions. Words serve only to destroy such inner peace. We become too
attached to our words and easily talk away the grandeur and mystery behind our lives.
According to many Eastern schools of thought, our earthly unhappiness is caused by too
much thinking, too many words. The Bhagavad-Gita reminds us that "focusing his mind
on the self, he [the man of discipline] should think nothing."11 It's not as if we are supposed
to give up thinking altogether (for that we wouldn't need so many volumes of philosophy),
but many Buddhists, in particular, make a distinction between thinking spontaneously and
thinking obsessively over concepts. Words are useful, even necessary for the transmission
of knowledge. Zen Buddhists in particular use words to help transmit knowledge from
teacher to student. But both Hindus and Buddhists alike understand the darker side of
poorly used speech. Words breed more words which can lead to further stress and anxiety.
Eastern enlightenment often involves a mystical connection with the natural world and
such a transformation is rarely concluded with words.
Acting spontaneously without becoming bogged down in the quicksand of words is
a necessary beginning on the road to enlightenment according to many Eastern schools. In
the West, the temptation is great to lead a life of all talk and no action. In "30 Minutes over
Tokyo" Bart has his mind temporarily opened in Japan and Lisa can put together a puzzle
of the Taj Mahal at the age of three ("Lisa's Sax"), but neither can seriously be considered
enlightened. Unlike her siblings, Maggie is too young to be distracted by words, and can
more effectively act spontaneously. However, according to this line of thinking, all babies
would be considered enlightened. We have to be careful to distinguish between
undeveloped thoughts and rigorously developed non-thoughts. As noted Indian historian
Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan points out, "By observing silence a man does not become a sage
if he be foolish or ignorant."12 In Zen Buddhist thought, it takes years and years of
disciplined thinking and meditation to reach the ecstatic state of childlike innocence.
Chief Wiggum assures Springfield residents that no jury will convict Maggie of
shooting Mr. Burns (except in the state of Texas), because she is too young. She is also, in
all likelihood, too young to have properly rid herself from all earthly attachments. However,
the residents of Springfield did learn one important lesson. A child without words is not
necessarily one without the ability to carry out a rather grave action. While Maggie almost
killed Mr. Burns, she has also saved the day on numerous occasions, without the burden of
speech. Sometimes silence is a sign of complex thought and profound intuition (though not
likely in Maggie's case). If we all practiced it more regularly we might just live a little
easier, and we would certainly spend fewer afternoons serving detention, writing
repetitively on the blackboard, or sitting in Principal Skinner's office.
What Can Maggie Teach Us?
Western philosophy has its own proponents of silence. From the early Jewish
mystics to the contemporary philosophy of Wittgenstein, there has arisen an uneasy tension
about when it is best to stay quiet. In The United States, the twentieth century has come to
a close with a multitude of contradictory messages. We were told to "stand up and be
counted" but "silence is golden." "Knowledge is power" but "no news is good news."
"Express yourself" but "talk is cheap." Rarely have we been more unsettled over the
question of when to keep our mouths shut.
A century earlier, ancient Eastern philosophy had already seeped into the fertile
intellectual soil of Western Europe. Important German philosophers such as Schopenhauer
and Nietzsche were students of the Orient and many Eastern allusions can be found in their
work. Following this tradition, in 1930, the German philosopher Martin Heidegger gave
Eastern philosophy a new popularity in the West. While Heidegger is surely placed in the
Western tradition, his emphasis on silence has a distinctively Eastern flavor. Silence,
Heidegger argued, was essential to humans hoping to live an authentic existence whereas
idle talk was a sure sign of inauthentic existence. Heidegger hoped to bridge the East and
West by speaking only about the more serious questions of "Existence" and staying quiet
about all else.
From all ends of the globe, Heidegger was hailed as a great thinker, one who knew
when and when not to speak. By the late 1930s, however, Germany had more pressing
concerns than existential theory. Adolf Hitler had come to power and World War II had
become an inevitable reality. With a few notable exceptions, Heidegger kept quiet, true to
his philosophy, and did not retract his earlier support for National Socialism and the Third
Reich. When the Nazis declared war on their neighboring countries, Heidegger refused to
speak out. And, when his Jewish students and colleagues were publicly forced out of his
university, Heidegger said nothing.13
History will condemn Heidegger's silence and so should we. Since World War II,
we have learned that speaking out can cause misunderstanding and conflict, but not
speaking out can endorse far worse. Nobel Peace Prize winner Elie Wiesel is fond of
saying that the opposite of love is not hate, but silence. So it seems as though we are left no
better off in determining when to favor Eastern silence and when to rely on Western
speech.
In "Lisa's Wedding," Lisa glimpses into her future with the help of a carnival
soothsayer. She is about to be to married to the man of her dreams, and at the wedding,
Maggie, the grown teenager with the beautiful voice, is set to sing. Just as she takes her first
deep breath, however, Lisa calls off the wedding and Maggie symbolically closes her
mouth. Once again, family turmoil has drowned out her voice.
In a world of growing bureaucracy and information overload, we too run the danger
of having our voices drowned out. In the modern world, the great challenge of both the East
and the West is figuring out how to critically respect each other's projects in a way that
encourages all voices to be heard. More than tolerant, we must be attentive. Otherwise,
more people, like Maggie Simpson, will feel left out of society and turn to more destructive
means of communication. And, in the real world, we don't always bounce back up so
quickly.14
1 The Complete Poems of Emily Dickinson, edited by Thomas Johnson (New York: Little Brown,
1961).
2 The teacher of Olympus, a well-known musician of mythical lore.
3 The Symposium, 215c, in The Symposium and the Phaedrus, translated by William S. Cobb
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1993).
4 The Family Idiot (Vol. 1), translated by Carol Cosman (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1981), p. 35.
5 Ibid, p. 133.
6 The Family Idiot, p. 129.
7 For an extended discussion of this episode see Chapter 14 of this volume.
8 The Analects of Confucius, translated by Arthur Waley (New York: Vintage, 989), 2:18.
9 The Tao Te Ching, translated by Stephen Addiss and Stanley Lombardo (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1993), Chapter 56.
10 The Bhagavad-Gita, translated by Barbara Stoler Miller (New York: Bantam, 1986), p. 33.
11 Ibid, p. 66.
12 A Source Book of Indian Philosophy, edited by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Charles A. Moore
(Princeton: Princeton University Press), p. 313.
13 For a balanced view of Heidegger's role in the Nazi Party see Richard Wolin's The Heidegger
Controversy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992).
14 Special thanks to Pasquale Baldino for the benefit of his vast Simpsons knowledge and research
and to Jennifer McMahon for helpful suggestions.
4
Marge's Moral Motivation
GERALD J. ERION and JOSEPH A. ZECCARDI
From the corrupt Mayor "Diamond" Joe Quimby and the incorrigible recidivist
Snake to such faithful figures as Reverend Lovejoy and Ned Flanders, Springfield's moral
extremes are bound only by the number of characters walking its streets. Bart admits that
he doesn't know the difference between right and wrong and bargains with the devil on a
first name basis, while Homer takes on one selfish and impulsive project after another,
even attempting to convince God of the value of skipping church to watch football.
Meanwhile, Flanders consults religious authorities and scriptures to settle every dilemma
he faces, from those concerning morality and ethics to those about fashion and breakfast
cereal.
Amidst such swirling ethical extremes, Marge stands as a remarkably stable
touchstone of morality. To resolve her moral dilemmas, Marge simply allows reason to
guide her conduct to a thoughtful and admirable balance between extremes. She differs
from Flanders in that Flanders always does as his religion commands, regardless of
whether it actually seems right to him to do so. Marge is religious, but her well-developed
conscience typically leads her to do only what any decent and reasonable person would do,
even when this conflicts with the direction she receives from her religious authorities.
These observations suggest that Marge's underlying moral philosophy may share much in
common with that of the great ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle; thus, in this essay we
will illustrate Aristotelian virtue ethics through a discussion of Marge's life in Springfield.
That said, we do not claim that Marge is some sort of paradigm Aristotelian who
carefully and consistently applies Aristotle's moral philosophy at every opportunity. In fact,
there are many things that she says and does that are not particularly virtuous (from an
Aristotelian standpoint) at all.1 However, our examination of her moral character should
draw not just from isolated actions, but from a broader sample of her behavior. Thus, just
as Barney Gumble remains an alcoholic despite his occasional moments of responsibility
in "The Days of Whine and D'oh'ses," artistic achievement in "A Star is Burns," and
astronaut training with "Deep Space Homer," Marge's overall pattern of behavior can serve
as an especially illustrative introduction to Aristotle's moral philosophy.2
Virtue and Character
While utilitarianism, Kantian deontology, and other modern moral philosophies
typically investigate the qualities that make an action a right action, the ancient Greeks
were more likely to focus upon the traits of character that make a person a good person.3
Aristotle provides one of the most important contributions to this tradition with his
Nicomachean Ethics. In this book, Aristotle not only compiles a long list of the virtuous
personality traits, he also presents a systematic explanation of each virtue as a mean
between two extremes. In addition, he attempts to justify the life of virtue, and even offers
suggestions to those interested in making their own lives more virtuous.
Given the unique focus of ancient Greek virtue ethics, we can understand an
Aristotelian virtue as a character trait that helps to make a person a good person. Such
character traits include not only tendencies to act in certain virtuous ways, but also
dispositions to experience certain virtuous feelings and emotions. In his Nicomachean
Ethics, Aristotle lists a number of these virtues including: 1. bravery; 2. temperance; 3.
generosity (especially when demonstrated on a large scale); 4. proper, self-confident pride
in one's own worth; 5. mildness; 6. friendliness; 7. honesty; 8. wit; and 9. modesty.4 Of
course, this list is not exhaustive, and philosophers since Aristotle have added other virtues
to it, but it does give us a preliminary grasp of the kinds of personality traits that Aristotle
thinks necessary for good character.
We find excellent illustrations of Aristotle's virtuous personality traits in Marge.
First, she is clearly a brave woman. Whether breaking up a counterfeit jeans ring run out of
her garage by "The Springfield Connection," escaping from a cult commune in "The Joy of
Sect," or standing up to a Poe-ssessed "Treehouse of Horror," Marge is rarely short on
courage. Her penchant for temperance pervades her daily life, leading her to shop at the
Safeway, discount dress barns, and the Ogdenville outlet mall in "Scenes from the Class
Struggle in Springfield." Finally, Marge's strong sense of honesty costs the Simpson family
millions of dollars in potential legal settlements ("Bart Gets Hit by a Car"). In these
examples and many others, then, Marge exhibits the personality traits that Aristotle
thought so important to good character.
As Aristotle enumerates his virtues, he also explains each as a mean or balance
struck between two vicious extremes, one excessive and the other deficient.5 For instance,
a virtuous sort of bravery lies somewhere between Homer's foolhardy recklessness and his
vicious cowardice. Likewise, a person who is virtuously self-controlled has neither
Barney's self-indulgence nor Flanders's indifference to physical pleasures, but something
between the two. People with the virtue of generosity do not give to others indiscriminately
(and thus are not wastefully over-generous, as Homer can sometimes be), but neither are
they as stingy as Mr. Burns usually is. We can define any virtue on Aristotle's list, then, by
relating it to its two corresponding, vicious extremes.6
Likewise, Marge's crime-stopping vigilantism in "The Springfield Connection" and
her dangerous escape from the Movementarian commune in "The Joy of Sect" demonstrate
that she is genuinely brave, but not foolhardy. She will hop across rivers through snapping
alligator jaws à la James Bond, but she won't jump from Jimmy's hansom cab to the family
car as they both speed though Central Park in "The City of New York vs. Homer Simpson."
Though she can be as brave as most any situation needs her to be, she does not simply fight
every battle that comes up. She employs diversionary tactics like "that hand thing" ("Blood
Feud") when she knows that brute strength will be useless. She also recognizes the value of
passive resistance, supporting Lisa as she boycotts Homer's screening of the Watson vs.
Tatum II fight ("Homer vs. Lisa and the Eighth Commandment"). Finally, when an edgy
new Krusty wrestles with his "Last Temptation" and incites members of his audience to
burn their cash, Homer tells Marge to give him all the money she has in her purse. Instead
of engaging Homer in a fruitless and unwinnable argument, Marge gives the money to Lisa,
telling her to run home and bury it in the back yard.
As for temperance, Marge tends to be more spartan than self-indulgent. As the wife
of an occasionally unemployed, incarcerated, and dimensionally-confused husband, Marge
has relatively little to work with financially. She shops wherever she thinks she might find
a bargain, and she refuses to squander the family's cash on a new pair of shoes that she
knows she does not need, semi-lamenting "If only I didn't already own a pair of shoes" in
"The City of New York vs. Homer Simpson." She is also shocked by the extravagance of
Mr. Burns's estate when the Simpson family house-sits the place, noting that the machine
that burns up his unmade bed each morning before pushing a new one out of the wall
"seems a little wasteful" ("The Mansion Family"). Nonetheless, she is not nearly as miserly
as Mega-Saver Chuck Garabedian, who conserves his cash by partying on an inexpensive
yacht that smells like cat pee with beautiful women who used to be men ("Thirty Minutes
Over Tokyo"). Garabedian represents a truly vicious frugality that Marge rejects,
especially after spoiled food purchased at the 33¢ store leaves Homer convulsing on the
floor (yet still craving more).
Given the Simpsons' fluctuating household income, it's perhaps not surprising to
find Marge a bit hesitant to donate her family's money to charity; she even refuses to allow
Lisa to "waste" a $100 inheritance with a donation to public broadcasting in "Bart the
Fink." But as Aristotle writes, "[O]ne who gives less [than another] may still be more
generous, if he has less to give," and Marge is as generous as her family's ever-changing
financial status allows her to be.7 For one thing, Marge always makes sure that Homer
gives sufficiently to the collection plate at church, scolding him as he tries to substitute a
30¢ Shake 'n' Bake coupon for the family's regular weekly contribution in "Bart's
Girlfriend." And even as the family's financial contributions are somewhat sparing, Marge
still graciously gives her time, talents, and other resources to those in need. She has taken
in Grandpa and Otto the bus driver as borders, scrubbed oil-slicked boulders with Lisa
("Bart after Dark"), volunteered to do telephone counseling for the Springfield Community
Church ("In Marge We Trust"), and donated to the local food drive ("Homer Defined").
Marge is inherently moderate in all things, from parenting and running the house to
making fun of the size of Burns's genitalia during her "Brush with Greatness." She is not as
stifling as Maude Flanders or Agnes Skinner, but not as permissive as Mrs. Muntz or the
recently-divorced Luann Van Houten. Marge even preaches moderation to Homer, urging
him to limit his pork intake to six servings per week in "Principal Charming." Thus, just as
Aristotle understands the importance of seeking a rational mean in a life of genuine virtue,
Marge directs her actions toward a moral balance between vicious extremes.
Justifying the Life of Virtue
Though virtue can be elusive, Aristotle believes that there is a significant payoff for
those who find it. This is because virtue is an essential component of successful living. As
he argues at the beginning of the Nicomachean Ethics, the ultimate end of human life is
happiness. There are many other things (such as fame, money, and pork chops) that we
may desire, but we desire these things because we believe they will ultimately make us
happy. We are sometimes wrong about this, of course, but the bottom line is that
"Happiness more than anything else seems unconditionally complete, since we always
[choose it, and also] choose it because of itself, never because of something else."8
Now, it is important to distinguish Aristotle's notion of happiness (the original
Greek term is eudaimonia) from pleasure (mmm. . . pleasure), for Aristotle does not want
to say that the goal of human life is the sort of mere physical gratification that Homer (not
the Greek) spends so much of his life pursuing. Rather, he seems to have in mind here a
more long-term happiness or general flourishing; Terence Irwin suggests that a better
translation of "eudaimonia" might be "doing well."9 With this sort of happiness established
as the ultimate goal of human life, Aristotle argues that the virtues are desirable because
they promote the long-term happiness of those who possess them. While living virtuously
does not guarantee that we will fare well in life, traits like self-confidence, friendliness, and
honesty do increase our chances of success. Thus, we can justify the virtuous life because
the virtues promote the well-being of people who have them.
Many have mistaken Aristotle's justification of virtue for a mere egoistic appeal to
our own selfish motives.10 However, Aristotle understood that we are a very social species,
and that our long-term happiness depends heavily upon our family and friends. We cannot
achieve eudaimonia without the contributions of others, and so many of the virtues
(generosity, friendliness, and honesty, for instance) are valuable to us precisely because
they help to cultivate the strong bonds of family and friendship that are essential to
successful living.
Marge's own happiness exemplifies this as well as anyone's. Besides her sisters
Patty and Selma ("the gruesome twosome"), she has no close friends, and without a regular
job or hobby to occupy her attention, her focus rarely wanders from Bart, Lisa, Maggie,
and Homer. The most important thing to her is, clearly, the well-being of her spouse and
children; indeed, this is something she values for its own sake. As she says, "The only thing
I'm high on is love; love for my son and daughters. Yes, a little L-S-D is all I need" ("Home
Sweet Home-Diddily-Dum-Doodily"). So it's through the happiness of her family that
Marge achieves eudaimonia for herself. Simple household tasks like washing clothes,
creating meatloaf men when "Mr. Lisa Goes to Washington," and knitting seatbelts for
homemade cars in "The City of New York vs. Homer Simpson" are not undesirable chores
to her. Rather, they bring her happiness because they contribute to the good of the family
she cherishes so dearly.11 In fact, Marge nearly loses her sense of purpose after Homer's
new job with the Globex Corporation requires the family to move into an automated home
that does most of the housework for her in "You Only Move Twice." No longer knowing
how to contribute to the good of her family, Marge sinks into a depression and develops a
drinking habit (though still a moderate one, not requiring David Crosby's intervention).
Thus, by living her life in accordance with the Aristotelian virtues, Marge nurtures the
kinds of strong social relationships that bring a deep and powerful happiness to her life.
Cultivating Virtue
Given the important role the virtues play in promoting eudaimonia, we might
wonder what we can do to make our own lives more virtuous, and thus more successful.
According to Aristotle, "None of the virtues of character arises in us naturally."12 Instead,
he says, we have a natural ability to acquire virtue through habituation; "We become just
by doing just actions, temperate by doing temperate actions, and brave by doing brave
actions."13
Refraining from pleasures makes us become temperate, and when we have become
temperate we are most able to refrain from pleasures. And it is similar with bravery; habituation in
disdaining what is fearful and in standing firm against it makes us become brave, and when we
have become brave we shall be most able to stand firm. (NE 1104a25-b5)
Virtuous people can thus serve as important models in our moral development. By
choosing to do the kinds of things that virtuous people themselves do, we can make
ourselves more virtuous. Eventually, we might even learn to feel the proper, virtuous
motivation of those who act virtuously just because they recognize the value of being
virtuous.
Marge also knows how important her model can be to the moral development of her
children. Her influence is strongest upon Lisa, and she takes advantage of any opportunity
she finds to encourage the growth of her daughter's own sense of right and wrong. When
Homer decides to steal services from the local cable television company in "Homer vs.
Lisa and the Eighth Commandment," Marge encourages Lisa's protest with lemonade and
the advice that "[W]hen you love somebody, you have to have faith that, in the end, they
will do the right thing." In "The Old Man and the Lisa," Marge encourages Lisa to listen to
her own conscience as she struggles with the moral dilemma brought on by a multi-million
dollar windfall from the animal recycling plant that she inadvertently convinced Mr. Burns
to build. "Lisa, you do whatever your conscience tells you," she says. The effect of Marge's
moral influence on Lisa is poignantly expressed in their aforementioned exchange in Moe's
Tavern:
MARGE: Lisa, here's all the money I have. Take it and bury it in the back yard.
LISA I love you, Mom. ("The Last Temptation of Krusty")
Marge's influence also has an effect on Bart's slower and somewhat more muddled
moral development. For instance, she advises Bart to "listen to your heart, and not the
voices in your head" as he grapples with the question of whether to testify in Freddy
Quimby's assault trial and risk punishment for skipping school himself in "The Boy Who
Knew Too Much."14 Like Aristotle, then, Marge knows what needs to be done to cultivate
the virtues in those still unable to fully appreciate their value.
Marge's Opposition
to the Divine Command Theory
Many of us believe that ethical questions can be settled only by reference to
religion. Thus, we often look to our ministers, priests, rabbis, and other religious leaders as
if they were moral experts with special abilities to solve ethical problems. It's also typical
for institutional and governmental ethics review boards to include representatives of the
major religions. Furthermore, many people have suggested that promoting school prayer,
publicly posting the Ten Commandments, or teaching religious creationism in our nation's
science classrooms could help to eliminate social problems like substance abuse and
school violence.
In Springfield, Ned Flanders exemplifies one way (if not the only way) of
understanding the influence of religion upon ethics.15 Ned seems to be what philosophers
call a divine command theorist, since he thinks that morality is a simple function of God's
divine command; to him, "morally right" means simply "commanded by God," and
"morally wrong" means simply "forbidden by God."16 Consequently, Ned consults with
Reverend Lovejoy or prays directly to God Himself to resolve the moral dilemmas he faces.
For instance, he asks the Reverend's permission to play "capture the flag" with Rod and
Todd on the sabbath in "King of the Hill"; Lovejoy responds, "Oh, just play the damn game,
Ned." Ned also makes a special telephone call to the model train room in Reverend
Lovejoy's basement as he tries to decide whether to baptize his new foster children, Bart,
Lisa, and Maggie, in "Home Sweet Home-Diddily-Dum-Doodily."17 (This call prompts
Lovejoy to ask, "Ned, have you thought about one of the other major religions? They're all
pretty much the same.") And when a hurricane destroys his family's home but leaves the
rest of Springfield unscathed in "Hurricane Neddy," Ned tries to procure an explanation
from God by confessing, "I've done everything the Bible says; even the stuff that
contradicts the other stuff!" Thus, Ned apparently believes he can find solutions to his
moral problems not by thinking for himself, but by consulting the appropriate divine
command. His faith is as blind as it is complete, and he floats through life on a moral
cruise-control, with his ethical dilemmas effectively pre-resolved.
In this context, it seems that Marge's religious beliefs have relatively little influence
on her moral decision-making. It's clear that she believes in God; she prays to prevent
Springfield's apparently imminent destruction in "Bart's Comet" and "Lisa the Skeptic,"
and when Homer gives up church, she warns him, "Don't make me choose between my
man and my God, because you just can't win" ("Homer the Heretic"). She even seeks out
Reverend Lovejoy's help with her marriage on two non-consecutive occasions in "War of
the Simpsons" and "Secrets of a Successful Marriage." Nonetheless, Marge's everyday
moral decision-making is driven more by her own well-developed conscience than by her
religious faith, and she is comfortable rejecting the Church's official moral judgments in a
way that Flanders never could be. For instance, instead of joining the Lovejoy and Flanders
families to protest an exhibition of Michelangelo's nude statue of David, Marge defends the
great work of art on Kent Brockman's Smartline news show ("Itchy & Scratchy & Marge").
She refuses to lead, or even support, the knee-jerk protest because she sees that nudity is
not necessarily evil or immoral, while all Helen Lovejoy can do is shout her favorite
canned phrase, "Won't someone please think of the children?" She also criticizes the
Reverend's out-of-touch pastoral counseling, then sets up her own counseling service that
receives rave reviews from the residents of Springfield:
MOE: I've lost the will to live.
MARGE: Oh, that's ridiculous, Moe. You've got lots to live for.
MOE: Really? That's not what Reverend Lovejoy's been tellin' me. Wow, you're good.
Thanks. ("In Marge We Trust")
Thus, Marge's ethical standards are independent of those taught by Springfield's most
prominent religious authorities.
Many moral philosophers, even religious moral philosophers, share Marge's doubts
about the divine command theory.18 The great ancient Greek philosopher Plato (Aristotle's
teacher at the Academy in Athens) has had an especially influential role to play in this
tradition. In his classic dialogue Euthyphro, Plato points out that morality would become
utterly arbitrary if the divine command theory were true.19 God could then command us to
do anything whatsoever, and His simply commanding it would make it morally right.
However, this general line of argument goes, it seems absurd to suggest that God's mere
command could make mass murder or rape acceptable, and so the divine command theory
must be flawed. Moral philosophy begins not with the observation that God's command
makes an action right, but with questions about which qualities make an action right, and
thus (perhaps) worthy of divine favor. In any case, Plato's critique has led many moral
philosophers to inquire more deeply into such ethical questions, and if these thinkers are
correct, then morality can be investigated and understood independently of religion.
Conclusion:
"Just do what I would do"
Is Marge the model Aristotelian? No. Like the rest of the cast of The Simpsons,
Marge is never totally defined, always ready to do or say something to set up a gag for
Homer or Bart, even if it seems completely out of character. Indeed, any Simpsons
character sketch is riddled with contradictions by the very nature of the show; as Burns
says in "Team Homer," "I've had one of my characteristic changes of heart." Nevertheless,
Marge typically follows the Aristotelian recipe for a happy, moral life, and with great
success. The good to which she looks in making her decisions (moral or otherwise) is the
good of her family, and therefore herself. She makes these decisions not because she hopes
that they will be reciprocated, but because they are reciprocated by their very nature; what
is good for them is good for her. In Marge we see that Aristotle's moral virtues can be
successfully applied not just in the abstract, ivory towers of academia, but in the real,
workaday cartoon world. Her bravery, honesty, temperance, and other virtues cannot be
denied, and neither can her resulting happiness. Marge enjoys being brave, honest, and
temperate because those qualities help her to help her family. Her happiness justifies her
life of Aristotelian virtue and proves that people (or cartoon people anyway) can live moral
lives regardless of their religious convictions.
Like so many people today, then, Marge might best be described as a
Christian-flavored Aristotelian. Such folks favor the underlying message of peace on earth
and good will toward men, but disregard many of the Bible's rigid moral rules, sanitary
guidelines, and dietary requirements. Instead of trying to follow "all the well-meaning
rules that don't work out in real life" like Flanders, people like Marge can support capital
punishment, vote pro-choice, and still sit comfortably in church on Sunday with the
knowledge that their ethical decisions are based on reason and conscience, not just blind
faith. Indeed, Marge is much less concerned with being a good Christian than with being a
good person.
1 For additional thoughts on this issue, see Chapter 1 of this volume.
2 Daniel Barwick takes on a similar project in his "George's Failed Quest for Happiness: An
Aristotelian Analysis," in William Irwin, ed., Seinfeld and Philosophy (Chicago: Open Court, 2000). See also
Aeon Skoble's chapter in the same book, "Virtue Ethics and TV's Seinfeld."
3 James Rachels includes a helpful introductory discussion of this distinction in his Elements of
Moral Philosophy (New York: McGraw Hill, 1999), pp. 175-77
4 This list appears in Book IV of the Nicomachean Ethics (abbreviated hereafter as NE; see T.
Irwin's translation (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985), or W.D. Ross and J.O. Urmson's translation in J. Barnes's
edition of The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1984).
5 NE 1106a6-1107a25.
6 Aristotle admitted that a virtuous mean does not exist for all character traits. For instance, he
claims that spite, shamelessness, and envy can never be virtuous, and that adultery, theft, and murder are
always wrong. As he writes, "[Thinking that these admit of a mean] is like thinking that unjust or cowardly or
intemperate action also admits of a mean, an excess, or a deficiency. For then there would be a mean of
excess, a mean of deficiency, an excess of excess, and a deficiency of deficiency" (NE 1107a9-25).
7 NE 1120b8-10.
8 NE 1097b1-5.
9 See Irwin's translation of the NE, p. 407.
10 For Aristotle's response to this criticism, see NE 1097b3 and 1170b5 as well as p. xviii of Irwin's
translation.
11 One might wonder whether these kinds of activities lead Marge to enjoy genuine eudaimonia or
something more like mere physical pleasure; note, though, that she doesn't seem to do these things because of
some selfish motivation, but because she sees the role such actions can play in nurturing strong familial
relations. For more on the feminist response to, and criticism of, Marge, see Chapter 9 of this volume.
12 NE 1103a15.
13 NE 1104a30-35.
14 Unfortunately for Bart, though, things are not always so clear; his conscience actually convinces
him to shoplift a copy of the videogame Bonestorm in "Marge Be Not Proud."
15 For another interpretation of Flanders's moral philosophy, see Chapter 14 of this volume. The
divine command theory is not the only religious theory of ethics; St. Thomas Aquinas's natural law theory,
for instance, is a religious moral philosophy, but very different from the divine command theory.
16 This presentation of the divine command theory comes from Rachels, Elements, pp. 55-59.
17 He also calls with concerns about enhancing his meekness and coveting his own wife, as well as
such non-moral questions as what to do when he swallows a toothpick ("In Marge We Trust").
18 Reverend Lovejoy himself even admits that Biblical teachings have their shortcomings; while
counseling Marge in "Secrets of a Successful Marriage," he asks, "Y'ever sat down and read this thing?
Technically, we're not allowed to go to the bathroom."
19 See G.M.A. Grube's translation of the Euthyphro in the Five Dialogues collection (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1981).
5
Thus Spake Bart:
On Nietzsche and the Virtues of Being Bad
MARK T. CONARD
For the present, the comedy of existence has not yet "become conscious" of itself. For the present,
we still live in the age of tragedy, the age of moralities and religions. -- NIETZSCHE 1
JESSICA LOVEJOY: You're bad, Bart Simpson.
BART: No I'm not! I'm really --
JESSICA LOVEJOY: Yes you are. You're bad. . . and I like it.
BART: I'm bad to the bone, honey.2
Good Girls and Bad Boys
You know the stories: he cut the head off the statue of Jebediah Springfield; he
burned down the family Christmas tree; he shoplifted a copy of Bonestorm; he cheated on
an IQ test and got himself placed in genius school; he fooled the town into thinking there
was a little boy trapped down a well, etc., etc., etc. Bart Simpson isn't some loveable little
scamp who always seems to find himself in trouble; he isn't a rebel with a heart of gold.
He's a wise-cracking delinquent, a bad boy in bright blue pants, a spoiler, one of Satan's
minions -- if you believe in that sort of thing.
You probably think it's his sister, Lisa, who's the virtuous one. She's bright, talented,
very logical, rational, sensitive. She has principles: she fights injustice as she sees it; she's a
vegetarian because she believes in animal rights; she stands up against the greedy Mr.
Burns's excesses; and she has love and compassion for her friends and family, and indeed
for all those who are less fortunate. She's the little girl we love to love. You'd probably say
she's the only admirable character on the show.
Well, let me tell you about another bad boy, the bad boy of philosophy (what -- you
didn't think philosophy had bad boys?). His name was Friedrich Nietzsche, and --
philosophically -- he's as bad as they come, honey. He too was a kind of wise-cracking
philosophical delinquent. He bucked authority, he was a spoiler. And one of Satan's
minions? -- hell, he wrote a book called The Antichrist! He seemed to hate everything,
every ideal that most people love and hold dear to themselves -- more, he would tear down
those ideals by cleverly showing how they were interconnected with things that those same
people hate. He rebuked religion, he laughed at pity. He called Socrates a buffoon who got
himself taken seriously. He called Kant a decadent, Descartes superficial, and John Stuart
Mill a flathead! He infamously wrote in Thus Spake Zarathustra, if you're going to women,
"Don't forget the whip!"3
Now, while Nietzsche rejected and even laughed at the traditional ideal, the
so-called "good person," the compassionate, religiously virtuous person, he forged
something of his own ideal: the free spirit; the person who rejects traditional morality,
traditional virtues; the person who embraces the chaos of the world and gives style to his
character.
Could it be that from a Nietzschean perspective we've been admiring the wrong
character? Might Lisa Simpson be part of what Nietzsche calls world-slandering weariness,
decadence, slave morality, resentment? Sure, it's fun to be bad, but might there be
something healthy and life-affirming, something philosophically important about it? Could
Bart Simpson be, in the end, the Nietzschean ideal?
The Birth of Comedy:
Appearance vs. Reality
In order to answer the above questions, we need to understand why Nietzsche was
the philosopher's bad boy, and why he extolled the virtues of acting out (so to speak).
In his earliest works, Nietzsche was very much influenced by the philosopher
Arthur Schopenhauer, who was a particularly unfunny man. As legend has it, for example,
he once threw an old lady down a flight of stairs. Now, among other things, Schopenhauer
held a version of the division between appearance and reality. He believed that the world as
we experience it, as things, people, trees, dogs and Squishies, is only a kind of surface
appearance or, in his words, a representation. Underneath or behind this appearance is the
true nature of the world, which he called will. This will is a blind, ceaseless, driving force,
the same force and will that we find in ourselves as the sex drive, for example, or as the
instinct for Duff Beer. Because the will is an endless striving, desires are sated but arise
over and over again. You drink a Duff (or ten), get drunk, and your desire is momentarily
satisfied. But tomorrow the desire arises anew. Now, Schopenhauer believed that to desire
and to have one's desires frustrated is to suffer, and thus since there is no ultimate end to the
desire, no ultimate satisfaction, life is perpetual suffering.
In his first book, The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche clearly adopts this
Schopenhauerian dualistic view of a distinction between appearance and reality, will and
representation, but interestingly he personifies the word "will," treats it as if it were a
conscious agent, and refers to it as "the primal unity."4 Now, the word "aesthetics," which
has to do with the study of art and beauty, is derived from the Greek word, "aisthetikos,"
which refers to the perceptive quality, or the appearance of things. Since the world as
representation, the world we experience around us everyday, is an appearance, Nietzsche
in this first work talks about this world as if it were a kind of artistic creation of this
personified primal unity at the heart of things: "[W]e may assume that we are merely
images and artistic projections for the true author, and that we have our highest dignity in
our significance as works of art -- for it is only as an aesthetic phenomenon that existence
and the world are eternally justified. . ."5 The "true author" is of course the primal unity, but
-- continuing the anthropomorphism -- why does it project us and the rest of the world, why
does it do art? Nietzsche says:
. . . the truly existent primal unity, eternally suffering and contradictory . . . needs the rapturous
vision, the pleasurable illusion, for its continuous redemption. And we, completely wrapped up in
this illusion and composed of it, are compelled to consider this illusion as the truly nonexistent -- i.e.,
as a perpetual becoming in time, space and causality -- in other words, as empirical reality.6
The world as we know it, the everyday world, the world as representation, is a mere
illusion, the "truly nonexistent." And at its heart, reality is so awful -- a ceaseless, blind,
driving, ultimately aimless and therefore unsatisfied and suffering will -- that to see into
this heart, to understand the true nature of existence, is debilitating. What's more, the curse
of human beings is to be (able to be) aware of their situation, to realize the nature of the
world and to want to put it right. But of course that's impossible. Nietzsche says:
"Conscious of the truth he has once seen, man now sees everywhere only the horror or the
absurdity of existence."7
According to Nietzsche, art, and only art, is our saving grace:
Here, when the danger to his will is greatest, art approaches as a saving sorceress, expert
at healing. She alone knows how to turn these nauseous thoughts about the horror or absurdity of
existence into notions with which one can live: these are the sublime as the artistic taming of the
horrible, and the comic as the artistic discharge of the nausea of absurdity.8
We and the primal unity alike, having grasped the meaningless chaotic nature of
things, both need the "rapturous vision" and the "pleasurable illusion" for our "continuous
redemption"; we need it really just to survive.
The Birth of Tragedy concerns the way the ancient Greeks dealt with the horror and
the absurdity of existence: through art, specifically Attic tragedy, they were able to
overcome the horrible truth, they were able to find redemption. According to Nietzsche,
this is the healthy, honest way to face chaotic, meaningless existence. But there are
unhealthy and dishonest ways as well. These consist mainly in denying the
meaninglessness, the absurdity, the chaos, the horror, turning away from it, lying to oneself
and others about the nature of reality. In Ancient Greece, this unhealthiness and dishonesty
is embodied, according to Nietzsche, in the person of Socrates. He says:
. . . there is, to be sure, a profound illusion that first saw the light of the world in the person of
Socrates: the unshakable faith that thought, using the thread of causality, can penetrate the
deepest abysses of being, and that thought is capable not only of knowing being but even of
correcting it.9
Instead of acknowledging the true character of the world and learning to deal with
the chaos, Socrates believed that thought was capable of not only grasping and
understanding the world, but also of fixing it. Nietzsche goes on to say:
Socrates is the prototype of the theoretical optimist who, with his faith that the nature of
things can be fathomed, ascribes to knowledge and insight the power of a panacea, while
understanding error as the evil par excellence.10
We all know Socrates to be the supremely rational person. Reason is not only our
guide to understanding the world, he tells us, but it is the key to living well, and evil is only
ignorance. For Nietzsche, in this earliest work, this is a grand mistake, a symptom of
degeneration and weakness; it is a lie we tell ourselves because we're too weak to face
reality.
It's clear that if our world is chaotic, meaningless and absurd, the Simpson universe
is even more so. Think of the craziness that we witness from episode to episode. Jasper
mistakes Friday's pills for Wednesday's and instantly turns into some kind of werewolf-like
creature; Mr. Burns is simultaneously seventy-two and a hundred and four years old;
Maggie manages to shoot Mr. Burns; Aunt Selma finds husband after husband; Marge and
Chief Wiggum have the same color blue hair; and nobody ever gets any older.
The point I want to make here is that in Springfield, the town without a state, Lisa
plays the role of Socrates, the theoretical optimist. Despite being confronted with the
chaotic, absurd world around her, she persists in believing that reason can not only help her
to understand that world but correct it. She tries to stand up for animal rights; she tries to
cure Mr. Burns of his greediness and Homer of his ignorance. She tries to mold Bart's
character, to teach him how to be virtuous. She uses flashcards to try and teach Maggie
such words as "credenza," even though Maggie never speaks. Lisa struggles from week to
week to penetrate the dark, abyssal clouds of absurdity and meaninglessness, vice and
ignorance, with her razor-sharp intellect and her reason. But, alas, nothing ever really
changes. Mr. Burns remains greedy, Homer ignorant, Bart vicious, and Springfield at large
absurd. Consequently, from a Nietzschean point of view, the tables might be turned on Lisa.
All the characteristics and virtues for which we admire and praise her might in fact be
symptoms of a Socratic sickness, a hyper-rational weakness, a flight from reality into
illusion and self-deception.
But even if this is true, even if this is the way we ought to view Lisa, that doesn't
automatically mean that Bart, the rebel, the spoiler, the maker of fart noises, and the
nightmare of Sunday school teachers and babysitters, is to be admired.
Life as Art, Or at Least as a Cartoon
Soon after The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche abandoned any form of dualism, he
rejected the split between representation and will, appearance and reality. In this later view,
Nietzsche claims there is only the chaotic flux; flux is the only reality: "The reasons for
which 'this' world has been characterized as 'apparent' are the very reasons which indicate
its reality," Nietzsche says; in other words, the fact that it becomes, that it's in flux, means
that it's real; "any other kind of reality is absolutely indemonstrable."11
So why did we ever believe there was something beyond what we experience,
beyond "this" world, why did we ever think there was a distinction to be made between
appearance and reality? One of the main reasons, Nietzsche says, is because of the
structure of language. We see actions, deeds, being performed (that is, we experience
phenomena in the chaotic world around us), and the only way we can make sense of these
actions or phenomena, to grasp them, is to project behind them, by means of language,
some stable subject which causes them. ("I" run; "you" yell; "Nelson" punches.) Because
thinking and language cannot describe or represent a world in flux, it is necessary to speak
as if there were stable things which have properties, and stable subjects which cause
actions. This limitation of thought and language then gets projected into the world. We
actually come to believe in unity, substance, identity, permanence (in other words, being).
Nietzsche says:
. . . the popular mind separates the lightning from its flash and takes the latter for an action, for the
operation of a subject called lightning. . . But there is no such substratum; there is no "being" behind
doing, effecting, becoming; "the doer" is merely a fiction added to the deed -- the deed is everything.
The popular mind in fact doubles the deed; when it sees the lightning flash, it is the deed of a deed:
it posits the same event first as cause and then a second time as its effect.12
We say, "lightning flashes," but are there really two things, the lightning and the
flash? No, of course not. But this seems to be the only way we're able to grasp and express
things. We have to use a subject, "lightning," and a verb, "flashes," in order to express what
we've experienced. But in so doing, we trick ourselves into believing that there's some
stable thing behind the action which in fact causes it. That is, because we have the
subject/predicate distinction built into our language, we come to believe that this
adequately mirrors the structure of reality. But this is a mistake. We say, "Homer eats,"
"Homer drinks," "Homer belches," when in reality there is nothing called "Homer" beyond
the eating, drinking, and belching. There is no being behind the doing. Homer just is the
sum of his actions, and no more.
This distinction between doer and deed petrified in our language is the beginning of
the split between appearance and reality, Nietzsche tells us, and gets transformed by Plato,
for example, into the forms/particulars dichotomy; by Schopenhauer into the
will/representation distinction; and by Christians into the split between heaven and earth,
God and man. "I am afraid we are not rid of God because we still have faith in grammar,"13
Nietzsche says.
Before going on to talk about Nietzsche's reversal of the traditionally "good" and
traditionally "bad," I want to point out that, though of course TV hadn't yet been invented
when Nietzsche lived, and though animation was the farthest thing from his mind, a
cartoon like The Simpsons may be the perfect embodiment of (or metaphor for) Nietzsche's
insight about the fiction of the "doer" being projected behind the "deed." That is, in a show
like The Simpsons there truly is no being behind the doing. What you see is what you get.
Homer, Bart, Lisa, Marge, and Maggie are indeed no more than the sum of their actions.
There is no substance, no ego, no being behind the phenomena, which then causes those
actions. A cartoon is of course purely phenomenal, pure appearance; there aren't even
actors on screen or on stage portraying the characters, who can, as it were, take off the
mask and step away from the character. What more is there to Bart than his weekly
misdeeds? The answer: nothing. There couldn't be anything more to him. He is purely the
sum of what he does. Nietzsche's insight, again, is that this is not only the way cartoons
work; this is the way the world is, the way reality is constructed. The world is a chaotic,
meaningless flux of becoming, and to be real, to be a part of the world, to be a part of the
flux, is to appear. The appearance doesn't mask reality; the appearance is reality. Or, better:
we can now do away with these concepts, appearance and reality, altogether. All we can
really say is, there is the flux.
The Nietzschean Ideal
To repeat, in his earliest writings, Nietzsche held that the world was divided into
appearance and reality, will and representation, a view which he soon repudiated by
claiming that there's nothing masking the chaos, there is no being behind doing. Now,
here's the really interesting consequence of this shift in his position: As opposed to the
earlier view, in which we were mere phenomena of the underlying will, artistic projections,
art works for the primal unity which is the true artist and spectator, we are now both will
and phenomenon, or rather, these are the same thing. Thus we ourselves become artist,
spectator, and artwork all in one: "As an aesthetic phenomenon existence is still bearable
for us, and art furnishes us with eyes and hands and above all the good conscience to be
able to turn ourselves into such a phenomenon."14 Nietzsche has obliterated the distinction
between art and life. Consequently, since it is as an aesthetic phenomenon, as an artistic
endeavor that existence is justified or redeemed, Nietzsche moves from talking about
justification of the world to individual justification. It is as expressions of will, as will
manifest, that we are artists and art works combined, and thus we justify ourselves, we
provide meaning for our lives, by creating ourselves, through these expressions of will,
through our actions.
What would it mean, though, to make an artwork of one's life? Recall that for
Nietzsche, abandoning a reality hidden behind appearance means also abandoning any
notion of a stable, enduring ego or subject: "The 'subject' is not something given, it is
something added and invented and projected behind what there is."15 Part of what
Nietzsche is after here, then, is to construct a self for oneself out of one's various drives,
instincts, wills, actions, etc. In his influential work, Nietzsche: Life as Literature,
Alexander Nehamas tells us: "The unity of the self, which therefore also constitutes its
identity, is not something given but something achieved, not a beginning but a goal."16 In
The Gay Science, Nietzsche hints at this ideal or project when he speaks of "giving style" to
oneself:
One thing is needful. -- To "give style" to one's character -- a great and rare art! It is
practiced by those who survey all the strengths and weaknesses of their nature and then fit them
into an artistic plan until every one of them appears as art and reason and even weaknesses delight
the eye. . . In the end, when the work is finished, it becomes evident how the constraint of a single
taste governed and formed everything large and small. Whether this taste was good or bad is less
important than one might suppose, if only it was a single taste!17
Since the ego is "only a conceptual synthesis,"18 not something stable or given, it is
a part of the flux, like everything else, the goal for Nietzsche becomes to perform this
synthesis, to construct an identity for oneself, to create oneself, according to some kind of
plan or schema, thus giving "style" to one's character.
This Nietzschean ideal culminates in the figure of the Übermensch, or overman, the
being who has achieved this very difficult project of making an artwork out of his life, the
self-creating being. Nehamas says: "Thus Spoke Zarathustra is constructed around the idea
of creating one's own self or, what comes to the same thing, the Übermensch."19 And
Richard Schacht says: ". . . the 'overman' is to be construed as a symbol of human life raised
to the level of art. . ."20
Sure, It's Fun To Be Bad,
But Might It Also Be. . .
I discussed above "Socratic optimism," the belief that the universe is intelligible
and meaningful, and how it is a means to avoid accepting and embracing the chaotic
meaningless flux of existence. Throughout his life, Nietzsche never ceases to rail against
those who he claims deny reality, those who aren't strong enough to affirm life the way that
it is. These include most traditional philosophers and virtually all religions. What they tend
to have in common, Nietzsche says, is that they posit a fictitious other world, something
beyond, as the denial of the here and now, the flux, in an effort to comfort themselves.
Plato, for example, believes in a realm of eternal and unchanging forms, beyond this world
of transient and unstable particulars. Christians posit as their "other" God, heaven, and a
soul, standing in opposition to human beings, the earth, and the body. In other words, this
world is chaotic and meaningless and therefore unendurable; consequently, in order to
make myself feel better, I'll believe that there is something which is the opposite,
something which is eternal rather than transient, stable rather than chaotic, and meaningful
rather than meaningless.
This would be all well and good, were it not for a couple of very dire consequences,
Nietzsche says. First, in positing a world of infinite value, reality, the here and now, is
divested of any possible value that it might have. Just because the world, as it is, is
inherently meaningless, doesn't mean that nothing has value. Value is something that is
generated by human beings, in the way we lead our lives, and through our relationships to
things and to other people. Our lives and this world have value because we invest them
with value. But when we create and believe in a beyond that is of infinite value, something
that's eternal and unchanging, the here and now, reality, in comparison, is emptied of any
possible value. What worth does the earth or my body have in comparison to heaven and
my immortal soul? What value do the particulars in the world have, in comparison to
Plato's eternal forms? None, of course! All worth, all value is transferred out of the world,
out of this life to a nonexistent beyond, leaving us with a world worth nothing.
Second, this kind of thinking is not just a private consolation. Those who believe in
a beyond traditionally have wanted to force others, and indeed typically the rest of the
world, to accept that belief too. In the first essay of On the Genealogy of Morals, " 'Good
and Evil,' 'Good and Bad'," Nietzsche tells the story of how moral valuations first came
about. The judgment, "good," Nietzsche says, first arose when the strong, the healthy, the
active, the noble, designated themselves and everything like them as "good":
[I]t was "the good" themselves, that is to say, the noble, powerful, high-stationed and high-minded,
who felt and established themselves and their actions as good, that is, of the first rank, in
contradistinction to all the low, low-minded, common and plebian.21
The strong nobles, as an affirmation of themselves and everything that was like them,
coined the word, "good," to designate themselves and their kind. In contrast, rather as an
afterthought, they designated everything that was not like them, everything weak, sickly,
ignoble, as "bad," not, mind you, as any kind of condemnation. These terms didn't yet have
any kind of moral connotation attached to them. The nobles had no sense that things could
or ought to be different, that a bad person was in any way responsible for being bad. This
mode of valuation was simply a way of distinguishing themselves, and of designating those
who were not like them.
Nietzsche refers to this mode of valuation as "master morality," and he doesn't pull
any punches in describing these early "masters" or "nobles": Indeed, they were strong,
healthy, and active, but they were also uneducated, lacking in self-reflection, and they were
violent. They took what they wanted, robbed, raped, pillaged, all because they could,
because they were strong enough to do so, and because they enjoyed it. Think of Nelson
and his cronies. They beat up kids, take their lunch money, steal their cupcakes, all with
seeming impunity. Why? Because they can, of course. No one is tough enough to stop
them.
Now, the "bad," as designated by the nobles, the weak, the sickly, the ignoble and
inactive, of course didn't like being beaten up and having their cupcakes stolen. But there
was nothing they could do about it. They weren't strong enough to stand up for themselves.
Consequently, there developed in them a deep, festering, hateful resentment against the
nobles. This festering resentment, then, is the origin of "slave morality":
The slave revolt in morality begins when ressentiment itself becomes creative and gives
birth to values: the ressentiment of natures that are denied the true reaction, that of deeds, and
compensate themselves with an imaginary revenge. While every noble morality develops from a
triumphant affirmation of itself, slave morality from the outset says No to what is "outside," what is
"different," what is "not itself; and this No is its creative deed. This inversion of the value-positing
eye -- this need to direct one's view outward instead of back to oneself -- is of the essence of
ressentiment: in order to exist, slave morality always first needs a hostile external world; it needs,
physiologically speaking, external stimuli in order to act at all -- its action is fundamentally
reaction.22
Out of his resentment for being weak, sickly, for being maltreated and being unable to do
anything about it, the "slave" reacts, he screams No at what is different, at the noble, at
what he wishes he could be. He labels the noble, "evil," and as an afterthought calls himself,
"good."
Nietzsche doesn't mean to say that these people were actually and literally slaves.
He's using that term to designate the weak, sickly type of man whose morality springs from
resentment. What this "slave," this weak man wants, more than anything, is to be strong, to
be healthy and active, to take, to conquer, to rule; he wants to be like the noble. Unable to
do this, he exacts his revenge upon the strong and healthy. First, Nietzsche says, the slave's
weakness is transformed into "something meritorious"; his "impotence which does not
requite [is changed] into 'goodness of heart'; anxious lowliness into 'humility'; subjection to
those one hates into 'obedience'."23 His inability to be strong, healthy and active is
reinterpreted as a virtue, as something desirable, and of course the commanding strength
and vitality of the "master" is, in contrast, redefined as something reprehensible. Then, in a
crafty and underhanded move, the weak man devises his heaven as the kingdom where he
will rule, and where the strong will be punished for their strength: "These weak people --
some day or other they too intend to be the strong, there is no doubt of that, some day their
'kingdom' too shall come -- they term it 'the kingdom of God,' of course . . ."24 The meek
shall inherit the earth, and the "evil" will be punished for eternity. Nietzsche says: "When
the herd animal is irradiated by the glory of the purest virtue, the exceptional man must
have been devaluated into evil."25
Slave morality triumphed, of course. The weak were able to convince the
simple-minded nobles that weakness, humility, obedience, pity, etc., are virtues, and that
strength, action, vitality, etc. are vices. According to Nietzsche, this was a calamity of
unimaginable proportions. Strength, health, vitality, an ability to not only accept the chaos
of the world, but to embrace it and to mold it into something beautiful -- these are the very
traits and characteristics necessary for the person who is capable of investing his life and
this world with meaning, with value and worth, to actually do so. And not only have they
been lied and vilified into something repugnant, but the earth and this life have been
devalued. Consequently, we're left with a valueless, devalued existence and are powerless
to reinvest it with meaning, with vitality, with worth.
This, then, is the root of Nietzsche's "bad boy" persona, why he bucks tradition and
morality, why he reviles most things that the majority of us weaklings take to be the most
important, but which, he claims, are really life-denying, life-slandering, and dangerous.
Consequently, he counsels us to go "beyond good and evil," to move beyond the "slave
morality," to stop transferring value and worth out of this world and out of this life, and to
have the strength and courage to embrace the chaos of existence and our lives and to forge
something meaningful out of it.
Bart the Übermensch?
Okay, so Nietzsche is the philosopher's bad boy, and Bart Simpson is Springfield's
bad boy. Certainly Bart bucks authority, and he has rejected (or perhaps never actually
adopted) traditional morality. Trying to convince Mr. Burns to allow him to come along to
retrieve the Flying Hellfish bonanza, for example, he says: "Can I go with you to get the
treasure? I won't eat much and I don't know the difference between right and wrong."26 But
would Nietzsche have approved of Bart? Could Bart in some way be an exemplar of the
Nietzschean (reverse) ideal? Alas, the answer is clearly no.
First -- and many people make this mistake -- even though Nietzsche condemns
"slave morality," calling it world-slandering and life-denying, he is not at all advocating
master morality. The masters were violent, unthinking brutes. Nietzsche is not holding
them up as an ideal, saying we should be like them, that might makes right, etc. He's not
counseling us to bully others, take their lunch money, and eat their cupcakes. So even if
Bart were to adhere to a master morality ethic -- and it seems that this characterization
would fit Nelson and Jimbo better than him -- that still wouldn't make him an exemplar of
the Nietzschean ideal.
No, Nietzsche's ideal is more the artist, the self-overcoming, self-creating
individual, who forges new values, who makes an artwork out of his life. And I think we'd
be hard-pressed to describe Bart in this way. He does seem at times to have a sense of the
chaos of the world and his existence. For example, hoping to play Fallout Boy in the new
Radioactive Man film, he says: "If I get this role, I can finally come to terms with this
funny little muddle called Bart."27 He realizes that his life is chaotic, that he's a "funny little
muddle," which needs to be given form. And indeed there does seem to be a consistent sort
of style to his character, but the way he defines himself is largely reactive, and this is of
course something that Nietzsche would not condone at all. What I mean is that Bart largely
defines himself and forges his identity, not as some kind of triumphant affirmation of his
talents and abilities, not as a grand and creative weaving-together of the disparate elements
of his self, but rather he defines himself in opposition to authority. For example, Bart
accidentally gets Principal Skinner fired when he brings Santa's Little Helper to school for
show-and-tell. Ned Flanders fills in as principal, eliminates detention, puts all the kids on
the honor system, and serves peanut butter cups and Yoo-Hoo to whomever gets sent to his
office. Bart and Skinner become friends, oddly enough, and then after Skinner re-enlists in
the army, Bart realizes that he misses Skinner's authoritarian (as opposed to Flanders's very
lax) rule. Lisa tells him why:
BART: It's weird, Lis: I miss him as a friend, but I miss him even more as an enemy.
LISA: I think you need Skinner, Bart. Everybody needs a nemesis. Sherlock Holmes had
his Dr. Moriarty, Mountain Dew has its Mellow Yellow, even Maggie has that baby with the one
eyebrow.28
Everyone may need a nemesis, but while Holmes had a distinct character all his
own and thus used Dr. Moriarty simply to test his formidable skills, Bart actually seems to
create or define himself precisely in opposition to authority, as the other to authority, and
not as some identifiable character in his own right.
In one very telling episode, the entire town of Springfield is convinced by self-help
guru Brad Goodman that they ought to act like Bart, and "do what they feel like." News
anchorman Kent Brockman curses on live TV and sprays his mouth full of whipped cream;
Reverend Lovejoy plays Marvin Hamlisch (very poorly) on the church organ in front of the
congregation; Aunt Patty and Aunt Selma ride naked through town on horseback. Seeing
that everyone is following his lead, Bart proclaims to his sister: "Lis, today I am a god."
But Bart soon finds that having everyone do as he does is not all ham and plaques.
He wants to respond to Mrs. Krabappel's questions in class, but everybody is giving
wise-cracking answers. He wants to do some of his "patented spitting off the overpass,"
only to find dozens of people already standing there hocking lugies. Bart is not happy, and
again it is Lisa who provides the answer to why:
BART: Lis, everyone in town is acting like me. So why does it suck?
LISA: It's simple, Bart: you've defined yourself as a rebel, and in the absence of a
repressive milieu your societal nature's been co-opted.
BART: I see.
LISA: Ever since that self-help guy came to town, you've lost your identity. You've fallen
through the cracks of our quick-fix, one-hour photo, instant oatmeal society.
BART: What's the answer?
LISA: Well, this is your chance to develop a new and better identity. May I suggest. . .
good-natured doormat?
BART: Sounds good, sis. Just tell me what to do.29
Bart's whole identity is created around rebelling, bucking authority. Consequently, when
the authority disappears, Bart loses his identity. He no longer knows who and what he is.
Interestingly, Lisa, in all her wisdom, suggests to Bart that he forge a new identity, a
good-natured doormat, presumably a Ned Flanders-like goody-goody, over whom people
(like Homer) walk. Bart, not knowing how to go about such a thing, wants her to tell him
what to do. In other words, again, far from being the Nietzschean self-overcoming,
self-creating ideal, the being who actively gives style to his character and forges new
values, Bart is still looking to identify himself reactively, in response to others, through the
mediation of others (both through Lisa, who will instruct him what to do, and through
others who, presumably, will be the ones to walk over him). In a "repressive milieu," Bart
is the anti-authority, he does everything his parents and teachers forbid him to do -- that's
just who he is, and that's all he is. In the absence of that milieu, Bart flounders and grasps
for someone to help define and create himself.
Bart may in fact represent the precariousness of our position in a post-Nietzschean
world. That is, according to Nietzsche we must go "beyond good and evil," and leave all
our metaphysical comforts behind: God, heaven, soul, a moral world order, and so on. But,
in abandoning another world, a beyond, we're in great danger of slipping into nihilism:
"The most extreme form of nihilism would be the view that every belief, every
considering-something-true, is necessarily false because there simply is no true world."30
He goes on to say: "One interpretation has collapsed; but because it was considered the
interpretation it now seems as if there were no meaning in existence, as if everything were
in vain."31 In other words, once we abandon any notion of some eternal and perfect beyond,
and are left with only the chaotic flux that is the world, we're in danger of falling into an
anything-goes nihilism, an intellectual and moral free-for-all. While the possibility of such
a thing terrified Nietzsche, it wasn't something he had to face. In his lifetime, the Western
world was still a very religious and oppressively moral place. Consequently, it made very
good sense -- and indeed, it was an act of great courage and foresight -- to act out the way
he did, to buck tradition, to rebuke the church. The last thing Nietzsche wanted to do was
create another religion, another eternal and absolute system, so, once he'd acted out, all he
could do was counsel his readers to invest their lives with meaning, to embrace the chaos
and make artworks out of their lives.
But what are we supposed to do, now that the dark blanket of nihilism has slipped
over us (and if you're not aware of it, trust me it has)? There's a thin fuzzy line between
continuing to act out, continuing to rebuke and destroy the old idols in an effort to forge a
new path, new values, on the one hand; and on the other hand immersing ourselves in the
nihilism, engaging in the intellectual and moral free-for-all, not taking anything seriously,
believing that, since there are no absolute values, nothing is of any real value. Bart, the boy
in the bright blue pants, may indeed represent this nihilistic danger. He has no (or few)
virtues; he has no creative spirit; he has accepted the chaos of existence, but not in such a
way as to form it and forge something beautiful out of it; he accepts and deals with it in a
sort of spirit of resignation. Nothing really means anything, so why not act out, why not do
what I feel like? He rejects, rebukes and reviles, not in an effort to destroy old,
life-slandering, life-denying and hollow idols, but really out of a lack of a solid identity, a
lack of any kind of complete self.
Comedy Becoming Conscious
Yes, sadly, in the end Bart may just be part and parcel of the decadence and
nihilism that pervades our era. And in that respect we might look upon him as a kind of
cautionary example: this is what Nietzsche was trying to warn us about. But, and to end on
a happier note, even though Bart isn't our Nietzschean hero and may be an example of
nihilistic decline, The Simpsons may as a whole be something more. Our lives and the
world are no less chaotic and absurd than they were for the ancient Greeks, and if, as
Nietzsche says, their comedy was a necessary "artistic discharge of the nausea of
absurdity,"32 then perhaps The Simpsons might serve that function for us as well. As a
social satire, a commentary on contemporary society, the show often achieves stunning
brilliance; it is often truly excellent, in the best Greek sense of the word. And it usually
achieves this excellence by taking the disparate elements of our chaotic American lives and
molding them together, giving them form, giving them style, forging them into something
meaningful and sometimes even beautiful. Even if it is only a cartoon.
1 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1974),
section 1, p. 74.
2 "Bart's Girlfriend."
3 Zarathustra is a fictional work, and thus the line is said by a fictional character, namely, a little old
woman who is advising the prophet Zarathustra. Consequently, it's not at all clear whether this represents
Nietzsche's own thinking, though he was known for saying some ridiculously awful things about women. On
the other hand, it's not even clear who the whip is for!
4 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1967),
section 4, p. 45.
5 Ibid., section 5, p. 52.
6 Ibid., section 4, p. 45.
7 Ibid., section 7, p. 60
8 Ibid., section 7, p. 60
9 Ibid., section 15, p. 95
10 Ibid., section 15, p. 97
11 Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, "Reason in Philosophy," from The Portable Nietzsche
(New York: Penguin, 1954), section 6, p.484.
12 Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, " 'Good and Evil', 'Good and Bad' " (New York:
Vintage, 1967), section 13, p. 45.
13 Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, "Reason in Philosophy," from The Portable Nietzsche,
section 5, p.483.
14 The Gay Science, section 107, p. 163.
15 The Will to Power, section 481, p. 267.
16 Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge: Harvard University Press), 1985,
p. 182.
17 The Gay Science, section 290, p. 232-3.
18 The Will to Power, section 371, p. 200.
19 Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature, p. 174.
20 Richard Schacht, Making Sense of Nietzsche, "Making Life Worth Living: Nietzsche on Art in
The Birth of Tragedy" (Urbana: University of Illinois Press), 1995, p. 133.
21 On the Genealogy of Morals, " 'Good and Evil', 'Good and Bad'," section 2, p. 26.
22 Ibid., section 10, p. 36-37. Nietzsche likes to use the French word, "ressentiment." For an
explanation, see Walter Kaufmann's Introduction to the Genealogy.
23 Ibid., section 13, p. 47.
24 Ibid., section 15, p. 48.
25 Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, "Why I Am a Destiny" (New York: Vintage, 1967), section 5, p.
330.
26 "The Curse of the Flying Hellfish."
27 "Radioactive Man."
28 "Sweet Seymour Skinner's Baadasssss Song."
29 "Bart's Inner Child."
30 The Will to Power, section 15, p. 14.
31 Ibid., section 55, p. 35.
32 The Birth of Tragedy, section 7, p. 60.
Part II
Simpsonian Themes
6
The Simpsons and Allusion
"Worst Essay Ever"
WILLIAM IRWIN and J.R. LOMBARDO
"A lot of talented writers work on the show, half of them Harvard geeks. And you know, when you
study the semiotics of Through the Looking Glass or watch every episode of Star Trek, you've got to
make it pay off, so you throw a lot of study references into whatever you do later in life." -- Matt
Groening
"We're really writing a show that has some of the most esoteric references on television. I mean
really, really, really, strange, odd, short little moments that very few people get and understand.
We're writing it for adults and intelligent adults at that." -- David Mirkin
"I hate quotations. Tell me what you know." -- Ralph Waldo Emerson
Matt Groening says: "The Simpsons is a show that rewards you for paying
attention." Any fan can confirm the creator's assertion, and, in fact, most true fans of The
Simpsons will tell you its episodes stand up to, and perhaps even demand, repeat viewing.
Thank God for reruns! Among the many reasons why fans continue to view and review The
Simpsons is the show's rich and clever use of allusion. From the venerable name of
"Homer" to Lisa's "Howl," to parodies of The Raven, Cape Fear, and All in the Family, The
Simpsons links itself to high culture and popular culture alike, weaving an intricate design,
making the show fit for repeat viewing and worthy of close attention.
What Is an Allusion?
The Simpsons is rife with satire, sarcasm, irony, and caricature. Often these stylistic
elements are linked to the use of allusion in The Simpsons, but, to be clear, they are not the
same as allusion. The Kennedyesque Quimby and the stereotypical Scot, Willie, are not
our direct concern here. Rather, we will train our focus on such references as the birds
reminiscent of The Birds and the "yabba dabba doo's" that link Springfield to Bedrock. By
definition, an allusion is an intended reference that calls for associations that go beyond
mere substitution of a referent.1 An ordinary reference allows us to easily substitute one
term or phrase for another. For example, "the author of Hamlet" refers to Shakespeare. An
allusion, however, calls for us to go beyond such substitution. For example, in "Lisa The
Simpson," in which Homer tries to show Lisa that the "Simpson gene" has not caused all
Simpsons to be dim-witted failures, one of Homer's relatives informs us that he runs an
"unsuccessful shrimp company." This is clearly intended as an allusion to Forrest Gump.
Notice, though, that we are not merely to substitute one term or phrase for another. Rather,
to really get the allusion, we must make additional associations. Gump, though mentally
challenged, runs the hugely successful Bubba Gump Shrimp Company ("It's a household
name"). The allusion suggests that the Simpson relative is so doltish and unlucky that he
cannot succeed in a business in which even the mentally challenged prosper.
The intent driving many allusions is for the audience to bring to mind certain things
and to let other connections flow freely. For example, the episode titled "The Day the
Violence Died" not only alludes to an allegorical and allusive Don Mclean dittie, but
includes "Amendment To Be," a parody of "I'm Just a Bill." In this case, not only is it
intended that we recognize that this cynical political commentary is poking fun at the sweet
and sincere Schoolhouse Rock classic, but we are to recall the pleasant memories and
sugared cereal highs of Saturday mornings long since gone. If there was any doubt about
this at the beginning of "Amendment To Be," it is quickly erased when Lisa explains to
Bart, "It's one of those crappy seventies throwbacks that appeals to Generation Xers."
Does an allusion have to be intended? Surely there are many connections that the
careful viewer can make in watching The Simpsons, and not all of these could have been
intended by the writers of the show. Such connections are not allusions, but rather
"accidental associations." They are "accidental" not in any negative sense, but in accord
with the etymology of 'accident'; they simply "happen" to be. The motivation for the
distinction between allusions and accidental associations is that it is at best inaccurate, and
at worst unethical, to attribute an association to a writer -- even a cartoon writer -- that he
did not intend. While it is often difficult to know with certainty if an association was
intended or not, clues such as context can make things clear. For example, when Homer
sings "I'm gonna make it after all," celebrating his success at his new job in the bowling
alley ("And Maggie Makes Three"), the writers intended the allusion to the "career girl" in
The Mary Tyler Moore Show. Not only is this a line from the show's opening theme song,
but Homer throws his bowling ball in the air, parodying the way Mary throws her hat in the
air in the show's opening sequence.
One way in which we can be sure that we have an accidental association, rather
than an allusion, is when it would be anachronistic to attribute a writer's intention to a
certain association. For example, in viewing reruns one might be tempted to see Marge's
short-lived career as real estate agent in "Realty Bites" as an allusion to Annette Benning's
character, Carolyn Burnham, in American Beauty. This, however, would be impossible,
given that the episode first aired in 1997 while the movie debuted in 1999. Obviously, one
cannot intend a reference to what does not yet exist. (The title "Realty Bites" is, however,
pretty clearly an allusion to the 1994 movie Reality Bites, and the episode also alludes to
elements of the movie GlenGarry Glen Ross.) Whatever connections or associations may
be drawn between the episode and American Beauty are the viewer's own, and are not
attributable to the writers. There may be inter-textual elements (as they are fashionably
called) which the writers did not actually intend, but which an ideal, or merely reasonable,
viewer notices, such as the contrast in the real estate sales techniques of Marge and Carolyn.
There is no harm in taking notice of these intertextual elements as long as we do not
incorrectly attribute them to the writers' intentions. They are, properly speaking, our
accidental associations. To take another example, the educated viewer cannot help but
think of the epic poet of Ancient Greece when he or she hears the name Homer. As it turns
out though, the character on The Simpsons is named after Matt Greening's father, just as the
other Simpsons are named after other Groenings. Still, one cannot help but suspect that
Groening intends for us to make the connection with the author of The Odyssey. After all,
this connection is much clearer and actually less esoteric, and it's deliciously ironic.
Mmmm. . . irony.
Consider another example. In watching reruns a viewer might mistakenly take
Otto's humming "Iron Man" in "Blood Feud" as an allusion to the signature chant of Beavis
and Butthead. Given that the episode originally aired in 1991 when Beavis and Butthead
had not yet (dis)graced the airwaves, this is impossible. Otto's choice of tunes is intended to
conjure up macabre images of the band who originally recorded the song, Black Sabbath,
and its erstwhile lead singer Ozzy Osbourne. One might suggest instead that Mike Judge,
the voice and creator of Beavis and Butthead, uses "Iron Man" to allude to Otto and The
Simpsons. Given the timeline this is possible, though improbable. More likely, any
connections the viewer makes between The Simpsons and Beavis and Butthead with regard
to Otto's rendition of "Iron Man" are accidental associations, and we should recognize
them as such rather than attribute them to the writers. The viewer has the right to be
creative in his viewing, but he must yield somewhat to what the writers give us.
Aesthetics of Allusion
Aesthetics is the branch of philosophy that studies the nature of the beautiful and
the pleasing, and includes the philosophical study of art. Why do we find aesthetic pleasure
in the allusions others make? Because, as audience members, we enjoy recognizing,
understanding, and appreciating allusions in a rather special way. The comprehension of an
allusion combines the pleasure we feel when we recognize something familiar, like a
favorite childhood toy, with the pleasure we feel when we know the right answer to the big
question on Jeopardy or Who Wants to be a Millionaire? We derive pleasure from
understanding allusions in a way we do not from understanding straightforward statements.
For example in the episode "Colonel Homer," in which Homer briefly manages the career
of country singer Lurleen Lumpkin, a boy on a porch plays the banjo tune from
Deliverance. This is a far more effective way of telling the audience that Homer has
entered a backward, redneck area than any straightforward statement could achieve. The
audience derives pleasure both from recognizing the significance of the banjo tune and
from recalling a favorite movie, asking themselves: Will Homer end up squealing like a
pig?
Audiences enjoy being involved in the creative process; they enjoy filling in the
blanks for themselves rather than being told everything. For example, in "A Streetcar
Named Marge," Maggie is placed in the "Ayn Rand School for Tots" where the proprietor,
Ms. Sinclair, reads The Fountainhead Diet. To understand why pacifiers are taken away
from Maggie and the other children one has to catch the allusion to the radical libertarian
philosophy of Ayn Rand. Recognizing and understanding this allusion yields much more
pleasure than would a straightforward explanation that Maggie has been placed in a
daycare facility in which tots are trained to fend for themselves, not to depend on others,
not even to depend on their pacifiers.
We also like allusions because of their game-like (ludic) quality. There is
something playful in making an allusion, and we are, in a sense, being invited to play in
considering an allusion. For example, in "Separate Vocations" Lisa becomes a
troublemaker at school when a career test suggests that her ideal line of work is that of a
homemaker.2 When Principal Skinner asks her, "What are you rebelling against?" the
audience anticipates her response, a la Brando in The Wild One, "Whattaya got?"
One of the most important aesthetic effects allusion can have is "the cultivation of
intimacy" and the forging of community.3 The clear advantage of making allusions that
draw on information that not everyone possesses is that they strengthen the connection
between the author and the audience. Author and audience become intimately connected;
they become, in effect, members of a club who know the "secret handshake." Such is the
case with the "Amendment to Be" allusion to Schoolhouse Rock. Similarly, the recurrent
allusions in The Simpsons to Hitchcock films such as The Birds, Rear Window, North by
Northwest, and Vertigo forge a bond between audience members (who recognize them)
and the writers of the show. Any reader of Ginsberg with a sense of humor could not help
but appreciate the writers' wit when they have Lisa utter, "I saw the best meals of my
generation destroyed by the madness of my brother / My soul carved in slices by
spikey-haired demons." Fans of classic television certainly find endearing the ubiquitous
allusions to, and parodies of, memorable Twilight Zone episodes. Those who cannot resist
watching The Graduate (any time they find it during a late night cable surf) feel a kinship
and bring forth a chuckle when Grandpa breaks up Mrs. Bouvier's wedding to Mr. Burns
by screaming from behind the glass of the church organist's booth ("Lady Bouvier's
Lover").
In the case of The Simpsons, perhaps nothing does more to cultivate intimacy and
forge community than allusions to past episodes. The Simpsons does not run a continuous
story line from one episode to the next, nor is it particularly linear in its storytelling within
a given TV season. Partly for this reason, the appearance of an object from a previous
episode has a real effect on the viewer. In "Natural Born Kissers" for example, Homer finds
a leaflet from the funeral of Frank Grimes in his sports jacket pocket. To the casual viewer
this appears incidental, but to the careful and faithful watcher, the leaflet recalls a favorite
episode featuring Homer's nemesis, Frank "Grimey" Grimes. The leaflet also comments on
Homer's typical attire, suggesting that the Grimes funeral, nearly one year ago in terms of
air dates, was probably the last time Homer wore that sports jacket. In "Mayored to the
Mob" Benjamin, Doug, and Gary, Homer's study buddies from "Homer Goes to College,"
dress as Mr. Spock for the Science Fiction Convention. This choice of costume alludes to
their nerdy tendencies, as revealed in the earlier episode, though the casual viewer would
just assume they were typical (nerdy) attendees at the convention. In "Viva Ned Flanders"
one of the Comic Book Guy's bumper stickers reads "Kang is My Co-pilot." This is what
we might call a "double allusion." The bumper sticker alludes to the alien who routinely
terrorizes the Simpson family in the "Treehouse of Horror" episodes, and The Simpsons
alien alludes to the Klingon captain of the same name from an episode of the original Star
Trek series.
There is, to be sure, a certain elitism and exclusion involved in the use of allusion.
To cultivate intimacy with some is, sometimes, to exclude others. Not all Simpsons viewers
will get the overt Ayn Rand allusions; fewer will get the more covert allusions to Ginsberg
and Kerouac; very few indeed will realize that Bart's vision of hell allusively makes use of
a Hieronymous Bosch painting ("Bart gets Hit by a Car"). Throughout the history of art and
literature (and now TV) some have understood cultural allusions while others have not, but
the growing numbers of those who do not understand is a problem we must face today. One
reason for the current problem is the lack of a substantial shared body of common
knowledge, what E.D. Hirsch, Jr. called "cultural literacy" in his acclaimed and defamed
bestseller, Cultural Literacy: What Every American Needs to Know. Cultural literacy is
essential for successful communication and comprehension, as is clear in considering
allusions. The cultural literacy presupposed by The Simpsons is not always, or even often,
highbrow, frequently relying on knowledge of earlier "classic" television shows. This has
the effect of excluding younger viewers who are not familiar with the likes of Yogi Bear,
Casper the Friendly Ghost, The Twilight Zone, Knight Rider, Dallas, Twin Peaks, The
Smurfs, I Love Lucy, Magilla Gorilla, That Girl, Bewitched, yada yada yada. This is a point
not lost on Homer Simpson, who bemoans the death of "pop-cultural literacy" as he berates
Bart for not knowing who Fonzie is. "Who's Fonzie? Don't they teach you anything in
school? He freed the squares"("Make Room for Lisa"). Ever the champion of pop-cultural
lore from the '70s and '80s, Homer is taken aback by the kid at the local record store when
he tells Homer that Hullabalooza is the greatest rock festival of all time. Homer's response?
There's only one great festival, The US Festival. It was sponsored by the guy from Apple
Computer. The Kid's response? What computer? Hirsch readily admits that cultural
literacy is an ever-changing phenomenon, and any list detailing it will be descriptive not
prescriptive. Still, I don't think he'd go as far as Homer in adding "Fonzie" and the US
Festival to the list of "What Every American Needs to Know," though perhaps Apple
Computer still stands a chance.
One way in which The Simpsons' use of allusion is aesthetically successful is that it
is generally not disruptive. The writers recognize that not everyone will catch all the
allusions, and so they craft them in such a way that the allusions enhance our enjoyment if
they are caught, but do not detract from the enjoyment of the show if they are missed. The
finely blended texture of the allusions in The Simpsons allows both the old and young,
sophisticated and naïve, educated and ignorant, to enjoy the same show. In fact, the true
test of the comic and aesthetic success of The Simpsons' use of allusion is to watch the
show alongside a child. If the child laughs at an obscure allusion, we know it's because of
the humor and not because he has "gotten it." The blending has succeeded. For example in
"Trash of the Titans" the band plays a brief flare from the Sanford and Son theme-song as
Homer is ousted and Sanitation Commissioner Patterson is reinstated. If one does not
recognize the musical allusion to Sanford and Son, one can still salvage an understanding.
In fact, part of the beauty of the allusion is that it blends into the scene perfectly well; it can
slide by without being understood, perhaps just taken as funny-sounding music, without
causing the feeling that one has missed something. Similarly, in "Lisa's Wedding," an
episode that looks into the future, a Jetsons motif comes into play. Homer wears a white
shirt like that of the "futuristic" George Jetson, and Jetsons sound effects are sprinkled
liberally throughout. Again, these allusions blend perfectly well, bringing pleasure to those
who recognize them without drawing attention to themselves and raising questions for
those who miss them. The same is true of allusions to high culture, such as the Pretzel
Man's parody of Tom Joad's famous speech in The Grapes of Wrath. As the Pretzel Man
tells Marge, "Wherever a young mother is ignorant of what to feed her baby you'll be there.
Wherever nacho penetration is less than total you'll be there. Whenever a Bavarian is not
quite full, you will be there" ("The Twisted World of Marge Simpson"). Again, the allusion
to Steinbeck's The Grapes of Wrath brings pleasure to those who recognize it, but goes
unnoticed and causes no disruption to those unequipped to get it. Perhaps some astute
viewers will realize, in this case or others, that an allusion is being made although they do
not know to what it refers. Still, this does not have the effect of making the viewer feel lost.
Rather the viewer may chuckle, realizing that something funny is going on even though he
can't fully appreciate it. The same blended texture can be found in more comprehensive
allusions, parodies that span an entire episode or segment, such as "The Shinning," "The
Raven," and "Bart of Darkness" (the title of which plays on a Conrad novel while the plot
of the episode parodies Hitchcock's Rear Window).
What's the Connection?
Allusions have a practical value in addition to, and beyond, their aesthetic value.
The practical value of allusions is found in their ability to provide links to other works of
art. Such links in turn provide a context and a tradition in which a work of art is to be
interpreted. Whereas philosophers deal with their predecessors or contemporaries by
criticizing their arguments and offering new, and hopefully better, arguments, artists tend
to allude to their predecessors or contemporaries. Artists use allusions in this way to pay
homage, parody,4 mock, and surpass.
We would not ordinarily expect the writers of a cartoon to employ allusion for the
purpose of linking their art and creating a context, but The Simpsons is no ordinary cartoon.
What context and tradition do the writers of The Simpsons attempt to dictate through their
use of allusion? Let's briefly consider the lists of artworks to which they allude.
The list of movies alluded to in The Simpsons includes, but is not limited to, the
following: 101 Dalmatians, 2001: A Space Odyssey, Alien, The Amityville Horror,
Apocalypse Now, Backdraft, Basic Instinct, Ben Hur, Big, The Birds, The Bodyguard,
Cape Fear, Chariots of Fire, Citizen Kane, Close Encounters of the 3rd Kind, A Clockwork
Orange, Cocktail, The Deer Hunter, Deliverance, Dr. Strangelove, Dracula, E. T., The
Exorcist, Fear and Loathing in Las Vegas, The Fly, Forrest Gump, Frankenstein, Full
Metal Jacket, The Godfather, Godzilla, Gone with the Wind, Goodfellas, The Graduate,
It's a Wonderful Life, Jaws, The Jazz Singer, Jumanji, Jurassic Park, King Kong, Lawrence
of Arabia, Mary Poppins, Midnight Express, Miracle on 34th St., The Natural, Night of the
Living Dead, A Nightmare on Elm Street, North by Northwest, An Officer and a Gentleman,
One Flew over the Cuckoo's Nest, Patton, Pink Flamingoes, Planet of the Apes, Pride of
the Yankees, Psycho, Pulp Fiction, Raiders of the Lost Ark, Rain Man, Rear Window, The
Right Stuff, Risky Business, Rocky, Rocky Horror Picture Show, Rudy, The Shining, The
Silence of the Lambs, Soylent Green, Speed, Star Wars, Steamboat Willie, Terminator,
Titanic, Treasure of the Sierra Madre, Vertigo, Village of the Damned, Waterworld, The
Wild One, and The Wizard ofOz.
The list of television shows alluded to in The Simpsons includes, but is not limited
to, the following: All in the Family, Batman, Beavis and Butthead, Bewitched, Bonanza,
Casper the Friendly Ghost, A Charlie Brown Christmas, Cheers, The Cosby Show, Dallas,
Davey and Goliath, Dennis the Menace, Doctor Who, Fish, The Flintstones, The Fugitive,
Futurama, Gilligan's Island, Happy Days, Hekyll and Jekyll, Home Improvement, Howdy
Doody, I Love Lucy, In Search Of, The Jeffersons, The Jetsons, Knight Rider, Lassie,
Laverne and Shirley, The Little Rascals, Mad about You, Magilla Gorilla, The Mary Tyler
Moore Show, Popeye, The Prisoner, Ren and Stimpy, Rhoda, The Ropers, Schoolhouse
Rock, The Smurfs, Star Trek, That Girl, That '70s Show, Twin Peaks, The Twilight Zone,
The Wonder Years, The X Files, Xena, Warrior Princess, and Yogi Bear.
The list of authors and works of literature alluded to in The Simpsons includes, but
is not limited to, the following: The Bible, Castaneda, Dickens's A Christmas Carol,
Ginsberg's "Howl, " Golding's Lord of the Flies, Hemingway's The Old Man and the Sea,
Homer's Odyssey, Kerouac, Melville's Moby-Dick, Michener, Poe's Telltale Heart, The
Raven, and The Fall of the House of Usher, Ayn Rand's The Fountainhead, Shakespeare,
Steinbeck's The Grapes of Wrath, and Tennessee Williams's A Streetcar Named Desire.
The first thing to notice about these lists is that the writers of The Simpsons do not
limit their allusions to the genre of cartoons or even the medium of television. There are
ample allusions to film and literature. Though less common, we could also note allusions to
paintings such as "The Kentuckian" and musical happenings such as "USA for Africa."
The second thing to notice is that the allusions are overwhelmingly, though not exclusively,
to American art works, both cultural and pop-cultural. This seems fitting given that
Springfield (the town without a state) is likely meant to represent America itself.
The allusions in The Simpsons are very "American" in one rather unflattering way,
pointing to America as a fast-food society in which the masses don't like to "think too
much." In many, though certainly not all, cases the allusions are very plainly stated or
shown to the viewer. Songs such as "The End" or "Hot Blooded" are nods to other forms of
popular art and do not demand any great effort or esoteric knowledge on the part of the
viewer, who simply must acknowledge the allusion and register the thought. The Simpsons
often uses real people or fictional characters, such as Ron Howard, Dennis the Menace, or
The Red Hot Chili Peppers. Frequently the use of these people constitutes an allusion
because of double layers; the viewer must know why the person or situation is funny in
addition to the mere fact that they are in the scene. For example, David Crosby has given
voice to his cartoon likeness in a number of episodes, most often in the context of some
rehabilitative or self-help role, such as a 12-step meeting of an "anonymous" group. We're
left with the questions: Do Americans like, or (worse) need, such "no-brainers"? Are all the
pop-cultural allusions a sign of American decay? Do they represent the immolation of
Hirsch's cultural literacy, with only a nihilistic pop-cultural literacy to rise from the ashes?
No, it's probably not meant to be all that grim. Consider that many baby boomers
and Generation-Xers had their first exposure to classical music through Bugs Bunny
cartoons, only to mature into a taste for Bach and Beethoven. The straightforward allusions
and combination of pop-culture and high culture need not signal "the closing of the
American mind." Such a death knell would only be sounded if a generation of Americans
never moved beyond The Simpsons in their aesthetic appreciation. There is no "clear and
present danger" of that. In fact, both The Simpsons and this book serve their purpose best
when they prompt their audience to consider cultural, aesthetic, and philosophical issues
whose surface the show only scratches.
Getting the Joke
Perhaps you think we've made "much Apu about nothing" in this discussion of
allusion. If so, you can count Homer on your side. "Oh Marge, cartoons don't have any
deep meaning. They're just stupid drawings that give you a cheap laugh" ("Mr. Lisa Goes
to Washington"). We prefer to side with Matt Groening, though, who says, "That's one of
the great things about The Simpsons -- if you have read a few books, you'll get more of the
jokes."5 In the end all we can ask is that you take this essay and this book as seriously as
you would a Simpsons episode.6
1We cannot present a theoretical defense of this definition here, but for a fuller discussion and
defense of this definition see William Irwin's article "What is an Allusion?" in The Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, forthcoming 2001.
2 For further discussion of this episode see Chapter 9 of this volume.
3 See Ted Cohen, Jokes: Philosophical Thoughts on Joking Matters (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1999), p. 29.
4 For further discussion of parody in particular see Chapter 7 of this volume.
5 http://www.snpp.com/other/interviews/groeining99e.html
6 We wish to thank the following folks for their help with this essay: Mark Conard, Raja Halwani,
Megan Lloyd, Jennifer O'Neill, David Weberman, Sarah Worth, and Joe Zeccardi.
7
Popular Parody:
The Simpsons Meets the Crime Film
DEBORAH KNIGHT
In this essay, rather than drawing on the corpus of episodes that make up The
Simpsons to establish general philosophical points, I want to work in the other direction by
looking at a particular episode of The Simpsons. My focus is on parody, in particular on the
strategies of parody that characterize popular rather than "High Art" narratives.1 The topic
of parody has obvious affinities to allusion. Irwin and Lombardo make the pertinent
observation that for something to be an allusion rather than an "accidental association," it
must be intended by the makers of the fiction -- usually, for the purposes of The Simpsons,
allusions must be intended by the writers.2 Parody operates the same way -- unintended
references are at best accidental. The Simpsons cites numerous American television series
and films, and makes these citations in a variety of ways. What I'm particularly interested
in is a specific way of citing and also using a recognizable narrative genre. My focus is the
crime film and the episode in question is "Bart the Murderer." But my point is applicable to
any episode of The Simpsons that uses the same strategies we find in "Bart the Murderer."
"Bart the Murderer"
You will remember how this episode goes. Bart wakes up singing and struts
confidently downstairs, thinking he's in for a great day. But things go downhill quickly.
First, Homer has stolen the police badge from Bart's box of cereal. Then Bart misses the
school bus. Sunny weather turns to thunderstorms as he makes his way to school -- only to
clear up the minute he gets there. He has to fill out a tardy slip. And if all that weren't bad
enough, he's forgotten his permission slip for the afternoon fieldtrip to the chocolate
factory. He gets to watch his classmates pour themselves into the bus, and winds up licking
PTA envelopes for Principal Skinner, who counsels Bart to "make a game of it" by
counting how many envelopes he can lick in an hour and then try to beat that number the
next hour. Bart calls it a "crappy game," and of course he's right. Gummy tongued, he
skateboards home, again in a rainstorm. But things still haven't stopped going wrong: he
falls off his skateboard and down a flight of stairs. "What now?" he despairs. That question
is quickly answered as a dozen handguns are pointed at him.
Bad as Bart's luck has been all day, this is the unluckiest turn of all. He has landed
outside a gangster hangout run by mob boss Fat Tony (Joe Mantegna) and his
trigger-happy henchmen. But all is not lost. Fat Tony, who likes to bet on the ponies, sets
Bart an initiation test. When asked which horse will win the third race, Bart replies, "Don't
have a cow." Sure enough, Don't Have a Cow is first to the wire, and Fat Tony's bet pays
off. Fat Tony starts to think that Bart might be lucky after all -- rather than just plain
mouthy. So Bart is set a second test. Seems the club is short its barkeep, and Fat Tony
wants to know if Bart can mix a Manhattan. Nervously, Bart manages it, and this secures
him entry into the mob "family." His career as a mob bartender seems to be going well -- if
you overlook the fact that he turns his bedroom into a storehouse for a stolen truck's worth
of cigarettes, begins to affect annoying mob mannerisms such as tucking money into
people's pockets for favors he thinks they owe him, and starts to dress like a junior member
of the Rat Pack after Fat Tony rewards him with a fancy suit. But when Principal Skinner
keeps Bart after school for trying to bribe him, Bart is late for work at Fat Tony's club, and
this is a problem, since Fat Tony has promised an antagonistic mob boss a superb
Manhattan -- only Bart isn't there to mix it. As the other mob boss leaves, he gives Fat Tony
the "kiss of death" as only mob bosses can do ("Just what I need!" says Fat Tony). And this
all because Bart was late for work. Bart finally arrives saying Principal Skinner kept him
after school for detention, and Fat Tony takes it into his head to go and talk with Skinner.
Skinner is soon confronted in his office by "tall men" who don't have an appointment.
(Skinner wants to know how they got past the hall monitor.)
When Skinner unexpectedly goes missing, Bart is the focus of police attention. In
fact, he is put on trial for Skinner's murder. At the trial, everyone turns on Bart: Homer
confesses on the stand that the evidence points to Bart. Fat Tony insists that Bart is the real
capo of the organization. Things would have been bleak indeed except for Skinner's
miraculous reappearance. Skinner explains how he came to be trapped for days under a pile
of newspapers in his garage -- keeping his mind agile by playing with a basketball,
counting the number of times he could bounce it in a day and then, the next day, looking to
beat his own score. The case against Bart is dismissed. On the courthouse steps, Bart
announces to Fat Tony what he has learned: that "crime doesn't pay." Tony agrees, before
getting into the first of a fleet of limousines that take him and his henchmen away. The
Simpson family is reunited.
Parody and Popular Narratives
As Thomas J. Roberts argues in An Aesthetics of Junk Fiction,3 it is characteristic of
popular fictions -- junk fictions, as Roberts affectionately calls them -- to be replete with
references to their own contemporary culture. Popular fictions establish connections with
their readers and viewers, Roberts argues, because of their frequent citations of familiar or
at least recognizable extra-textual people, events, and objects. For instance, popular
fictions refer to makes of cars and guns, to songs, movies and television shows, to public
figures such as movie or rock stars, sports stars and politicians, to clothes and makeup, to
major news stories, to types of technology. These references can involve something as
straightforward as naming or depicting, or they can be as subtle as some of the associative
allusions Irwin and Lombardo describe. Given the speed at which cars, movies, stars,
fashion, and technologies change -- and recognizing how many of them simply drop out of
memory -- even a generation or two later the references a contemporary audience would
have immediately recognized can become opaque. One notable thing that happens when a
work of junk fiction changes status from popular to classic is that our attention shifts from
immediate recognition of these extratextual references to other matters, for instance to such
literary critical matters as form and theme. This shift actually naturalizes our own cultural
forgetfulness. Let's just consider a few examples. Who remembers teen idols of the
seventies such as Bobby Sherman and Leif Garrett? If asked about the Barracuda, would
you think first of the make of automobile or the character on Frasier? One of the defining
features of junk fiction is its constant referencing of what often turn out to be culturally
(and technologically) transient entities. The likelihood of being able to recognize this sort
of specific reference cannot be reliably predicted outside of the immediate temporal
framework that indexes the reference's intended audience. Homer Simpson himself makes
this point when he realizes that Bart doesn't know who The Fonz was, as Irwin and
Lombardo remind us.
The Simpsons is of course chock full of these sorts of references to contemporary
culture. To mention only one from the episode in question: at breakfast as Bart is hunting
through his cereal box for the police badge, we see that Lisa's breakfast cereal is called
"Jackie-Os." I probably don't have to spell out that this cereal exploits the name given to
Jacqueline Kennedy Onassis by the popular press -- and even the popular press recognized
Jackie O as a woman of distinctive beauty not to mention remarkable connections, power,
and influence. Nor do I need to mention that Jackie-Os also allude to Cheerios, the cereal
probably best known for its dependable focus on good health, and correlatively noteworthy
for its announced lack of sugar, frosting, flavor or, for that matter, any sort of cereal
pizzazz. One day not long from now we may well have to explain both who Jackie O was,
and what Cheerios were. What needs emphasis here, however, is that there is no single
attitude that The Simpsons adopts to the extratextual cultural references it cites. On the face
of it, we can't isolate exactly what sort of attitude motivates the reference to Jackie O. Nor
can we even be certain that the reference to Jackie O is intended as anything more than a
fortuitous sound-alike for other breakfast cereals whose names end in "o."
There is, however, another sort of referencing that needs to be considered when
thinking about, for instance, "Bart the Murderer." Many episodes of The Simpsons
including "Bart the Murderer" refer to recognizable cinema and television genres. We can
call this generic referencing. Not all of the references to cinema and television in The
Simpsons are of the same order, and in particular not all suggest a single attitude toward the
genres referenced. In another episode, Apu is trying to get Homer and his family to watch
an Indian film on television. Apu is merely trying to share his culture with Homer and
Marge, though as one might have anticipated he has little success. Homer can only see the
visible differences between the conventions of this Indian film and the sorts of films he is
used to, that is, American films. The best Homer can do is laugh himself silly because he
thinks the Indian costumes are ridiculous. One of the wonderful references built into this
scene as something of a throw-away line is Apu's assurance to Homer and Marge that this
film made it into the "Top 400" list of Indian films.
One way to access this joke, although I think it is a wrong way, is to suppose that
Indian cinema cannot make sensible discriminations between its films and thus overpraises
all of them by including them in such an enormously long list. Another way to access the
joke, again a wrong one, is to think that Apu's remark is simply an exaggeration -- here the
humor would be found by thinking that there are only a few if any "Top" Indian films. The
right way to access the joke, by contrast, involves knowing that the Indian cinema is one of
the most productive and vibrant among the world cinemas. It has one of the highest outputs
of any national cinema, outproducing by far the American cinema. This makes the idea of a
"Top 400" more understandable, since the enormous pool of Indian films explains the shift
from a more usual idea of a "Top 10" or a "Top 100" to something much larger, for instance,
a "Top 400." Here the joke works for those viewers who know something about Indian
cinema. To know something about Indian cinema would tend to align viewers with Apu,
and if we share that affinity, then we will empathize with him and not with Homer's crude
response. Of course, there is no way to ensure that this interpretation of the joke is the one
viewers recognize. Here we have a familiar problem in the hermeneutics of narrative: to
feel an affinity with Homer is certainly possible, but to do so really means that you are in
the wrong hermeneutic circle.
I will call this reference to Indian cinema and others that work like it extrinsic
references. They are extrinsic in the sense that the reference originates from and points
back to something outside the narrative. It references but does not embody in the narrative
aspects of the cinematic practices it alludes to. So the reference to the Indian cinema is
comparable to the reference to Jackie Onassis in the cereal name. Both get their meaning
because they are extratextual. "Bart the Murderer," by contrast, engages in intrinsic
reference: it references by means of incorporating specific generic patterns into the very
story that makes the allusion. The genre in question is the crime film. "Bart the Murderer"
allows us to think about the more general contribution of The Simpsons to such things as
generic development and transformation, parody, and homage. It also allows us to think
about one of the central thematics of the crime film: the family. There are different sorts of
crime films -- and there are even different sorts of crime films that focus on the figure of the
gangster. Donnie Brasco (Mike Newell, 1997), for example, follows an undercover cop
(Johnny Depp) as he infiltrates a group of mobsters by befriending one of its weaker
members (Al Pacino). But Donnie Brasco is best looked at as an undercover crime thriller
with a gang setting. By contrast, an important subgenre of the crime film running from the
1930s to the present focuses on the rise and fall of the gangster. A central dynamic of such
gangster films is the contrast they draw between the ordinary American family and the
crime family. This subgenre informs "Bart the Murderer." The thematic contrast between
ordinary American family and crime family is made more arresting in this episode since it
is the Simpsons themselves who fill the role of the "ordinary American family."
The Family and Popular Genres
Among popular Hollywood film genres, only two are primarily defined by their
focus on the family. One, the family melodrama, is standardly thought of as a "woman's"
genre -- also known as "weepies" because of their ability to reduce audiences to tears.
Family melodramas such as Stella Dallas (King Vidor, 1937), Mildred Pierce (Michael
Curtiz, 1945) and Imitation of Life (Douglas Sirk, 1958) focus on an incomplete nuclear
family, usually headed by a single mother who is seen to be in need of a husband. From the
1930s through the 1950s, in particular, a frequent theme of these films was the tension
between being a mother and being the head of the household. The central characters of two
of the three films just named pursue successful professional careers, and it is their success
in the public sphere that threatens the stability of their families and causes problems in their
relationships with men, whether husbands or lovers. The other family-centered Hollywood
film genre is, ironically, the gangster film. Classics include The Public Enemy (William
Wellman, 1931), The Godfather (Francis Ford Coppola, 1971, 1974, 1990), and
Goodfellas (Martin Scorsese, 1990). In the women-centered family melodramas, the
family is held up for the most part as the basic social unit, dependent upon both mother and
father figures, good relationships between parents and their children, and the inculcation of
social values. In family melodrama, loyalty is ideally centrifugal, moving outward from the
couple to their family and from there to the community. The gangster film offers an inverse
vision of the family, one in which women characters are marginalized, usually reduced to
such roles as trophy wife or mistress. The value systems of gangster films also invert those
of the family melodramas. The gangsters' values never benefit the broader community but
instead only support and preserve the criminal microcosm. In the crime film, loyalty is
radically centripetal, turned in on the crime family and most importantly directed to the
mob boss. As Robert DeNiro's character says in Goodfellas, in the mob there are two rules:
don't tell anyone anything and always keep your mouth shut.
The generic referencing of "Bart the Murderer" turns our attention toward the
gangster film, away from the family melodrama. What is the relationship, then, between
The Simpsons and these two genres? Let's look first at The Simpsons. Clearly, it is closer in
structure and format to the family sit-com than to either the family melodrama or the crime
film. In fact, it is part of the tradition of critical family sit-coms focusing on the
working-class rather than the middle-class, and featuring ongoing disputes between family
members as a primary mechanism of plot construction. This puts The Simpsons in the line
of television situation comedies running from All in the Family to Roseanne. And it
distinguishes these three programs and related family sitcoms from family-centered
television dramas, for instance The Waltons, Little House on the Prairie, and,
paradigmatically, Family, all of which incline more toward the overtly melodramatic than
the sit-coms do. Still, the family sit-com does have recognizable affinities with the family
melodrama, since it is precisely the struggles of the family that are centermost in both cases.
We might think of the family sit-com as a transformation of fifties-style family
melodramas brought about through the new conventions and formats of sixties and
post-sixties television.
We can say, then, that the connection between The Simpsons and the family
melodrama is neither intrinsic nor extrinsic, but rather one of historical inheritance and
variation on the thematics of the family. The relationship of "Bart the Murderer" to the
crime film, however, is intrinsic rather than extrinsic, since in "Bart the Murderer," the
crime film isn't simply extrinsicly referenced; it is incorporated as part of the narrative
structure of the episode. "Bart the Murderer" can be thought of as a combination of parody
and homage to the crime film, as in fact The Simpsons itself is a combination of parody and
homage to the family sitcom. Which leads us to consider how parody operates here.
Art Parody and Popular Parody
We are considering parody in a popular context. How exactly does popular parody
square with theories of parody? Let us look at Linda Hutcheon's theory. Art parody --
which Hutcheon calls, simply, "parody" -- is "a sophisticated genre in the demands it
makes on its practitioners and its interpreters."4 Parody describes a relationship between
two texts: the parodic text itself and the parodied or target text. For Hutcheon, parody is a
self-conscious, indeed a self-reflexive, practice, one that involves the intention of the artist
or author in the encoding, and the interpretive activity of the audience in decoding. The
intention of the artist is necessary because parody involves "repetition with difference" --
repetition denoting the acknowledgement of historical precedents in the artworld, and
difference marking the shifts, variations or ironic examination to which that historical
precedent is subjected (p. 101). The interpretive activity of the audience is likewise
necessary to recognize the target text and thus to work out the relationship between the
parodic and the parodied.
Hutcheon wants to distinguish parody from a range of artistic and literary practices
with which it has often been confused, among them "burlesque, travesty, pastiche,
plagiarism, quotation, and allusion" (p. 43). Nevertheless, her account pertains primarily to
modernist and postmodernist "High Art" practices. Perhaps her favorite example is
Magritte's parody of Manet's parody of Goya's Majas on a Balcony. In fact, this example
raises the question of just what counts as parody and when, and it actually doesn't provide
an easy answer. What, we might ask, is the critical advantage of treating Manet's Le Balcon
as a parody? Did it, perhaps, only become one after Magritte painted Perspective: Le
Balcon de Manet? When not referring to the tradition of oil painting, Hutcheon focuses on
the masterworks of the European novel such as Proust's allegedly parodic relationship to
Flaubert. Film parodies do get a mention, for instance Brian DePalma's reworking of
Hitchcock's Psycho (1960) in his Dressed to Kill (1980) and of Michelangelo Antonioni's
Blow-Up (1966) in Blow-Out (1981). But little is said about just how much an audience
needs to know about the target texts here in order to understand De Palma's films. Arguably,
Psycho is such a classic of Hollywood cinema that it would be hard to imagine audiences
not seeing the connection. But Blow-Up, also a masterpiece, is not nearly as popular as
Psycho, and thus isn't as well-known, and it strikes me that knowledge of the target text in
this case is only a distraction from the plot of Blow-Out, whose audiences are certainly
more familiar with John Travolta's previous roles than with Antonioni's film.
While Hutcheon does periodically mention popular rather than canonical artworks,
there are obvious problems with her account. For starters, a parodic text need not parody
some particular canonical artwork. Indeed, it need not parody an artwork at all: it can just
as easily parody the recognizable conventions of a narrative genre. Second, parodic texts
need not refer to so-called "High" artworks -- consider Roy Lichtenstein's parodies of
cartoons. Nor need the parodic text itself qualify as "High" art: witness this and related
episodes of The Simpsons. Hutcheon would probably agree with me about these latter two
points, but it is worth emphasizing that even her selection of mass artworks (in this case,
films) focuses on target texts which are recognized as masterpieces by admired auteurs.
Perhaps the most telling problem with Hutcheon's account, though, is her
privileging of irony: "Ironic inversion is a characteristic of all parody" (p. 6). This move
owes much to the centrality of irony among literary values which we find in most critical
practices from the New Critics to the present. Irony grounds Hutcheon's notion that parody
"marks the intersection of. . . invention and critique," since irony is understood to have an
inherently critical function (101). But this takes irony for granted as a mark of literary
seriousness, and anything that seeks out seriousness as a criterion of aesthetic merit can be
traced back to "High Art" critical traditions. Not surprisingly, then, Hutcheon approvingly
quotes Robert Burden's observation5 that parody "is created to interrogate itself against
significant precedents; it is a serious mode" (Hutcheon, p. 101; Burden, p. 136; emphasis
added). Clearly, Hutcheon is right to insist that parody does not exhaust itself by merely
mocking or ridiculing the target text. But she is too quick to dismiss Margaret Rose's notion
that parody is "the critical quotation of a preformed literary language with comic effect" (p.
41). Understanding Rose to mean something like literary forms, conventions, narrative
structures and so forth when she says "language," the acknowledgement of the comic rather
than paradigmatically ironic effect achieved by parodic texts is an important corrective to
Hutcheon's account.
In what sense, then, is "Bart the Murderer" an example of parody? Arguably it isn't
art parody. The episode seems to exploit the comic rather than the ironic. It doesn't set itself
the task of interrogating significant precedents. "Bart the Murderer" is simply not critical in
the sense beloved by critical theorists. Does this mean that the intrinsic referencing we find
in "Bart the Murderer" isn't parody after all? The answer, I suggest, is that this episode is an
example of popular parody, and its primary attitude isn't one of criticism but rather one of
homage. In parodic homage, the intention is to rework a loved and well-known text or
narrative form. We can see this sort of homage at work, for instance, in Clueless (Amy
Heckerling, 1995), among whose range of intrinsic references we cannot fail to note Jane
Austen's Emma -- a point that is not affected by the fact that much of the film's comedy
depends on extrinsic references to fashion, the media, and popular culture. If Clueless
ascends to the status of a classic, Cher's tendency to describe cute guys as Baldwins may
need explanation if the Baldwin brothers are forgotten. One hopes that a similar reminder
will not be necessary with respect to Emma. There are other parody-homages, of course.
Charade (Stanley Donen, 1963) and other suspense-comedies of the sixties are
parody-homages to the great Hitchcock suspense-comedies, notably North By Northwest
(1959). Many Woody Allen films are parody-homages. De Palma's films also count.
Whereas Hutcheon claims that art parody involves using irony to create a critical distance
between the parodic text and its target, this objective seems largely absent in Clueless and
Charade, just as it is largely absent from "Bart the Murderer."
Back to "Bart the Murderer"
The primary target of "Bart the Murderer" is Scorcese's brilliant Goodfellas,
starring Ray Liotta, Robert De Niro, and Joe Pesci.6 But Goodfellas is an instance of the
gangster genre, and as such the conventions that make the genre what it is, and the key
films that make up the genre, are also targets. Viewers approach Goodfellas with some
knowledge of the gangster genre, and this generic knowledge is what allows them to
understand the situation and actions of the characters involved. There is a generic
verisimilitude at work in any genre. This is what makes it reasonable for characters to
break into song in musicals, action heros to survive when outnumbered a dozen to one by
bad guys with far superior fire power, and everyone to realize that, after Wile E. Coyote
falls (again!) to the bottom of the canyon, in the next scene he will be unboxing a package
from Acme Inc. to help him catch the Roadrunner. Some of the features of the gangster
film that contribute to its generic verisimilitude include the evident ethnicity of the
gangsters (Irish Americans, Italian Americans, and so on), the principal settings in bars,
casinos, and anywhere that promotes drinking, smoking, and gambling, the characteristic
and illegal money-making enterprises, the tight-knit group of men who flaunt guns and
serve their boss. It takes the episode of "Bart the Murderer" some time to arrive in the
gangster world, but as soon as Bart falls into the hands of Fat Tony's men, we find all these
features of the gangster film present.
A recurrent thematic feature of the gangster film, which we see in the figure of
James Cagney in The Public Enemy as well as in Ray Liotta's character in Goodfellas, is
the impressionable youth who is taken into the mob and slowly ascends to positions of
greater trust and importance, adapting to the dynamics of the new mob family and turning
against his own. The narrative trajectory of the gangster film is a paradoxical one: ascent
within the power structure of the crime family corresponds to descent into the morally
twisted mobsters' world. This peculiar conjunction of ascent and descent makes sense, of
course, because the gangster isn't a hero but rather an anti-hero. And the values that
dominate the mobsters' world are themselves an inversion of those usually associated with
the American Dream. If the American Dream is the myth that everyone can make it in
America by hard work and the right connections, then the mobsters' world is exactly that
myth inflected by corruption, excess, violence, and an out-of-balance ethic of masculinity
as brute power and greed. The basic story structure featuring an anti-hero or villain
involves a series of increasing successes -- here understood as the gangster's slow but
steady rise in power, position, wealth, and material accessories -- that nevertheless bring
about a precipitating event which "makes inevitable a failure followed by punishment."7
Thus The Public Enemy ends with Cagney's death -- fitting punishment for his life of crime.
The ending of Goodfellas is rather different. Henry Hill's fate is sealed when he turns state's
evidence. But unlike Cagney, he doesn't die. His punishment is worse than death; in fact,
he sees it as a living death. Hill is forced to return to anonymous middle-class life in
anonymous middle America. No more big money, no more flashy clothes or fast cars or
hanging with the rich and powerful in casinos and night clubs, no more easy women, no
more influence: just a normal suburban house in an average suburban neighborhood.
Punishment indeed.
Bart follows the path of ascent in the mob world as evidenced by his job, the cash
he keeps receiving, the fancy suit, and the way the other mobsters, especially Fat Tony,
come to rely on him. This series of successes leads to the inevitable failure -- his arrest in
the alleged murder of Principal Skinner. But "Bart the Murderer" is a selective parody of
the gangster genre, which is pretty much what we ought to expect from a cartoon comedy.
What is most obviously missing is the excess of violence which is a hallmark of the genre
targets and embodied by all gangster protagonists from Cagney to Liotta. Also missing is
the sense of corruption of values. Yes, Bart gets a bit above himself when he calls Principal
Skinner, "My man," and stuffs cash into his pocket. Still, this sort of cheekiness is not
atypical of Bart. A more important contrast is that, unlike The Public Enemy and
Goodfellas, there is no epic timeframe. The classic gangster films develop over years,
charting the "good life" which our anti-hero enjoys before his downfall. Since no one ever
ages in The Simpsons, this option is plainly unavailable.
Although the parody is selective, "Bart the Murderer" does exploit the idea of
punishment we found in Goodfellas. Just as Liotta's character, Henry Hill, has to go back to
the very way of life he had tried to escape, so too does Bart wind up having to return to his
normal life. That means returning from the mob family to his own.
The gangster as anti-hero has always longed at best to be able to do a better job of
providing for the family than his father was able to do, or at worst to get away from his
natural family, neighborhood, and class altogether. In gangster films, the protagonist's
family is either naive or uninterested. Either way, they don't fully understand just what sort
of company their son has gotten himself involved with. Marge's and Homer's reactions to
Bart's new situation are in this sense classic. Although Marge frets about Bart's changes in
behavior, both Marge and Homer agree that it's good for a boy to have a part-time job.
Marge's anxieties aren't wholly allayed, however, and she persuades Homer to go check
out Bart's place of work. Homer, oblivious to all the signs, is allowed to win at poker and
concludes that everything is fine. In short, Homer and Marge exert very little positive
influence over Bart during his brief career in the mob.
What does it mean for Bart to return to his family after charges against him are
dismissed? There are two ways of answering this question, and which you choose depends
upon whether or not you think that the conclusion of "Bart the Murderer" is ironic. If you
don't think that irony is involved, then the selectivity of the parody just means that, since
nothing fundamental ever changes in cartoon comedies such as The Simpsons, it's simply
inevitable that the end of the episode returns Bart to the situation in which he started out. If
you think that irony is involved, then despite the selectivity of the parody, this conclusion
is a critical observation about the limits of the family structure in which Bart finds himself.
If Ray Liotta's punishment is to return to "normal" -- that is, "average" -- American life, we
might want to think about Bart's return to his family as an irony at the expense of the very
notion of American family life. Which, of course, is one of the most striking and persistent
themes of The Simpsons.
Conclusion
What conclusions can we draw about popular parody as opposed to art parody?
First, that it tends to focus on the comic rather than the ironic. This does not mean that irony
is necessarily absent; merely that the primary mechanisms are comic, with irony
subordinate to comic intentions. Furthermore, popular parody is often undertaken out of
fondness for the target texts rather than an attitude of aesthetic self-consciouness or
self-reflexivity. Popular parody, unlike art parody, is not primarily critical of its target texts
-- at least, it is not critical in the sense of "interrogating" its precedents. Homage rather than
criticism is a significant and recurring parodic strategy found in popular art. Certainly
popular parody can ridicule and lampoon its target text. But lampooning is usually based
on extrinsic rather than intrinsic references. "Bart the Murderer" exploits intrinsic
references by employing some of the most central narrative themes and structures from the
gangster genre. But as we have seen, the parody here is selective: not all the defining
thematics are explicitly present. Is "Bart the Murderer" itself part of the genre of gangster
films? It is hardly a paradigm example of the genre, especially given the absence of
extreme violence. Still, it is a good mixed example. What The Simpsons tells us about the
family in the 1990s thanks to the other primary generic component of the mix, the
cartoonized version of the family sit-com, is expertly analysed by Paul A. Cantor in this
volume8 And that turns out to be something even Goodfellas could not tell us.9
1 Contrasting so-called "high" and "popular" artforms is a convenient though problematic way of
speaking. Cinema and more recently television are obvious examples of media which can pretty much
collapse this distinction. Philosophers of art such as Stanley Cavell and Ted Cohen have long recognized that
Hitchcock's North By Northwest is just as clearly an example of art as a Rembrandt self-portrait. Noel Carroll,
in A Philosophy of Mass Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), suggests that we are better off talking about
"mass" art if what we are referring to is "popular art produced and distributed by a mass technology" (p. 3). I
think it is beyond contention that The Simpsons qualifies as an example of this sort of mass or popular art. I do
not assume that "high" art is necessarily superior to "popular" art: there are great popular artworks just as
there are lousy "high" artworks.
2 See Chapter 6 of this volume.
3 Thomas J. Roberts, An Aesthetics of Junk Fiction (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press,
1990).
4 Linda Hutcheon, A Theory of Parody: The Teachings of Twentieth-Century Artforms (New York:
Methuen, 1985), p. 33.
5 Robert Burden, "The Novel Interrogates Itself: Parody as Self-consciousness in Contemporary
English Fiction," in Malcom Bradbury and David Palmer, eds., The Contemporary English Novel (London:
Edward Arnold, 1979)
6 The enormous popularity of Martin Scorsese should not be underestimated. For instance, he has
been voted the most popular movie director by readers of the Time-Out Film Guides -- more popular even
than Hitchcock -- and in their 2000 edition Goodfellas ranks 11th on the list of most popular films, between
It's A Wonderful Life and North By Northwest. Of the top thirty most popular films on that list, only two --
Pulp Fiction (13th) and Schindler's List (20th) -- were made more recently than Goodfellas.
7 Algis Budry, quoted in Roberts, p. 90.
8 See Chapter 11.
9 Thanks to George McKnight, Bill Irwin, and Carl Matheson for comments and suggestions.
8
The Simpsons, Hyper-Irony,
and the Meaning of Life
CARL MATHESON
DISAFFECTED YOUTH #1: Here comes that cannonball guy. He's cool.
DISAFFECTED YOUTH #2: Are you being sarcastic, dude?
DISAFFECTED YOUTH #1: I don't even know anymore.
-- "Homerpalooza," Season 7
What separates the comedies that were shown on television fifty, forty, or even
twenty-five years ago from those of today? First, we may notice technological differences,
the difference between black-and-white and color, the difference between film stock (or
even kinescope) and video. Then there are the numerous social differences. For instance,
the myth of the universal traditional two-parent family is not as secure as it was in the
1950s and 1960s, and the comedies of the different eras reflect changes in its status --
although even early comedies of the widow/widower happy fifties, sixties, and seventies
were full of non-traditional families, such as are found in The Partridge Family, The Ghost
and Mrs. Muir, Julia, The Jerry van Dyke Show, Family Affair, The Courtship of Eddie's
Father, The Andy Griffith Show, The Brady Bunch, Bachelor Father, and My Little Margie.
Also, one may note the ways in which issues such as race have received different
treatments over the decades.
But I would like to concentrate on a deeper transformation: today's comedies, at
least most of them, are funny in different ways from those of decades past. In both texture
and substance the comedy of The Simpsons and Seinfeld is worlds apart from the comedy
of Leave it to Beaver and The Jack Benny Show, and is even vastly different from much
more recent comedies, such as MASH and Maude. First, today's comedies tend to be highly
quotational: many of today's comedies essentially depend on the device of referring to or
quoting other works of popular culture. Second, they are hyper-ironic, the flavor of humor
offered by today's comedies is colder, based less on a shared sense of humanity than on a
sense of world-weary cleverer-than-thou-ness. In this essay I would like to explore the way
in which The Simpsons uses both quotationalism and hyper-ironism and relate these
devices to currents in the contemporary history of ideas.
Quotationalism
Television comedy has never completely foregone the pleasure of using pop culture
as a straight man. However, early instances of quotation tended to be opportunistic; they
did not comprise the substance of the genre. Hence, in sketch comedy, one would find
occasional references to popular culture in Wayne and Shuster and Johnny Carson, but
these references were really treated as just one more source of material. The roots of
quotationalism as a main source of material can be found in the early seventies with the two
visionary comedies, Mary Hartman Mary Hartman, which lampooned soap operas by
being an ongoing soap opera, and Fernwood 2Night, which, as a small-budget talk show,
took on small-budget talk shows. Quotationalism then came much more to the attention of
the general public between the mid-seventies and early eighties through Saturday Night
Live, Late Night with David Letterman, and SCTV. Given the mimical abilities of its cast
and its need for weekly material, the chief comedic device of SNL was parody -- of genres
(the nightly news, television debates), of particular television shows (I Love Lucy, Star
Trek) and of movies (Star Wars). The type of quotationalism employed by Letterman was
more abstract and less based on particular shows. Influenced by the much earlier absurdism
of such hosts as Dave Garroway, Letterman immediately took the formulas of television
and cinema beyond their logical conclusions (The Equalizer Guy, chimp cam, and
spokesperson Larry "Bud" Melman).
However, it was SCTV that gathered together the various strains of quotationalism
and synthesized them into a deeper, more complex, and more mysterious whole. Like Mary
Hartman, and unlike SNL, it was an ongoing series with recurring characters such as
Johnny Larue, Lola Heatherton and Bobby Bittman. However, unlike Mary Hartman, the
ongoing series was about the workings of a television station. SCTV was a television show
about the process of television. Through the years, the models upon which characters like
Heatherton and Bittman were based vanished somewhat into the background, as
Heatherton and Bittman started to breathe on their own, and therefore, came to occupy a
shadowy space between real (fictional) characters and simulacra. Furthermore, SCTVs
world came to intersect the real world as some of the archetypes portrayed (such as Jerry
Lewis) were people in real life. Thus, SCTV eventually produced and depended upon
patterns of inter-textuality and cross-referencing that were much more thorougoing and
subtle than those of any program that preceded it.
The Simpsons was born, therefore, just as the use of quotationalism was maturing.
However, The Simpsons was not the same sort of show as SNL and SCTV. One major
difference of course, was that The Simpsons was animated while the others were (largely)
not, but this difference does not greatly affect the relevant potential for quotationalism --
although it may be easier to draw the bridge of the U.S.S. Enterprise than to rebuild it and
re-enlist the entire original cast of Star Trek. The main difference is that as an ostensibly
ongoing family comedy, The Simpsons was both plot and character driven, where the other
shows, even those that contained ongoing characters were largely sketch driven.
Furthermore, unlike Mary Hartman Mary Hartman, which existed to parody soap operas,
The Simpsons did not have the raison d'être of parodying the family-based comedies of
which it was an instance. The problem then was this: how does one transform an essentially
non-quotational format into an essentially quotational show?
The answer to the above question lies in the form of quotationalism employed by
The Simpsons. By way of contrast, let me outline what it was definitively not. Take, for
instance, a Wayne and Shuster parody of Wilde's The Picture of Dorian Gray. In the
parody, instead of Gray's sins being reflected in an artwork, while he remains pure and
young in appearance, the effects of Gray's overeating are reflected in the artwork, while he
remains thin. The situation's permissions and combinations are squeezed and coaxed to
produce the relevant gags and ensuing yuks. End of story. Here the quotationalism is very
direct; it is the source both of the story line and of the supposedly humorous contrast
between the skit and the original novel. Now, compare this linear and one-dimensional use
of quotation for the purposes of parody with the pattern of quotation used in a very short
passage from an episode from The Simpsons entitled "A Streetcar Named Marge." In the
episode, Marge is playing Blanche Dubois opposite Ned Flanders's Stanley in Streetcar!,
her community theatre's musical version of the Tennessee Williams play. In need of day
care for little Maggie, she sends Maggie to the Ayn Rand School for Tots, which is run by
the director's sister. Headmistress Sinclair, a strict disciplinarian and believer in infant
self-reliance, confiscates all of the tots' pacifiers which causes an enraged Maggie to lead
her classmates in a highly organized reclamation mission, during which the theme from
The Great Escape plays in the background. Having re-acquired the pacifiers the group sits,
arrayed in rows, making little sucking sounds, so that when Homer arrives to pick up
Maggie, he is confronted with a scene from Hitchcock's The Birds.
The first thing that one can say about these quotations is that they are very funny.
However, I don't want to play the doomed game of saying why they're funny, because any
crinkly-eyed chuckler who tries to analyze sources of humor ends up seeming about as
funny as Emil Jannings in Blue Angel (and not in the really funny part where he is
cuckolded by a circus strongman, forced to do a grief-stricken and impotent imitation of a
rooster in front of his jeering students, and sent off to die a broken man, but in the less
funny parts before that). To see that these quotations are funny just watch the show again.
Second, we note that these quotations are not used for the purpose of parody.1 Rather, they
are allusions, designed to provide unspoken metaphorical elaboration and commentary
about what is going on in the scene. The allusion to Ayn Rand underscores the ideology
and personal rigidity of Headmistress Sinclair. The theme music from The Great Escape
stresses the determination of Maggie and her cohort. The allusion to The Birds
communicates the threat of the hive-mind posed by many small beings working as one. By
going outside of the text via these nearly instantaneous references, The Simpsons manages
to convey a great deal of extra information extremely economically. Third, the most
impressive feature of this pattern of allusion is its pace and density, where this feature has
grown more common as the series has matured. Early episodes, for instance the one in
which Bart saws the head off the town's statue of Jebediah Springfield, are surprisingly free
of quotation. Later episodes derive much of their manic comic energy from their rapid-fire
sequence of allusions. This density of allusion is perhaps what sets The Simpsons most
apart from any show that has preceded it.2
However, the extent to which The Simpsons depends on other elements of pop
culture is not without cost. Just as those readers who are unfamiliar with Frazer's Golden
Bough will be hindered in their attempt to understand Eliot's "The Waste Land," and just as
many modern day readers will be baffled by many of the Biblical and classical allusions
that play important roles in the history of literature, many of today's viewers won't fully
understand much of what goes on in The Simpsons due to an unfamiliarity with the popular
culture that forms the basis for the show's references. Having missed the references, these
people may interpret The Simpsons as nothing more than a slightly off-base family comedy
populated with characters who are neither very bright nor very interesting. From these
propositions they will probably derive the theorem that the show is neither substantial nor
funny, and also the lemma that the people who like the show are deficient in taste,
intelligence, or standards of personal mental hygiene. However, not only do the detractors
of the show miss a great deal of its humor, they also fail to realize that its pattern of
quotations is an absolutely essential vehicle for developing character and for setting a tone.
And, since these people are usually not huge fans of popular culture to begin with, they will
be reluctant to admit that they are missing something significant. Oh well. It is difficult to
explain color to a blind man, especially if he won't listen. On the other hand, those who
enjoy connecting the quotational dots will enjoy their task all the more for its exclusivity.
There is no joke like an in-joke: the fact that many people don't get The Simpsons might
very well make the show both funnier and better to those who do.
Hyper-Ironism and The Moral Agenda
Without the smart-ass, comedy itself would be impossible. Whether one subscribes,
as I do, to the thesis that all comedy is fundamentally cruel, or merely to the relatively
spineless position that only the vast majority of comedy is fundamentally cruel, one has to
admit that comedy has always relied upon the joys to be derived from making fun of others.
However, usually the cruelty has been employed for a positive social purpose. In the
sanctimonious MASH, Hawkeye and the gang were simply joking to "dull the pain of a
world gone mad," and the butts of their jokes, such as Major Frank Burns, symbolized
threats to the liberal values that the show perpetually attempted to reinforce in the souls of
its late twentieth-century viewers. In Leave it To Beaver, the link between humor and the
instillation of family values is didactically obvious. A very few shows, most notably
Seinfeld, totally eschewed a moral agenda.3 Seinfelds ability to maintain a devoted
audience in spite of a cast of shallow and petty characters engaged in equally petty and
shallow acts is miraculous. So, as I approach The Simpsons, I would like to resolve the
following questions. Does The Simpsons use its humor to promote a moral agenda? Does it
use its humor to promote the claim that there is no justifiable moral agenda? Or, does it stay
out of the moral agenda game altogether?
These are tricky questions, because data can be found to affirm each of them. To
support the claim that The Simpsons promotes a moral agenda, one usually need look no
further than Lisa and Marge. Just consider Lisa's speeches in favor of integrity, freedom
from censorship, or any variety of touchy-feely social causes, and you will come away with
the opinion that The Simpsons is just another liberal show underneath a somewhat thin but
tasty crust of nastiness. One can even expect Bart to show humanity when it counts, as
when, at military school, he defies sexist peer-pressure to cheer Lisa on in her attempt to
complete an obstacle course. The show also seems to engage in self-righteous
condemnation of various institutional soft targets. The political system of Springfield is
corrupt, its police chief lazy and self-serving, and its Reverend Lovejoy ineffectual at best.
Property developers stage a fake religious miracle in order to promote the opening of a
mall. Mr. Burns tries to increase business at the power plant by blocking out the sun. Taken
together, these examples seem to advocate a moral position of caring at the level of the
individual, one which favors the family over any institution.4
However, one can find examples from the show that seem to be denied
accommodation within any plausible moral stance. In one episode, Frank Grimes (who
hates being called "Grimey") is a constantly unappreciated model worker, while Homer is a
much beloved careless slacker. Eventually, Grimes breaks down and decides to act just like
Homer Simpson. While "acting like Homer" Grimes touches a transformer and is killed
instantly. During the funeral oration by Reverend Lovejoy (for "Gri-yuh-mee, as he liked
to be called") a snoozing Homer shouts out "Change the channel, Marge!" The rest of the
service breaks into spontaneous and appreciative laughter, with Lenny saying "That's our
Homer!" End of episode. In another episode, Homer is unintentionally responsible for the
death of Maude Flanders, Ned's wife. In the crowd at a football game, Homer is eager to
catch a T-shirt being shot from little launchers on the field. Just as one is shot his way, he
bends over to pick up a peanut. The T-shirt sails over him and hits the devout Maude,
knocking her out of the stands to her death. These episodes are difficult to locate on a moral
map; they certainly do not conform to the standard trajectory of virtue rewarded.
Given that we have various data, some of which lead us towards and others away
from the claim that The Simpsons is committed to caring, liberal family values, what
should we conclude? Before attempting to reach a conclusion, I would like to go beyond
details from various episodes of the show to introduce another form of possibly relevant
evidence. Perhaps, we can better resolve the issue of The Simpsons' moral commitments by
examining the way it relates to current intellectual trends. The reader should be warned that,
although I think that my comments on the current state of the history of ideas are more or
less accurate, they are greatly oversimplified. In particular, the positions that I will outline
are by no means unanimously accepted.
Let's start with painting. The influential critic, Clement Greenberg, held that the
goal of all painting was to work with flatness as the nature of its medium and he
reconstructed the history of painting so that it was seen to culminate in the dissolution of
pictorial three-dimensional space and the acceptance of total flatness by the painters of the
mid-twentieth century. Painters were taken to be like scientific researchers whose work
furthered the progress of their medium, where the idea of artistic progress was to be taken
as literally as that of scientific progress. Because they were fundamentally unjustifiable
and because they put painters into a straitjacket, Greenberg's positions gradually lost their
hold, and no other well-supported candidates for the essence of painting could be found to
take their place. As a result painting (and the other arts) entered a phase that the
philosopher of art, Arthur Danto, has called "the end of art." By this Danto did not mean
that art could no longer be produced, but rather that art could no longer be subsumed under
a history of progress towards some given end.5 By the end of the 1970s, many painters had
turned to earlier, more representational styles, and their paintings were as much
commentaries on movements from the past, like expressionism, and about the current
vacuum in the history of art, as they were about their subject matter. Instead of being about
the essence of painting, much of painting came to be about the history of painting. Similar
events unfolded in the other artistic media as architects, film-makers, and writers returned
to the history of their disciplines.
However, painting was not the only area in which long-held convictions
concerning the nature and inevitability of progress were aggressively challenged. Science,
the very icon of progressiveness, was under attack from a number of quarters. Kuhn held
(depending on which interpreter of him you agree with) either that there was no such thing
as scientific progress, or that if there was, there were no rules for determining what
progress and scientific rationality were. Feyerabend argued that people who held
substantially different theories couldn't even understand what each other was saying, and
hence that there was no hope of a rational consensus; instead he extolled the anarchistic
virtues of "anything goes." Early sociological workers in the field of science studies tried to
show that, instead of being an inspirational narrative of the disinterested pursuit of truth,
the history of science was essentially a story of office-politics writ large, because every
transition in the history of science could be explained by appeal to the personal interests
and allegiances of the participants.6 And, of course, the idea of philosophical progress has
continued to be challenged. Writing on Derrida, the American philosopher Richard Rorty
argues that anything like the philosophical truth is either unattainable, nonexistent, or
uninteresting, that philosophy itself is a literary genre, and that philosophers should
reconstrue themselves as writers who elaborate and re-interpret the writings of other
philosophers. In other words, Rorty's version of Derrida recommends that philosophers
view themselves as historically aware participants in a conversation, as opposed to
quasi-scientific researchers.7 Derrida himself favored a method known as deconstruction,
which was popular several years ago, and which consisted of a highly technical method for
undercutting texts by revealing hidden contradictions and unconscious ulterior motives.
Rorty questions whether, given Derrida's take on the possibility of philosophical progress,
deconstruction could be used only for negative purposes, that is, whether it could be used
for anything more than making philosophical fun of other writings.
Let me repeat that these claims about the nature of art, science, and philosophy are
highly controversial. However, all that I need for my purposes is the relatively
uncontroversial claim that views such as these are now in circulation to an unprecedented
extent. We are surrounded by a pervasive crisis of authority, be it artistic, scientific or
philosophical, religious or moral, in a way that previous generations weren't. Now, as we
slowly come back to earth and The Simpsons, we should ask this: if the crisis I described
were as pervasive as I believe it to be, how might it be reflected generally in popular culture,
and specifically in comedy?
We have already discussed one phenomenon that may be viewed as a consequence
of the crisis of authority. When faced with the death of the idea of progress in their field,
thinkers and artists have often turned to a reconsideration of the history of their discipline.
Hence artists turn to art history, architects to the history of design, and so on. The
motivation for this turn is natural; once one has given up on the idea that the past is merely
the inferior pathway to a better today and a still better tomorrow, one may try to approach
the past on its own terms as an equal partner. Additionally, if the topic of progress is off the
list of things to talk about, an awareness of history may be one of the few things left to fill
the disciplinary conversational void. Hence, one may think that quotationalism is a natural
offshoot of the crisis of authority, and that the prevalence of quotationalism in The
Simpsons results from that crisis.
The idea that quotationalism in The Simpsons is the result of "something in the air"
is confirmed by the stunning everpresence of historical appropriation throughout popular
culture. Cars like the new Volkswagen Beetle and the PT Cruiser quote bygone days, and
factories simply can't make enough of them. In architecture, New Urbanist housing
developments try to recreate the feel of small towns of decades ago, and they have proven
so popular that only the very wealthy can buy homes in them. The musical world is a
hodgepodge of quotations of styles, where often the original music being quoted is simply
sampled and re-processed.
To be fair, not every instance of historical quotationalism should be seen as the
result of some widespread crisis of authority. For instance, the New Urbanist movement in
architecture was a direct response to a perceived erosion of community caused by the
deadening combination of economically segregated suburbs and faceless shopping malls;
the movement used history in order to make the world a better place for people to live with
other people. Hence the degree of quotationalism in The Simpsons could point towards a
crisis in authority, but it could also stem from a strategy for making the world better, like
the New Urbanism, or it could merely be a fashion accessory, like retro-Khaki at The Gap.
No, if we want to plumb the depths of The Simpsons' connection with the crisis in
authority we will have to look to something else, and it is at this point that I return to the
original question of this section: does The Simpsons use its humor to promote a moral
agenda? My answer is this: The Simpsons does not promote anything, because its humor
works by putting forward positions only in order to undercut them. Furthermore, this
process of undercutting runs so deeply that we cannot regard the show as merely cynical; it
manages to undercut its cynicism too. This constant process of undercutting is what I mean
by "hyper-ironism."
To see what I mean, consider "Scenes from the Class Struggle in Springfield," an
episode from the show's seventh season. In this episode Marge buys a Coco Chanel suit for
$90 at the Outlet Mall. While wearing the suit, she runs into an old high-school classmate.
Seeing the designer suit and taking Marge to be one of her kind, the classmate invites
Marge to the posh Springfield Glen Country Club. Awed by the gentility at the Club, and in
spite of sniping from club members that she always wears the same suit, Marge becomes
bent on social climbing. Initially alienated, Homer and Lisa fall in love with the club for its
golf-course and stables. However, just as they are about to be inducted into the club, Marge
realizes that her newfound obsession with social standing has taken precedence over her
family. Thinking that the club also probably doesn't want them anyway, she and the family
walk away. However, unbeknownst to the Simpsons, the club has prepared a lavish
welcome party for them, and is terribly put out that they haven't arrived -- Mr. Burns even
"pickled the figs for the cake" himself.
At first glance, this episode may seem like another case of the show's reaffirmation
of family values: after all, Marge chooses family over status. Furthermore, what could be
more hollow than status among a bunch of shallow inhuman snobs? However, the people in
the club turn out to be inclusive and fairly affectionate, from golfer Tom Kite who gives
Homer advice on his swing despite that fact that Homer has stolen his golf clubs -- and
shoes -- to Mr. Burns, who thanks Homer for exposing his dishonesty at golf. The jaded
cynicism that seems to pervade the club is gradually shown to be a mere conversational
trope; the club is prepared to welcome the working-class Simpsons with open arms -- or
has it realized yet that they are working class?8 Further complicating matters are Marge's
reasons for walking away. First, there is the false dilemma between caring for her family
and being welcomed by the club. Why should one choice exclude the other? Second is her
belief that the Simpsons just don't belong to such a club. This belief seems to be based on a
classism that the club itself doesn't have. This episode leaves no stable ground upon which
the viewer can rest. It feints at the sanctity of family values and swerves closely to class
determinism, but it doesn't stay anywhere. Furthermore, upon reflection, none of the
"solutions" that it momentarily holds is satisfactory. In its own way, this episode is as cruel
and cold-blooded as the Grimey episode. However, where the Grimey episode wears its
heartlessness upon its sleeve, this episode conjures up illusions of satisfactory
heart-warming resolution only to undercut them immediately. In my view, it stands as a
paradigm of the real Simpsons.
I think that, given a crisis of authority, hyper-ironism is the most suitable form of
comedy. Recall that many painters and architects turned to a consideration of the history of
painting and architecture once they gave up on the idea of fundamental trans-historical goal
for their media. Recall also that once Rorty's version of Derrida became convinced of the
non-existence of transcendent philosophical truth, he reconstructed philosophy as an
historically aware conversation which largely consisted of the deconstruction of past works.
One way of looking at all of these transitions is that, with the abandonment of knowledge
came the cult of knowingness. That is, even if there is no ultimate truth (or method for
arriving at it) I can still show that I understand the intellectual rules by which you operate
better than you do. I can show my superiority over you by demonstrating my awareness of
what makes you tick. In the end, none of our positions is ultimately superior, but I can at
least show myself to be in a superior position for now on the shifting sands of the game we
are currently playing. Hyper-irony is the comedic instantiation of the cult of knowingness.
Given the crisis of authority, there are no higher purposes to which comedy can be put,
such as moral instruction, theological revelation, or showing how the world is. However,
comedy can be used to attack anybody at all who thinks that he or she has any sort of
handle on the answer to any major question, not to replace the object of the attack with a
better way of looking at things, but merely for the pleasure of the attack, or perhaps for the
sense of momentary superiority mentioned earlier. The Simpsons revels in the attack. It
treats nearly everything as a target, every stereotypical character, every foible, and every
institution. It plays games of one-upmanship with its audience members by challenging
them to identify the avalanche of allusions it throws down to them. And, as "Scenes from
the Class Struggle in Springfield" illustrates, it refrains from taking a position of its own.
It would be quite right to point out that many other episodes are far less bleak or
narratively unstable than the Frank Grimes and the country club episodes. Most of the early
shows, such as the episode in which Bart decapitates the town statue, possess simple
family-oriented resolutions. Later shows contain some cosmetic undercutting. Early in
"Deep Space Homer," from season five, Bart writes "Insert Brain Here" in felt marker on
the back of Homer's head. Later, after Homer the astronaut saves his space capsule, Bart
writes "Hero" on the back of Homer's head. Here, the illusion of undercutting serves
merely to bitter-coat an otherwise unpalatably sugary pill. Or does it? After all, Homer
saved the space mission by mistake: he unintentionally repaired a damaged air hatch while
trying to kill another astronaut with a carbon rod. The air hatch in question had been shaken
loose during an attempt to evacuate some experimental ants which Homer had accidentally
released. In addition, the world -- and Time magazine -- recognized the "inanimate carbon
rod" for saving the space-craft, not Homer. Therefore, it would be fair to say that the
moment between Homer and Bart was somewhat contaminated by previous events.
However, to be fair to those who believe The Simpsons takes a stable moral stance,
there are episodes which seem not to undercut themselves at all. Consider, for instance the
previously mentioned episode in which Bart helps Lisa at military school. In that episode,
many things are ridiculed, but the fundamental goodness of the relationship between Bart
and Lisa is left unquestioned. In another episode, when Lisa discovers that Jebediah
Springfield, the legendary town founder, was a sham, she refrains from announcing her
finding to the town when she notices the social value of the myth of Jebediah Springfield.9
And, of course, we must mention the episode in which jazzman Bleeding Gums Murphy
dies, which truly deserves the Simpsonian epithet "worst episode ever." This episode
combines an uncritical sentimentality with a naive adoration of art-making, and tops
everything off with some unintentionally horrible pseudo-jazz which would serve better as
the theme music for a cable-access talk show. Lisa's song "Jazzman" simultaneously
embodies all three of these faults, and must count as the worst moment of the worst episode
ever. Given these episodes and others like them, which occur too frequently to be
dismissed as blips, we are still left with the conflicting data with which we started the
section. Is The Simpsons hyper-ironic or not? One could argue that the hyper-ironism is a
trendy fashion accessory, irony from The Gap, which does not reflect the ethos of the show.
Another critically well-received program, Buffy the Vampire Slayer is as strongly
committed to a black and white distinction between right and wrong as only teenagers can
be. Its dependence on wisecracks and subversive irony is only skin deep. Underneath the
surface, one will find angst-ridden teens fighting a solemn battle against evil demons who
want to destroy the world. Perhaps, one could argue, beneath the surface irony of The
Simpsons one will find a strong commitment to family values.
I would like to argue that Simpsonian hyper-ironism is not a mask for an underlying
moral commitment. Here are three reasons, the first two of which are plausible but
probably insufficient. First, The Simpsons does not consist of a single episode, but of over
two hundred episodes spread out over more than ten seasons. There is good reason to think
that apparent resolutions in one episode are usually undercut by others.10 In other words,
we are cued to respond ironically to one episode, given the cues provided by many other
episodes. However, one could argue, that this inter-episodic undercutting is itself undercut
by the show's frequent use of happy family endings.
Second, as a self-consciously hip show, The Simpsons can be taken to be aware of
and to embrace what is current. Family values are hardly trendy, so there is little reason to
believe that The Simpsons would adopt them whole-heartedly. However, this is weak
confirmation at best. As a trendy show, The Simpsons could merely flirt with hyper-irony
without fully adopting it. After all, it is hardly hyper-ironic to pledge allegiance to any flag,
including the flag of hyper-ironism. Also, in addition to being a self-consciously hip show,
it is also a show that must live within the constraints of prime-time American network
television. One could argue that these constraints would force The Simpsons towards a
commitment to some sort of palatable moral stance. Therefore, we cannot infer that the
show is hyper-ironic from the lone premise that it is self-consciously hip.
The third and strongest reason for a pervasive hyper-ironism and against the claim
that The Simpsons takes a stand in favor of family values is based on the perception that the
comedic energy of the show dips significantly whenever moral closure or didacticism rise
above the surface (as in the Bleeding Gums Murphy episodes). Unlike Buffy the Vampire
Slayer, The Simpsons is fundamentally a comedy. Buffy can get away with dropping its
ironic stance, because it is an adventure focussed on the timeless battle between good and
evil. The Simpsons has nowhere else to go when it stops being funny. Thus, it's very funny
when it celebrates physical cruelty in any given Itchy and Scratchy Show. It's very funny
when it ridicules Krusty and the marketing geniuses who broadcast Itchy and Scratchy. It's
banal, flat, and not funny when it tries to deal seriously with the issue of censorship arising
from Itchy and Scratchy. The lifeblood of The Simpsons, and its astonishing achievement,
is the pace of cruelty and ridicule that it has managed to sustain for over a decade. The
prevalence of quotationalism helps to sustain this pace, because the show can look beyond
itself for a constant stream of targets. When the target-shooting slows down for a
wholesome message or a heart-warming family moment, the program slows to an
embarrassing crawl with nary a quiver from the laugh-meter.
I don't mean to argue that the makers of The Simpsons intended the show primarily
as a theater of cruelty, although I imagine that they did. Rather, I want to argue that, as a
comedy, its goal is to be funny, and we should read it in a way that maximizes its capability
to be funny. When we interpret it as a wacky but earnest endorsement of family values, we
read it in a way that hamstrings its comedic potential. When we read it as a show built upon
the twin pillars of misanthropic humor and oh-so-clever intellectual one-upmanship, we
maximize its comedic potential by paying attention to the features of the show that make us
laugh. We also provide a vital function for the degree of quotationalism in the show, and as
a bonus, we tie the show into a dominant trend of thought in the twentieth century.
But, if the heart-warming family moments don't contribute to the show's comedic
potential, why are they there at all? One possible explanation is that they are simply
mistakes; they were meant to be funny but they aren't. This hypothesis is implausible.
Another is that the show is not exclusively a comedy, but rather a family comedy --
something wholesome and not very funny that the whole family can pretend to enjoy. This
is equally implausible. Alternatively, we can try to look for a function for the
heart-warming moments. I think there is such a function. For the sake of argument, suppose
that the engine driving The Simpsons is fuelled by cruelty and one-upmanship. Its viewers,
although appreciative of its humor, might not want to come back week after week to such a
bleak message, especially if the message is centered on a family with children. Seinfeld
never really offered any hope; its heart was as cold as ice. However, Seinfeld was about
disaffected adults. A similarly bleak show containing children would resemble the parody
of a sit-com in Oliver Stone's Natural Born Killers, in which Rodney Dangerfield plays an
alcoholic child-abuser. Over the years, such a series would lose a grip on its viewers, to say
the least. I think that the thirty seconds or so of apparent redemption in each episode of The
Simpsons is there mainly to allow us to soldier on for twenty-one and a half minutes of
maniacal cruelty at the beginning of the next episode. In other words, the heartwarming
family moments help The Simpsons to live on as a series. The comedy does not exist for the
sake of a message; the occasional illusion of a positive message exists to enable us to
tolerate more comedy. Philosophers and critics have often talked of the paradox of horror
and the paradox of tragedy. Why do we eagerly seek out art forms that arouse unpleasant
emotions in us like pity, sadness, and fear? I think that, for at least certain forms of comedy,
there is an equally important paradox of comedy. Why do we seek out art that makes us
laugh at the plight of unfortunate people in a world without redemption? The laughter here
seems to come at a high price. The Simpsons' use of heart-warming family endings should
be seen as its attempt to paper over the paradox of comedy that it exemplifies so well.
I hope to have shown that quotationalism and hyper-ironism are prevalent,
inter-dependent, and jointly responsible for the way in which the humor in The Simpsons
works. The picture I have painted of The Simpsons is a bleak one, because I have
characterized its humor as negative, a humor of cruelty and condescension -- but really
funny cruelty and condescension.11 I have left out a very important part of the picture
however. The Simpsons, consisting of a not-as-bright version of the Freudian id for a father,
a sociopathic son, a prissy daughter, and a fairly dull but innocuous mother, is a family
whose members love each other. And, we love them. Despite the fact that the show strips
away any semblance of value, despite the fact that week after week it offers us little
comfort, it still manages to convey the raw power of the irrational (or nonrational) love of
human beings for other human beings, and it makes us play along by loving these
flickering bits of paint on celluloid who live in a flickering hollow world. Now that's
comedy entertainment.12
1 I don't mean to say that The Simpsons does not make use of parody. The episode currently under
discussion contains a brilliant parody of Broadway adaptations, from its title to the show-stopping tune "A
Stranger is Just a Friend You Haven't Met!"
2 For more on allusion in The Simpsons, see Chapter 6 of this volume.
3 For a different view, see Robert A. Epperson, "Seinfeld and the Moral Life," in William Irwin, ed.,
Seinfeld and Philosophy: A Book about Everything and Nothing (Chicago: Open Court, 2000), pp. 163-174.
4 For a defense of the thesis that The Simpsons defends family values, see Chapter 11 of this volume.
5 See Arthur Danto, After the End of Art (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).
6 Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, second edition (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1970). Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: NLB, 1975). For a lively debate on the
limits of the sociology of knowledge, see James Robert Brown (ed.), Scientific Rationality: The Sociological
Turn (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1984).
7 Richard Rorty, "Philosophy as a Kind of Writing," pp. 90-109 in Consequences of Pragmatism
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982).
8 For further discussion of the working class see Chapter 16 of this volume.
9 Was Lisa being hypocritical? For discussion of justifiable hypocrisy see Chapter 12 of this volume.
10 Thanks to my colleague and co-contributor, Jason Holt, for first suggesting this to me.
11 Although I have shown that the humor of The Simpsons is frequently cruel, I have not shown that
it is always cruel. Indeed it isn't. Some very funny moments are based on harmless sight gags, such as when
Sideshow Bob hides behind an intricately shaped statue of an aircraft that exactly matches the outlines of his
hair. Furthermore, I have only stated rather than argued that the show stops being funny when it moves away
from cruelty for long. Part of my reason for this claim is my belief that all of comedy (as opposed to every
instance of humor) is based on cruelty. However, this claim is extremely controversial and there isn't enough
space to argue for it here. To assess the centrality of cruelty as the mainspring of The Simpsons' humor, we
would have to look at many supposedly funny examples from the show. What I fear is simply that different
people would disagree over what was funny. Since, at this point, matters become philosophically interesting
but also extremely messy, I must admit that any sort of universal claim about the role of cruelty within the
show is controversial and in need of additional support.
12 This paper has benefited greatly from discussions I have had with Heidi Rees, Jason Holt, Adam
Muller, Emily Muller, George Toles, Steve Snyder, and Guy Maddin. Thanks also to William Irwin for his
supportive editorship and to The Simpsons Archive (www.snpp.com) for very helpful episode listings.
9
Simpsonian Sexual Politcs
DALE E. SNOW and JAMES J. SNOW
What The Simpsons does best is question television pieties ranging from the fifties
bromide that "Father knows best" to the burning question of the quality of present-day Fox
programming. Yet it continues and extends a conservative sexual politics in three ways: the
depiction of Springfield as having an overwhelmingly male population; the fact that a large
majority of the episodes are focused on Bart or Homer; and the characterization given of
both Marge and Lisa.
It's a Male, Male, Male, Male World
REP. ARNOLD: You must be Lisa Simpson.
LISA: Hello, sir.
REP. ARNOLD: Lisa, you're a doer. And who knows, maybe someday you'll be a
congressman or senator. We have quite a few women senators, you know.
LISA: Only two. I checked.
REP. ARNOLD: [chuckles] You're a sharp one. ("Mr. Lisa goes to Washington")
One of the unfailing visual delights of almost every Simpsons episode is the
richness and detail of the backgrounds, especially crowd scenes. Bugs Bunny may have
played baseball before a stadium of indistinct oval squiggles, and we find similar empty
faces in Doug or Ren and Stimpy (to name two rather different recent cartoons), but
Springfield is alive with real and recognizable people in every crowd scene. It is easy to
understand why each episode takes six months to animate, given the care lavished on
signage, background landscapes both urban and rural, and the creation of dozens of
instantly recognizable Springfield residents.
The regular viewer is not surprised to see Moe, Otto, Mr. Burns, Smithers, and
Jasper in the audience at school functions, for example, despite the fact that (we presume)
they do not have school age children at Springfield Elementary. Similarly, Principal
Skinner, Groundskeeper Willy, and Edna Krabappel are familiar faces in the crowds
listening to hucksters, attending the circus, or demonstrating outside Town Hall. The
regular viewer feels that he or she knows the town, as numerous critics have pointed out.
Indeed, Springfield is a vital element in The Simpsons' success:
By bringing life to such a "wonderfully congested cosmos," Groening manages to leave the
main plot line undetermined for a relatively long period of time. . . The series setting and basic
composition contribute to and are preconditions for an exceptional variety of plot lines, opening up
the whole infinite universe of storytelling the genre of animation is capable of; that is, portraying
both reality and the surreal in an artistic as well as dramatic manner which is otherwise particular to
literature only and can rarely be found in modern film.1
Therefore it's hardly a minor matter to point out that in terms of gender distribution,
the town of Springfield is, if anything, slightly more conservative than the universe of
shows it often satirizes. Julia Wood describes the television norm:
White males make up two-thirds of the population. The women are less in number, perhaps
because fewer than ten percent live beyond 35. Those who do, like their younger and male
counterparts, are nearly all white and heterosexual. In addition to being young, the majority of
women are beautiful, very thin, passive, and primarily concerned with relationships. . . There are a
few bad, bitchy women, and they are not so pretty, not so subordinate, and not so caring as the
good women. Most of the bad ones work outside of the home, which is probably why they are
hardened and undesirable. 2
To the best of our knowledge, Census 2000 has not visited Springfield, so we will
rely on three sources in an effort to establish the distribution of the sexes. "Who's Who? in
Springfield," a web site which describes itself as "an exhaustive list of literary, political,
historical, television, military, movie, musical, commercial, and cartoon allusions to
supporting characters in The Simpsons"3 contains a sub-section called "Recurring
Characters," which purports to include every character to have appeared in more than one
episode, from Bleeding Gums Murphy to Rainer Wolfcastle. In addition to the five
immediate Simpson family members, it lists 45 male characters, as well as "Radioactive
Man" (Bart's favorite comic book character), and eleven female characters, along with
"Malibu Stacy," Lisa's doll. Even if Itchy and Scratchy are regarded as beyond gender, this
is a 4:1 ratio.
Another source of information is The Simpsons: A Complete Guide to Our Favorite
Family4 and Simpsons Forever: A Complete Guide to Our Favorite Family Continued.5
The Complete Guide's "Who Does the Voice?" section lists 59 male characters, to which
we would add Lionel Hutz, Troy McClure, Sideshow Bob and Sideshow Mel, for a total of
63, and 16 female characters.6 The Simpsons Forever adds five male characters (Database,
Dr. Loren J. Pryor, Mr. Bouvier, Gavin, and Billy) and one female one, sort of (the voice of
Malibu Stacy); but it also drops Jacqueline Bouvier and Aunt Gladys, presumably because
they are dead, in which case Maude Flanders should also be dropped.7
Finally, we have done our own head count. We would add Agnes Skinner, (Mrs.)
Helen Lovejoy, (Mrs.) Luanne Van Houten, Manjula (Apu's fiancée/wife), and Janey
Powell to the "Who's Who" list, which brings the total of recurring female characters to
fifteen. The roster is still far from inspiring: of the fifteen, six appear exclusively as wives
or mothers of much more fully developed male characters: Mrs. Bouvier, Maude Flanders,
Mrs. Lovejoy, Mrs. Van Houten, Agnes Skinner, and Manjula. Five are truly minor
characters who seldom speak: Sherri and Terri, the purple-haired twins, Janey Powell,
Lunchlady Doris, and Miss Hoover (Lisa's teacher). That leaves Selma and Patty, along
with Edna Krabappel, to represent working women (and since a defining characteristic of
all three is incessant chain-smoking, they do seem to be presented as "hardened and
undesirable," as Wood puts it). Only Ruth Powers, the Simpsons' divorced neighbor, is an
unattached adult female with a mind of her own (and she has had speaking parts in only
two episodes: "New Kid on the Block" and "Marge on the Lam").
Thus it comes as something of a shock (and here we merely choose one of many
critics who have expressed similar sentiments) to read, in James Poniewozik's essay for
Time magazine, "The Best TV Show Ever," that one of The Simpsons' strengths is:
It has TV's greatest cast. No other series has developed as numerous and fully fleshed a
supporting cast as the population of Springfield. The writers of "The Simpsons" opened worlds
within worlds, investing seemingly minor characters with full back stories and lives. Any character
who showed up for a few seconds in one episode might carry entire episodes later on: Apu,
Smithers, Barney the drunk. To look at one of these B-listers, Krusty the Clown, is to understand
the endless fertility of "The Simpsons." Beginning as a prop for Bart and Lisa to watch on the family
TV, Krusty developed a story of ethnic identity (born Herschel Krustofsky, he rebelled against his
rabbi father) and became a satiric stand-in for the entire entertainment industry.8
If "TV's greatest cast" is at least three quarters male, what does this say about the
mirror of reality TV holds up to us, the viewers? And it is no help to point out that The
Simpsons is a fun-house mirror, for in this instance, Springfield's majority male population
is not an ironic commentary on television as usual, but rather an unquestioning extension of
the norm.
That the population of Springfield skews so heavily male might in and of itself
seem to be a minor matter, but it takes on an added significance when the content and focus
of the episodes themselves are considered. Of the 248 episodes broadcast through the first
eleven seasons, "The Lisa File"9 lists 28 "Lisa Episodes," to which we would add eight
more titles.10 "The Marge File"11 has an obviously incomplete list of episodes which might
be claimed to focus on Marge; we put the total at 21, even including those episodes which
"flash back" to Homer and Marge's courtship days. We have gone into some detail in order
to provide evidence for our claim that there is approximately the same ratio in episode
content that was to be found in the population of Springfield (that is, between four and five
times as many episodes are focused on Bart, Homer, or another male character as episodes
devoted to Lisa, Marge, or another female character12). Those fond of conspiracy theories
will be entertained to note that, according to The Simpsons Archive article "Simpsons
Guest Stars," there have been exactly 160 male guest stars (not counting multiple
appearances of Phil Hartman, Albert Brooks, Jon Lovitz, etc.) and 40 female guest stars.13
In the large majority of cases these guest stars were playing themselves, so the skewed
male-female ratio extends even to the guest list.
The Content of Their Character
Marge is directly descended from a long line of saintly and long-suffering TV
wives and mothers whose main dramatic function is to understand, love, and clean up after
her man. Of course this lovely creature pre-existed television; Virginia Woolf described
her with taxonomic precision in her essay "Professions for Women" by the name "The
Angel in the House":
You who come of a younger and happier generation may not have heard of her -- you may not know
what I mean by The Angel in the House. I will describe her as shortly as I can. She was intensely
sympathetic. She was immensely charming. She was utterly unselfish. She excelled in the difficult
arts of family life. She sacrificed herself daily. If there was chicken, she took the leg; if there was a
draught, she sat in it -- in short she was so constituted that she never had a mind or wish or her own,
but preferred to sympathize always with the minds and wishes of others.14
Marge is not quite so angelic a character, perhaps, but her small-screen foremothers
are easy to identify: Alice Kramden bore with her irascible Ralph, Edith Bunker with
Archie's unpredictable outbursts, and Marion Cunningham with her entire wacky family in
much the same all-forgiving spirit that Marge uses with Homer. Patricia Mellencamp,
discussing the archetypal fifties sitcom, Father Knows Best, points out that a staple of
domestic situation comedy is a portrayal of the "comic containment of women" in
traditional domestic roles.15 An attempt to break out of the traditional female role is
obviously funny, and a large number of Marge episodes trade on precisely this kind of
humor. The other main aspect of the "comic containment of women" is on display in the
efforts of the traditional wife to uphold etiquette, moral, or legal standards; this transforms
her into the familiar "nag" which makes her the butt of much male humor, and here too,
Marge more than fits the mold.
At first blush, Marge is insurgent as a television mom. Her blue well-coiffed hair
and yellow skin make her visually startling. On closer inspection, however, she remains
well within the boundaries of television-motherhood in the late 1950s and early 1960s. The
well-coiffed hair recalls mothers from Harriet Nelson to June Cleaver. Her pearl necklace
recalls Margaret Anderson (Father Knows Best), June Cleaver, Donna Stone (The Donna
Reed Show), and even Wilma Flintstone. Whether in the house or in public, Marge wears
the conventional dress of her late 1950s and early 1960s predecessors. The dress of the
television mom was only briefly subverted by Morticia Addams and Lily Munster between
1964 and 1966. And like many of her lineage, motherhood has made her relatively asexual,
yet all the while, traditionally feminine.
Recall that the first sexualized T.V. moms -- Morticia Addams and Lily Munster --
were, quite simply, freaks of nature (Lily and Herman Munster were the first TV couple to
share a bed).16 The first truly sexually defined television mother, Peg Bundy, gained her
sexuality by a kind of grudging non-participation in the traditionally female familial roles;
although she did not work outside the home, she did not do housework, either, and she
certainly did not mother. The first TV mom to completely subvert all traditional maternal
roles is South Park's Mrs. Cartman. Mrs. Cartman challenges traditional maternal roles
insofar as she is a calamitous contradiction. She recognizes motherhood as a role, even a
facade (and she is not very good at it), as she drinks, smokes crack, and is sexually
promiscuous. If we indulge ourselves for a moment and construct a continuum of
television mothers from say, Harriet Nelson to Mrs. Cartman, we see that Marge remains
firmly within the tradition of television motherhood of the 1950s and 1960s.
There is yet another way in which Marge remains deeply traditional as a television
mother; not only is she in terms of temperament mostly Virginia Woolf's "Angel," but like
so many of her predecessors, she remains "in the house." Recall that Harriet Nelson never
left the house, nor did June Cleaver, Donna Stone, Morticia Addams, Lily Munster,
Samantha Stevens, and others. Many traditional television moms who did work outside the
home (such as Elyse Keaton or Clair Huxtable) did their work largely off camera to insure
that it would not interfere with mothering. So too the case with Marge Simpson; married
women do not work in the world of The Simpsons, so the drama of her life usually unfolds
within the confines of the house on Evergreen Terrace.
The house on Evergreen Terrace is a bastion of domestic harmony and moral
serenity. Springfield, representative of the public sphere, is marked by moral decay,
whether it be the gluttonous capitalism of Mr. Burns or the drunkenness at Moe's. This is
not to suggest that the Simpson home itself is never morally challenged, but it is morally
challenged when the private sphere is threatened with subversion by the public. Often
Groening and the writers will allow evil to invade the house through television (Krusty the
Clown and especially Itchy and Scratchy, but also slightly more subtly, in Kent
Brockman's obviously biased newscasts, or Troy McClure's unctuous infomercials). But
the home remains ultimately impervious to moral disintegration; the family remains intact
and morally functional.
Marge is often the only adult defender of moral and aesthetic values, and as such
recalls "The Angel in the House" and her legendary purity. She takes on violence in
cartoons ("Itchy and Scratchy and Marge") and wasteful public projects ("Marge vs. the
Monorail"), and defends the artistic merit of Michelangelo's David. She is even able to get
Homer to quit drinking, at least for a month ("Duffless"). The flashbacks to Homer and
Marge's courtship reveal a completely conventional story of Homer pursuing Marge by
arranging to be tutored by her in French; when she discovers that he is not even taking
French, it is too late -- they are in love, and Marge is firmly on course for life with a man
who would try the patience of a saint. We are not surprised to hear the litany of quite
reasonable complaints she makes during her first visit to a marriage counselor:
He's so self-centered. He forgets birthdays, anniversaries, holidays -- both religious and secular --
he chews with his mouth open, he gambles, he hangs out in a seedy bar with bums and lowlifes. He
blows his nose on the towels and puts them back in the middle. He drinks out of the carton. He
never changes the baby. When he goes to sleep, he makes chewing noises. When he wakes up,
he makes honking noises. Oh, oh, and he scratches himself with his keys. I guess that's it. ("The
War of the Simpsons")
Although Marge does occasionally take jobs ("Marge Gets a Job," "Marge in
Chains," "Springfield Connection," "Realty Bites," "The Twisted World of Marge"), or
even snaps from the strain of her daily life and takes off for a break at Rancho Relaxo
("Homer Alone"), she is always back (or unemployed) by the end of the episode. Far more
usual are the scenarios which require her to bail out Homer or play along with some wild
scheme of his, often for no very obvious reason, as when he begs her to pretend to be Apu's
wife in order to fool Apu's mother into believing that he is already married, which involves
(among other things), putting Apu's mother up at their house, while Homer basks in
irresponsibility out at the Springfield Retirement Castle.17 This is tantamount to asking
Marge to participate in two marriages, when her marriage to Homer obviously provides all
the burdens one woman can possibly be expected to bear. This is wifehood above and
beyond the call of duty, or even what fifties and sixties sitcom moms were expected to
handle, and as such makes Marge the undisputed champion of the genre.
Lisa's crisis in "Separate Vocations," when the school aptitude test (Career
Aptitude Normalizing Test or CANT) has predicted that her future career will be
"homemaker," is especially revealing with respect to Marge's role. First we see Lisa at her
desk, writing "Dear log: This will be my last entry, for you were a journal of my hopes and
dreams. And now, I have none." The next morning, when she comes down to breakfast,
grumbling, Marge attempts to convince her of the creativity of homemaking by pointing
proudly to the smiley faces she has created on Bart and Homer's plates with bacon, eggs
and toast.
LISA: What's the point? They'll never notice.
MARGE: You'll be surprised.
Of course, Bart and Homer come to the table and obliviously wolf down their food
without a word to Marge.
Angel that she is, Marge only allows herself the smallest murmur of
disappointment; it's Lisa who is truly aghast at the unsentimental truth about the
thanklessness of housework, even though she had predicted Bart and Homer's reaction (or
lack thereof) accurately moments before. So Marge is, in an important sense, even worse
off than her predecessors. Although their sacrifices may have been largely invisible and
unappreciated, at least in the terms that matter most on television: screen time, lines, and
plots devoted to their characters, they were at least respected. Marge's whole way of life is
openly despised by Lisa, and this, too, is something Marge resignedly accepts.
It must be admitted that Homer is conscious of needing her, as his immortal lines
from the episode "Marge in Chains" proves. As Marge is being hauled off to jail to serve
her sentence for shoplifting from the Kwik-E-Mart, Homer moans: "Marge, I'm going to
miss you so much. And it's not just the sex. It's also the food preparation." Marge does have
one enormous advantage over her counterparts in non-animated shows: even after many
years of marriage and three children, she has a satisfying sex life. From the twin beds of
Rob and Laura Petrie on The Dick Van Dyke Show to the constant marital sniping of Peg
and Ted Bundy on Married with Children, television writers have both implicitly and
explicitly depicted marriage as the death of sex (at least between husband and wife). The
Simpsons' departure from the television norm in this respect may partially explain Marge's
curiously anachronistic personality: she has to be the ultimate loving and accepting wife in
order for viewers to embrace Homer as the inimitable boob that he is. No matter what mad
stunt he pulls, from joining the Movementarians sect to climbing Mount Springfield, no
matter how much his shenanigans cost in property damages, legal fees, or self-respect, we
know Marge will rescue him and take him back.
If Marge is in some respects a throwback to the loving, giving, and self-effacing TV
wives and mothers of TV's golden age, and this explains her limited role, the same kind of
explanation will not work for Lisa, who is if anything ahead of her time. In the brief shorts
on The Tracey Ullman Show which introduced the Simpson family as characters, Lisa was
little more than Bart's partner in crime, and there are still episodes in recent seasons in
which Bart and Lisa are an effective team, although the goals of their activities tend to be
higher-minded now. This is seen in the exposure of voter fraud in "Sideshow Bob
Roberts," or trying to effect Krusty's reconciliation with his estranged father in "Like
Father, Like Clown."
Lisa has become a complex character and the writers do a good job of allowing the
different sides of her personality to emerge, without ever entirely abandoning the fiction
that the speaker of their words is supposed to be an eight-year-old, albeit a highly
intelligent one. Lisa has a crush on a substitute teacher, begs her father for a pony, is upset
by an unflattering caricature, is jealous of other (smart) girls, and fights with her brother.
Yet she also suffers existential despair, plays the sax like a Marsalis, wins essay contests,
displays rare mathematical and scientific ability, and joins Mensa. So why is this dynamic
and intelligent character not more of a presence on the show?
One possibility might lie in the supposed unpopularity of her views: some critics
have pigeonholed Lisa as little more than a precocious feminist, based on her rejection of
Marge's limited life and her penchant for crusades, such as her campaign to reform the
entire doll industry in "Lisa versus Malibu Stacy," which seems to appear on almost every
"best episodes" list. Lisa objects to the silly and sexist things her new talking Malibu Stacy
doll has been programmed to say, and in her usual take-charge manner goes straight to the
top to confront Malibu Stacy's creator. An interview with the actress who does Lisa's voice,
Yeardley Smith, reveals that she felt that the writers were trying to strike an elusive balance
on a difficult subject in the Malibu Stacy episode: "I'm always proud of Lisa when she
stands up on principle and does that stuff, but I get a little worried when she gets too
principled and doesn't act enough like an eight-year-old."18
Sometimes the crusade is moral, as in "Homer vs. Lisa and the 8th
Commandment," when Lisa tries to convince her family and especially Homer that it is
wrong to steal cable; even law-abiding Marge vacillates, and Lisa needs the entire episode
to prevail. Vegetarianism is another of Lisa's moral causes, but in this instance she does not
succeed in persuading the other Simpsons, although it might be argued that the most
important moral lesson of "Lisa the Vegetarian" comes at the end, when Lisa the vegetarian
learns tolerance from Apu the vegan. Some writers identify Marge and Lisa in this respect,
but the comparison usually redounds to Lisa's credit:
Like her mother, she possesses strong ethical virtues. Although Marge has accepted the lesser
sins as a part of society, Lisa advocates morality in any situation. . . With her honest principles, Lisa
is disillusioned by corruption in society, often making her "the saddest kid in grade number two."19
It is Lisa the intellectual20 -- the overachiever to Bart's under-achiever -- who gets
the most attention, at least from critics. One typical description reduces her to nothing more
than this:
Lisa Simpson, like Homer, is governed by one trait. She is the site of rationality. Lisa acts as the
voice of reason, questioning with a critical eye the motives and behavior of other characters. Her
intelligence, however, only makes her an outcast. The family usually ignores her advice and she
has few friends at school. She is often at odds with the entire community, suggesting the dismissal
of reason in American culture.21
From her God-like powers in the "Treehouse of Horror VII" episode, "The Genesis
Tub," in which she creates an entire race of tiny people, to her mathematical abilities in
"Lisa the Greek," to her hard-headed insistence on a scientific explanation for the
angel-shaped fossil she found at the ground-breaking for the new mall in "Lisa the
Skeptic," we are given a quirky but clearly recognizable portrait of a nerd. And the "smart
kid," male or female, has always been a relatively minor character, at least on television.
We think that the main reason why only around 15 percent of the episodes are
focused on Lisa is not just her feminism or intellectual gifts. Indeed, the variations on the
oft-cited idea that Lisa is somehow Bart's opposite confuse rather than explain the issue,
for if they are genuinely opposites, we might reasonably expect them to receive
approximately equal time. Jeff MacGregor, in The New York Times, defends one of the
most articulate versions of this view when he observes:
Bart and Lisa, the scapegrace and overachiever, the delinquent yin and bookish yang, id and
superego of American children everywhere, are characters far richer and more fully evoked than
the one-dimensional little wisenheimers so often seen dissing their parents on other sitcoms. Their
fears and neuroses prevent these two from becoming simple punch-line delivery platforms in the
manner of the Olsen twins.22
What MacGregor perhaps has seen is that for most people (and arguably American
culture in general), there is far more psychic energy invested in the id (Bart) than in the
superego (Lisa). The Simpsons needs Lisa for psychic balance, but in a very real sense it
does not need too much of her. She is not the yang to Bart's yin, for this image assumes
complementarity if not equality of influence, which we have abundantly proven not to be
the case.
A related aspect of the unusually philosophical dimensions of Lisa's personality
emerges most clearly in "They Saved Lisa's Brain," the episode in which Lisa is secretly
invited to join the Springfield chapter of Mensa. Even in comparison with her fellow
Mensa members, she quickly shows herself to be a Utopian and an idealist. After Mayor
Quimby abdicates and the Mensa members have become the new government of
Springfield, Lisa is astonished at how quickly even very smart people can become
narrowly partisan and argumentative. Even Steven Hawking cannot quite convince her that
her dream of the common good is an unrealizable mirage. Since most societies have been
able to tolerate at most one idealist or reformer without martyring him or her, the Simpson
family should probably be given high marks for the degree to which they embrace theirs.
Good Girls and Dumb Guys
It must, of course, be recognized that episodes of The Simpsons often provide a rich
parody of television, family, and a host of other cultural institutions and conventions.
Therefore, an all-too-serious deconstruction of the text risks effacing the humor and
scathing social commentary that have sustained it through eleven seasons to a
demographically diverse audience. Still, the series demands analysis within the very genre
of the television situation comedy it so often, and so perceptively, parodies.
The demographics of Springfield, as we have seen, precisely mirror the
demographics of the television world writ large. In Springfield (and in most of television),
it is a man's world, even if the men (and boys) are in large measure bumbling idiots. The
male characters in The Simpsons, like the characters in most of mainstream television
comedy over the last half-century, (dys)function in a public world of work and commerce,
of public recreation and entertainment. And the public world in which these men
(dys)function is all too often a bitter world of moral challenge, a truly postmodern arena
devoid of meaningful social structure and lacking a moral center. And it is to the credit of
Groening and the writers that this public world is so wittily examined, disentangled, and
sometimes turned upside down. It is equally ironic, then, that Homer and Bart, like so
many in television land before them, are able to come home to the house on Evergreen
Terrace that despite all its eccentricities, remains an asylum in a postmodern world. The
home on Evergreen Terrace remains a place not unlike the home of the Nelsons, the
Cleavers, and the Munsters, a place where the center does hold, and where things
(ultimately) do not fall apart, and where Marge Simpson faithfully waits, the "Angel in the
House."
Might one respond to our observations by complaining that we have missed the
point, that The Simpsons is intended as parody of "the normal American family in all its
beauty and horror."23 We think not: the ideal of the family does not come in for anything
like the skewering bestowed on other targets. Take the case of capitalism: Mr. Burns is to a
great degree capitalism personified. Most often, Mr. Burns is presented as an exaggerated
characterization of the Friedmanesque free-wheeling capitalist whose telos is profit, whose
raison d'être is greed. In the character of Mr. Burns we have an effective caricature of the
relentless capitalist. Like all effective satirists, Groening is able to offer up some biting
criticisms of the capitalist world-view by exaggerating or magnifying that view. Put
another way, Mr. Burns shows us the logical conclusion of the capitalist world-view when
it is unchecked by other fundamental moral or social commitments. Still, Mr. Burns is not
merely the personification of capitalist greed, but a character in his own right, insofar as he
has occasional moments of angst, if not existential despair, as a direct result of his
unwavering capitalist machinations. In a similar vein, it might well be argued that the
character of Marge (like Mr. Burns) is a parody of the culturally constructed ideal of wife
and mother, an exaggerated spoof meant only to reveal the ultimately vacuous nature of her
roles. There is, no doubt, some merit to this view.
However, if we read the character of Marge as largely satirical in nature, problems
emerge. First, satire, by its nature, requires that we take an all-too-familiar cultural
convention (capitalism, religion, motherhood. . .) and exaggerate its most salient
characteristics to a very great degree, thereby revealing absurdities latent within the
cultural convention itself, but then revealed through the satiric exaggeration of that
convention or idea. The character of Marge does not exaggerate motherhood, wifehood, or
femininity nearly to the extent that the character of Burns exaggerates and lampoons
capitalism, or the Reverend Lovejoy satirizes postmodern religion. Burns takes capitalism
to its logical conclusion and reveals it to be a barren way of life. Marge, by contrast, does
not take the conventions she embodies to their logical conclusions, she does not exaggerate
them grossly, and she certainly does not reveal them to be vacuous or superficial. Secondly,
parody (at its best) reveals to us an aspect of something heretofore not seen or appreciated.
It jars us from our complacencies by showing us where a convention or idea may end up if
unfettered by other ideas or conventions. In the case of Mr. Burns and capitalism we are
reminded of the lineaments of unfettered capitalist pursuits (environmental destruction,
exploitation of workers, self-loathing, and loneliness). Not so with Marge: not only does
she not seem a grossly exaggerated portrayal of wifehood or motherhood, her character is
continuous with the virtues we know so well from her predecssors. Marge presents the
viewer with a valorized and largely affectionate view of a woman who rules as wife and
mom.
Groening and company are to be saluted for their originality in expanding the moral
center with the character of Lisa as "the Idealist in the House" (with apologies to Virginia
Woolf). Not merely the voice of reason, Lisa emerges as fully human, giggling at Itchy and
Scratchy cartoons, gleefully participating in the grease fight which interrupts a school
dance, and risking her life to rescue precious airline tickets for her family. In the fullness of
time, she has even succeeded in changing Bart's behavior for the better, at least to some
extent. An early example can be found in the second season's "Bart Gets an F"; after Bart
has prayed for one more day to study for a test, and received it in the form of a freak
snowstorm, he is tempted to forget studying and play in the snow. It is Lisa who reminds
him: "I heard you last night, Bart. You prayed for this. Now your prayers have been
answered. I'm not a theologian. I don't know who or what God is exactly. All I know is He's
a force more powerful than Mom and Dad put together and you owe him big." Bart studies
(and passes).
In the fourth season, Lisa and Bart work together to expose the horrible conditions
at "Kamp Krusty," the cruelty to animals of "Whacking Day," and help Krusty revitalize
his image in "Krusty gets Kancelled." Season Six features Lisa and Bart pitted against one
another as athletic rivals in pee-wee hockey, egged on by most of adult Springfield,
including Homer. As the game comes down to a final penalty shot, Bart and Lisa take off
their equipment and embrace; the game ends in a tie ("Lisa on Ice"). It is one thing to rise
above the inanity of the ethos of winning at any cost, especially for boys, but the true
measure of Lisa's influence on Bart can be seen in "The Secret War of Lisa Simpson." As
the lone female cadet at Rommelwood Military Academy, Lisa's faith in her ability to cope
with the hazing and demanding physical tests begins to flag as she becomes increasingly
isolated. At first Bart will only help her train in secret, but at the crucial moment during the
dreaded rope test, he risks ostracism from the other boys by shouting words of
encouragement. Lisa finishes successfully.
A kind of symmetry has been achieved: Bart the under-achiever has grown
sufficiently (by the end of the eighth season) to put the private value of family loyalty
ahead of even male solidarity in a public setting. Moral truths that only Lisa could see in
earlier seasons (keep your promises, protect the vulnerable, even if they are snakes, stand
by your friends) have been adopted by Bart to the extent that he actually acts nobly on his
own, without prompting from Marge or Lisa (this interpretation conveniently ignores the
fact that Bart did give Lisa the silent treatment at the beginning of the episode).
The real acid test for the influence of Lisa's moral idealism is not, of course, Bart,
but Homer. The time frame here is of necessity even longer -- in fact, Homer's only explicit
recognition of Lisa's worth comes in the flash-forward episode "Lisa's Wedding." Now 23,
Lisa has met and fallen in love with Hugh Parkfield, an upper-class Englishman who shares
her interest in the environment, high opinion of the art of Jim Carrey, and typically
humorless vegetarianism. When she returns to Springfield for the wedding, Homer is
overcome with emotion:
HOMER: Little Lisa, Lisa Simpson. You know, I always felt you were the best thing that my
name has ever been attached to. Since the time you learned to pin your own diapers, you've been
smarter than me.
LISA: Oh, Dad --
HOMER: No, no, let me finish. I just want you to know that I've always been proud of you.
You're my greatest accomplishment and you did it all yourself. You've helped me understand my
own wife better and taught me to be a better person, but you're also my daughter, and I don't think
anyone could have a better daughter than you.
LISA: Dad, you're babbling.
HOMER: See? You're still helping me.
Despite a valiant effort, Hugh is somewhat put off and alarmed by Lisa's family,
and when he offhandedly remarks that it will be a relief to get back to England and not have
to deal with them, she calls off the wedding. This is a vital moment in the development of
Lisa's character. Despite the broad hint given in "Lisa the Simpson," in which Lisa
discovers stupidity to be a sex-linked trait appearing in all male Simpsons (which seems to
imply that her talents and intelligence may yet take her far from Springfield and her family),
Lisa's reaction to criticism of her family shows that her love for them will perhaps, as it
were, outweigh the promise of her intelligence. One episode does not define Lisa's
character, and one can even hope that love for family can be maintained along with the
promise of intelligence, but Lisa's choice to remain in the quagmire of Simpson family life
suggests that her promise is yet to be realized. In an interview in Loaded Magazine
Groening himself addresses this concern with the character of Lisa. "The men have no
self-awareness at all in The Simpsons and the women are on the verge of gaining some. I
think that Lisa might escape Springfield eventually so there's hope for her."24 Lisa's
promise is yet to be fulfilled.
Marge is the guardian of the home and the refuge to which Homer and Bart return
every episode, and we know that she is too important in that role to ever be more than
temporarily released from it. In any case, she is too good to succeed in the harsh and
corrupt public sphere. After all, she failed to sell a single house during her brief
employment at Lionel Hutz's Red Blazer Realty, not because she was a woman but because
she was unable to lie to her clients. Lisa, too, will never really grow up or leave home
because she is too important as moral exemplar. Marge reassures her boys that she loves
them just the way they are; Lisa makes them want to be better, and guides them in the
direction of that possibility. These are wonderful and dramatically significant roles, and
seem to attribute the best human qualities exclusively to the female of the species. Yet to be
an inspiration to dumb guys everywhere (as well as those in your own family) is to still
leave unquestioned the position of those dumb guys squarely at the center of life's stage.
1 Gerd Steiger, "The Simpsons: Just Funny or More?" The Simpsons Archive,
http://www.snpp.com/other/papers/gs.paper.html.
2 Gendered Lives: Communication, Gender, and Culture (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1994), p. 232.
Donald M. Davis finds a similar pattern in prime-time television: men are 65.4 percent of all prime-time
television characters, women 34.6 percent ("Portrayals of Women in Prime-Time Network Television: Some
Demographic Characteristics," Sex Roles 23: 325-332).
3 "Who's Who? In Springfield" http://snpp.com/guides/whoiswho.html.
4 Matt Greening, Ray Richmond, ed., New York: Harperperennial Library, 1997.
5 Matt Greening, Scott M. Gimple, ed., New York: Harperperennial Library), 1999.
6 A Complete Guide, pp. 178-79.
7 Simpsons Forever, pp. 86-87.
8 http://www.time.com/time/daily/special/simpsons.html
9 The Simpsons Archive, "The Lisa File," created by Dave Hall, maintained by Dale G. Abersold,
http://www.snpp.com/guides/lisa.file.html.
10 "Round Springfield," "Make Room For Lisa," "They Saved Lisa's Brain," "Desperately Xeeking
Xena" from Treebouse of Horror X, "Little Big Mom," "Bart to the Future," "Last Tap Dance in Springfield,"
and "Lisa Gets an A."
11 http://www.snpp.com/guides/marge.file.html
12 Only Patty and Selma, in "Homer vs. Patty and Selma," "A Fish Called Selma," "Selma's Choice"
and "Black Widower" and Mrs. Simpson, in "Mother Simpson" seem to have received this honor; "Lady
Bouvier's Mother" is clearly devoted to Grandpa.
13 http://www.snpp.com/guides/gueststars.html
14 William Smart (ed.), Eight Modern Essayists, 4th edition (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1985), p.
9.
15 Cited in June M. Frazer and Timothy C. Frazer, " 'Father Knows Best' and 'The Cosby Show':
Nostalgia and the Sitcom Tradition," Journal of Popular Culture, 13, p. 167.
16 Ray Richmond observes, "Until The Munsters, married folk on the air were required to sleep in
separate twin beds, which had to have made it awfully difficult to conceive the children who always kept
popping out. But Lily and Herman snuggled under the same sheets in a queen-size bed, the thinking evidently
being that they were kind of like cartoon characters, anyway, so it didn't really count. But it did." TV Moms:
An Illustrated Guide (New York: TV Books, 2000), p. 52.
17 Homer reflects on living in a retirement home: "It's like being a baby, only you're old enough to
appreciate it" ("The Two Mrs. Nahasapeemapetilons").
18 "Yeardley's Top Ten Episodes" in "The Simpsons Folder: Writings" at
http://springfield.simplenet.com/folder/yardley.html
19 John Sohn, "Simpson Ethics." The Simpsons Archive, http://www.snpp.com/ other/papers/js.
paper.html.
20 For a more complete analysis of Lisa's role in the portrayal of the intellectual, see Aeon J. Skoble's
essay, "Lisa and American Anti-Intellectualism," in this volume.
21 Sam Tingleff, "The Simpsons as a Critique of Consumer Culture," http://www.snpp.com/other
papers/st.paper.html.
22 "More Than Sight Gags and Subversive Satire," New York Times (20 June, 1999); also in The
Simpsons Archive, http://www.snpp.com/other/ articles/morethan.html.
23 Description of the Simpson family attributed to series executive producer James L. Brooks in
"The Simpsons: Just Funny or More?", by Gerd Steiger, The Simpsons Archive,
http://www.snpp.eom/other/papers/gs/.paper.html.
24 "And on the Seventh Day Matt Created Bart," The Simpsons, Archive,
http:/www.snpp.com/other/interviews/groening96.html.
Part III
I Didn't Do It:
Ethics and The Simpsons
10
The Moral World of the Simpson Family:
A Kantian Perspective
JAMES LAWLER
In a review of Harry Potter and the Goblet of Fire, by J.K. Rowling, science fiction
author Spider Robinson writes: "Okay, Harry himself is a bit of a goody-goody. . . in fact,
let's admit it: Harry is the AntiBart. But do you really want your own kids to have no better
role model than a Simpson?" (The Globe and Mail, 15 July 2000, p. D14).
As a role model for children, we don't have to choose between a goody-goody
Harry Potter and a hellion Bart Simpson. There is also, for example, Lisa Simpson. The
Simpsons is not reducible to any one of its parts but comes in the totality of its perspectives.
Failure to recognize the unique moral perspective of Lisa Simpson, and the representation
of the moral role model in the form of the "goody-goody" individual, suggests a narrow
view of moral goodness.
What is moral goodness? A central feature of the moral point of view, according to
Immanuel Kant, is a commitment to the performance of "duty." The term "duty" implies
the presence of two opposing forces. On the one hand, there are our spontaneous desires,
feelings and interests -- including our fears and hatreds, our jealousies and insecurities. On
the other hand, there is what one believes one ought to do and the kind of person one ought
to be. The term "duty" suggests that these two forces frequently come into conflict, and
consequently doing what one ought to do or trying to be what one ought to be can be
difficult or painful, involving sacrifices of various kinds. The individual who is committed
to maintaining a moral point of view -- the ideal moral role model -- is one who resolves to
subordinate, and to sacrifice if need be, personal desires, feelings and interests to duty -- for
the sake of doing the right thing or becoming the right kind of person.
Episodes of The Simpsons frequently highlight the conflict between personal desire,
feelings, or interests, on the one hand, and the sense of moral duty, on the other. Each
member of the Simpson family, including baby Maggie, contributes to the creation of a
complex moral atmosphere, in which morality stands out in its significance as duty
precisely because the contrary exists as well -- the passionate desires, feelings, and
interests of strong personalities. We will look briefly at the way these themes are played
out in the characters of Homer, Bart, and Marge, before focusing on the primary instance of
the dutiful moral person, in the character of Lisa. In this exposition it will become clear that
it is the entire Simpson family that ultimately resolves and surmounts the contradictions of
duty and desire.
Homer Between Moe and Flanders
Sometimes this conflict is underscored by a caricature of the sense of duty. Homer
Simpson exhibits a great ability to rationalize his desires and interests as constituting moral
duty itself, so that no difficult conflict arises for him. In "Dumbell Indemnity," Moe wants
Homer to destroy Moe's automobile so that Moe can collect on his insurance policy.
Homer feels intense pressure from the generally egotistical or me-first character Moe. He
is intimidated by the threat of Moe's sharp tongue and so wants to yield to his friend's
insistent demand. Moe as a rule puts his own personal desires and interest first and has little
or no concern for any conflicting moral duty. By contrast, Homer has a moment of doubt in
which he wonders whether or not he is doing the right thing. He consults his "conscience,"
which takes the form of a mental picture of his wife Marge talking to him. Laughably,
"Marge" tells him quite definitively: his duty consists in destroying Moe's car so that Moe
can collect on the insurance. His "conscience" thereby satisfied, Homer proceeds with
characteristic energy to perform the "dutiful" action.
Though in a satirical manner, the episode clearly raises the moral perspective of
duty. Rather than providing a positive role model, Homer Simpson here shows us how not
to act. We laugh at this caricature of the moral situation, but at the same time we ask
ourselves whether or not our conceptions of moral obligation are not frequently determined
by a similar procedure.
Homer's moral dilemmas emerge in largely concrete ways, as when he must weigh
his love for Marge, and his duty to her as her husband, against his love for fishing and other
personal pursuits. Homer truly wants to be a good father and husband, but the appeal of
personal pleasures continually drives such dutiful thoughts out of his head. In "War of the
Simpsons," after a particularly flagrant demonstration of Homer's thoughtlessness, Marge
persuades Homer to attend a weekend marriage counseling session at Catfish Lake, led by
the Reverend Lovejoy. Although he recognizes the marital problem he has created, Homer
is mainly motivated by the possibility of catching the legendary giant catfish, "General
Sherman," "five hundred pounds of bottom-dwelling fury."
Early their first morning, Marge catches Homer, in full fishing regalia, trying to
sneak out of their cabin. How can he possibly think about fishing when their marriage is at
stake? Sincerely ashamed, Homer renounces his plan and takes a walk along the lakeside
instead. Seeing that someone has apparently left a fishing pole behind, Homer
conscientiously picks up the pole to return it to its owner. At that instant, General Sherman
takes the bait with a force that hurls Homer into a rowboat and drags him out to the middle
of the lake.
There ensues an epic battle of will and strength between man and beast, a lonely
and heroic struggle out of Ernest Hemingway's Old Man and the Sea. Homer, finally
victorious, returns to shore with great expectations of lasting fame as history's greatest
fisherman, only to find a furious Marge charging him with utter selfishness. Face to face
with the choice between selfish desire and moral duty, Homer renounces fame for family
and returns the gasping General Sherman to the watery depths. In surmounting such
powerful impulses of personal desire, Homer transmutes his physical exploit into a truly
great feat of moral heroism. Homer recognizes his dutiful sacrifice: "I gave up fame and
breakfast for our marriage."
The "goody-goody" Flanders is also at the counseling session with his wife. What
is the problem with their marriage, if such a question is thinkable? Ned's wife sometimes
underlines in his copy of the Bible! Flanders is an important figure in the moral universe of
The Simpsons, as he represents morality gone overboard, morality which no longer
involves a conflict with personal desires and interests because Flanders no longer
apparently has personal desires and interests.1 In this respect, Flanders is the opposite of
Moe. For there to be a real sense of moral duty, there must be two forces, not just one: an
awareness of moral duty and a healthy sense of individual desire, pleasure, and interest.
The two tendencies contain the possibility of conflict. Whereas Moe is decidedly out for
himself, Flanders, in his caricature of Christian morality, has no personal life whatsoever.
This point is humorously brought home in "Viva Ned Flanders," when the rather
youthful looking Flanders confesses that he is actually sixty years old. The reason for his
youthful appearance, Homer tells him, is that he hardly has a life of his own. Regretfully
accepting this analysis, he appoints Homer as his instructor on how to live.2 The outcome,
of course, is disastrous, involving a drunken double wedding in Las Vegas. Homer's
passion for immediate personal gratification is the inverse of Flanders's moralistic failure
to "have a life." Neither has much of a sense of the limits to their respective approaches to
life.
Even Bart Knows That's Wrong
Bart Simpson has a lot of his father in him. His is the devil-may-care attitude of the
fun-loving, trouble-seeking boy. In "Bart's Girlfriend," Bart develops a compulsive
infatuation with Reverend Lovejoy's daughter, Jessica. At first Bart thinks he has to
convert to Sunday school piety in order to win Jessica's affections. But Jessica only
becomes interested in him when she thinks she recognizes a possible partner in crime. This
episode illustrates the possibilities for moral hypocrisy3 when morality is identified with
conformity to an external code of behavior. As the minister's daughter, Jessica plays the
role of the "goody-goody" child for all that it is worth. She hypocritically plays on morality
to secure her selfish desires. But with Bart there are limits, a sense that enough is enough.
As Jessica steals from the collection basket in Church, Bart does his best to oppose the theft:
"Stealing from the collection basket is really wrong!" Bart tells her. "Even I know that."
When Bart gets blamed for the theft, he asks Jessica why he should protect her. She replies:
"Because, if you tell, no one will believe you. Remember I'm the sweet, perfect minister's
daughter, and you're just yellow trash."
Because of his usual devilishness, Bart's periodic acknowledgements of duty may
more effectively underline certain moral issues than would be the case with a
conventionally well-behaved child. In "Bart the Mother," Bart experiences a moving crisis
of conscience when his thoughtless antics lead to the death of a mother bird. Bart decides to
devote himself entirely to the raising of the parentless eggs, uncharacteristically sacrificing
his usual pleasures for the sake of his demanding charges. Life has its way of turning the
best of intentions, perhaps especially when grounded in emotional impulse, into the path to
hell. When it turns out that the eggs contain bird-eating reptiles, banned by federal law,
Bart stands by his charges. He tells his mother, "Everyone thinks they're monsters. But I
raised them, and I love them! I know that's hard to understand." Marge replies: "Not as hard
as you think."
In the end, Bart's lizards decimate the pesky pigeon population of Springfield and
Bart is celebrated as a town hero. Bart allows fame to smother whatever moral principle
underlay his original actions. "I don't get it, Bart," says sister Lisa. "You got all upset when
you killed one bird, but now you've killed tens of thousands, and it doesn't bother you at
all." But Bart has returned to his usual non-moral mode and can hardly focus his mind on
Lisa's ecologically relevant paradox.
Marge Stands Up for Herself
Marge is characteristically submerged in her role as the conventional wife and
mother without a life of her own.4 She becomes the focus of a high level of moral
awareness when she challenges and rises above her conventional upbringing. We have
duties to ourselves as well as to others, Kant insists. We have an obligation to develop the
talents within us to the best of our ability. The path to independent self-development can,
under certain circumstances, be a painful moral duty. It takes courage to stand up for your
own personal development when social pressures and upbringing insist on service, and
subservience, to others. Thus the great moral case of feminism is often put forward by
Marge, otherwise the traditional housewife.
In the episode, "Realty Bites," borrowing from the film Glengarry Glen Ross,
Marge takes a job as a real estate agent. She has had enough of having her selfless services
taken for granted by her family. She too is a person, with a right to a life of her own. Marge
wants a career in which she can prove her value and abilities to herself, to her family, and to
the larger society of Springfield. As she is introduced to her colleagues in the business, we
see that she's getting into a cut-throat, dog-eat-dog world. One agent venomously defends
her rights to the West Side, while an older man, looking like a broken Jack Lemmon, is on
the verge of complete personal demolition. Marge is unconscious of this environment at
first, as she enthusiastically and proudly dons the spiffy red jacket of her company.
The trouble is that Marge sincerely wants to help her customers and is prepared to
sacrifice her own interests for the sake of her perceived duty.5 Trusting Marge, friends and
neighbors defer to her opinion. Responding to that trust, Marge cannot help telling them
what she actually thinks about the houses they are interested in buying. Marge is nothing if
not honest with her customers, with whom she feels the ties of friendship in this tightly
connected community, and as a result she doesn't make the sales that ensure her a
continued place in the company. She fails to be "a closer."
Marge defends her approach to the suave manager, Lionel Hutz: "Well, like we say,
The right house for the right person!'" Lionel replies: "Listen, it's time I let you in on a little
secret, Marge. The right house is the house that's for sale. The right person is anyone." "But
all I did was tell the truth!" says Marge. "Of course you did," says Hutz. "But there's the
truth" (here he frowns and shakes his head negatively) "and the truth" (here he looks
cheerful and shakes his head positively). A sale could be made if she would only put her
product in the right light: call a tiny, cramped house "cozy," describe a ramshackle,
falling-down dump "a handy-man's dream," and so forth.
Marge is unconvinced, but eventually she must face the option: either fail at her job,
or do some shading of the truth. In the conflict between personal interest and moral duty,
we see how, because of underlying structures of competitive social organization, she is
pressured into choosing personal interest. Changing her approach, then, Marge makes a big
sale while concealing from the naively trusting Flanders family the fact that there was a
brutal murder in the house they are buying. She tries to find pleasure in the possession of
Flanders's check, the sign of her success in her chosen career, the tribute to her worth as a
person. But she feels guilty for what she believes is a betrayal of duty. Her sense of duty
ultimately triumphs over desire and self-interest. She decides to risk sacrificing everything
she has aspired to, and goes back to her customers with the whole story. It turns out that her
expectation of the Flanders's response had been quite wrong. They are delighted with the
adventure of living in a house with such an interesting, gruesome history. Paradoxically, in
this case complete honesty would have been, from the very beginning, the best policy.
After some initial fluctuation, Marge finally does her duty for the sake of duty, and
still achieves her personal goals. Isn't this the way life should always work? Why should
doing the right thing result in personal sacrifice? This brings us to a second major feature of
moral consciousness: If you do the right thing, somehow you ought to be rewarded. This
second feature of morality seems to contradict the first -- the tension and possible conflict
between duty and desire. But this tension is only momentary, Kant argues. Ultimately, in
the long run, moral duty and personal happiness ought to be reconciled. The "highest good"
and supreme moral duty is to create a world in which happiness arises out of the
performance of moral duty. People who do their duty ought to be rewarded; self-centered
people who pursue their goals at the expense of others ought to be punished.
Just as we are led to adopt this comfortable and consoling moral conclusion, Homer,
on a parallel escapade involving a struggle over a car, crashes his automobile into the
newly sold house. Emerging from the resulting rubble, Flanders turns to Marge and asks,
"Do you still have that check?" Marge resignedly hands it over and he tears it up. The
lesson? Do what you ought to do whatever the consequences.
Success in a career is not the most important thing in life. Marge returns to the
bosom of her family amidst cheers and, finally, respect. By her ultimate commitment to
moral principle she achieves an even higher reward than a big sale -- the happiness that
comes from experiencing the love and respect of her family. We periodically catch
glimpses of the "highest good," the unity of duty and happiness, in such luminous moments
of the Simpson household.
Lisa Stands Up for Principle
Dutiful moral consciousness is most graphically depicted in the character of
second-grader Lisa Simpson. Lisa has an acute sense of moral duty. Hers is not, however,
the self-assured, institutionally-based morality of Flanders, confident in the authority of his
Bible and Church. Lisa's morality arises out of precocious personal reflection on the great
themes of moral life: truthfulness, helping others in need, a commitment to human equality,
and justice. Lisa shows us how difficult it sometimes is to live up to such principles in the
face of thoughtless conventional compromises with the status quo. This points to another
central characteristic of morality, according to Kant. Morality is essentially
inner-determined. It arises out of personal reflection rather than from external social
conventions or authoritative religious teachings. It involves clarity and consistency in the
principles by which a person lives her life.
In "Lisa the Iconoclast," Lisa discovers that the legendary and supposedly heroic
founder of Springfield was actually a vicious pirate who tried to kill George Washington.
Lisa receives an "F" for her essay, "Jebediah Springfield: Superfraud." Her teacher
explains: "This is nothing but dead white male bashing by a P.C. thug. It's women like you
who keep the rest of us from landing a husband." Lisa is merely trying to tell the truth, as
she has discovered it. This is not the varnished truth of the selling profession, but objective,
historical, scientific truth, to be defended as an inherent value, no matter what the
consequences and no matter what the sacrifices.
Some truths about founders, however, need to be upheld against contemporary
practices. In "Mr. Lisa Goes to Washington," Lisa discovers that a certain politician is on
the payroll of private moneymakers. Lisa attempts to expose this perversion of the
founding ideals of American democracy. She takes her case to Thomas Jefferson himself.
As usual, Lisa takes a stand for principle and suffers for it. The easier path is to go along
with the crowd, not make waves, and turn a blind eye. Lisa fights City Hall.
Committed to fulfilling her duty as determined by consistent principles, Lisa
continually raises difficult questions. Is it right to eat meat, and so cause suffering to
innocent animals? In "Lisa the Vegetarian," Lisa identifies the lamb chop on her plate with
the sweet, defenseless lamb in the children's zoo. She generalizes from this experience and
militantly adopts vegetarianism. In standing up for consistent principles, she exemplifies a
central aspect of Kant's moral theory, which requires that we thoughtfully examine the
principles of our actions and eliminate contradictions between them. If it is wrong to harm
a helpless animal in a zoo, how can it be right to condone the slaughter of a similar animal
for our eating pleasure? This is one way to understand Kant's formulation of his
Categorical Imperative: "Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time
will that it should become a universal law."
In fighting for her principles, Lisa ruins Homer's barbecue party. Homer is angry
and Lisa feels ostracized from her family and the general community, until she finds refuge
on the roof garden of the vegetarian Hindu storeowner, Apu. There she finds a new
community with vegetarians Paul and Linda McCartney, where she finally feels that her
ideas will be respected. "When will all those fools learn that you can be perfectly healthy
simply eating vegetables, fruits, grains, and cheese?" But the mild Apu replies, "Oh,
cheese!" Lisa recognizes the arrogance of her sense of moral superiority on discovering
that others have higher standards. Apu, who will not even eat cheese, advises tolerance.
Lisa develops a more subtle moral understanding as a result of this experience: "I guess I
have been pretty hard on a lot of people. Especially my dad. Thank you, guys."
Lisa's Isolation
Lisa focuses attention on inescapable moral principles and makes people uneasy
with the conventional compromises. Hence she is typically isolated and suffers intensely
from her isolation. She yearns for respect and friendship. She too wants to be popular and
to be liked. Because she is a Simpson she is not a goody-goody. She is not someone who
finds happiness simply in doing what is acknowledged by all to be good. Like her brother,
Lisa is adventuresome, but her adventures are on the moral rather than on the physical
plane. Because of this, moral values are most sharply highlighted in the Lisa episodes --
positively, not negatively as in many of the Homer episodes, with principled consistency
rather than through the role-reversals of her mother.
In "The Secret War of Lisa Simpson," Lisa's moral isolation is graphically
illustrated in her encounter with the military academy. Bart is being sent to a military
academy on the theory that strict military discipline will control his wayward impulses. We
understand in Bart's successful adaptation to the school that this can hardly be the right way
to restrain possible tendencies to delinquency. "My killing teacher says I'm a natural," Bart
boasts. Such moral reflections on conventional social values frequently shout at the viewer
of The Simpsons. Is the objection really that there is not enough morality in this program, or
that there is too much morality -- too much of a critical perspective on our society, too
much of the Lisa Simpson outlook?
The episode focuses, however, not on Bart but on Lisa, who insists that she be
enrolled as well. Lisa is looking for the challenge that she can't find in the dumbed-down
curriculum of her school. She's also standing up for her right as a woman to equal treatment
with men. Her introduction as the first girl in the academy involves moving all the boys out
of their sleeping quarters -- hardly a good way to gain the acceptance Lisa is anxious to
achieve. Alone and facing a hostile male-chauvinist environment, Lisa consoles herself
with thoughts of Emily Dickinson. She too was lonely and yet was able to write beautiful
poetry, she reflects. And then, Lisa recalls, she went crazy as a loon!
Publicly, Bart goes along with the ostracism, afraid to acknowledge his sister.
Privately he apologizes: "Sorry I froze you out Lis. I, I just didn't want the guys to think I'd
gone soft on the girl issue." However, Bart secretly helps Lisa train at night on "The
Eliminator," a rope-crossing exercise at a vertiginous height, "with a blister factor of
twelve." Ultimately, Lisa conquers the obstacle, despite shouts of "drop, drop, drop" from
the boys. Bart finally stands up to the bullies, a sole but effective voice of encouragement.
Even Bart knows it's wrong to abandon a sister. I wonder if such a point could be made as
effectively by Harry Potter.
Lisa's Sorrow and the Saxophone
What makes Lisa more than a goody-goody kid is the fact that she is an acutely
sensitive person with a great desire for personal happiness. The conflictual nature of moral
duty, with its tendency to require personal sacrifice, is accordingly represented here in all
its poignancy. Hers is all the suffering that a commitment to self-determined principle
creates in a precocious, sensitive child. Her deep love of life and beauty, played out against
a no less profound commitment to truth and goodness, issues in the frustrations and
sorrows that she expresses in the woeful, yearning sounds of the jazz saxophone. Kant
holds that beauty and art bring into sensuous presence the possibilities of a higher moral
life. When actual life seems to pay little or no attention to such possibilities, the doleful cry
of Lisa's soul finds an outlet in the wail of a saxophone. In the character of Lisa, the
comedy of The Simpsons does not allow us to forget a depth of tragedy.
In the episode "Moaning Lisa" Lisa has trouble going along with conventional
patriotism. In a music class, instead of playing the simple notes of "My Country Tis of
Thee," Lisa improvises a soulful jazz solo on her saxophone. "There's no crazy bebop in
'My Country 'Tis of Thee,' " says the teacher. "But that's what my country's all about," Lisa
momentously declaims. "I'm wailing out for the homeless man living out of his car, the
Iowa farmer whose land has been taken away by unfeeling bureaucrats, the West Virginia
coal miner, caught. . ." "That's all well and good," says the teacher, "but, Lisa, none of those
unpleasant people are going to be at the recital next week."
A letter is sent home from school, critical for a change of Lisa, not Bart: "Lisa won't
play dodge ball because she is sad." The game of dodge ball seems particularly expressive
of Lisa's situation. One person is singled out for attack by all the others. Lisa just allows
herself to be bombarded, refusing to enter the spirit of the game by defending herself. We
should remember that this episode was made well before the onslaught of "Reality TV"
with its glorification of the Darwinian struggle for survival.
The main problem is that there seems to be no one with whom Lisa can
communicate the reasons that she feels are at the root of her melancholy. Bart and Homer
are engrossed in ferocious videogame slugfests. How can they understand her issues? Lisa
tries to explain: "I'm just wondering, what's the point? Would it make any difference at all
if I never existed? How can we sleep at night when there's so much suffering in the world?"
Homer tries to cheer her up by bouncing her on his knees. Perhaps it's an underwear thing,
he later surmises when Marge remarks on her difficult age. Homer has his heart, at least, in
the right place.
Lisa's gloomy mood first begins to lift when she hears the plaintive notes of fellow
saxophonist, Bleeding Gums Murphy, playing into the night on a lonely bridge in a
haunting moon-illuminated cityscape. Murphy's gums bleed because he has never been to
the dentist. "I have enough pain in my life," he says. Lisa tells about her own pain. "I can't
help you with that," he says, "but we can jam together."
Lisa and Bleeding Gums jam together -- "I'm so lonely, since my baby left me. . ."
And Lisa responds:
I got this bratty brother,
He bugs me every day,
And this morning my own mother
Gave my last cupcake away.
My dad acts like
He belongs in a zoo.
I'm the saddest kid
In grade number two.
Marge interrupts the session and commandeers Lisa. "Nothing personal," Marge
says to Bleeding Gums. "I just fear the unfamiliar."
Marge, in her persona as the conventional mother, advises Lisa to smile. That was
her own mother's advice to her: "Put your happy face on," her mother tells a young Marge
in a flashback, "because people know how good a mom you have by the size of your
smile." Lisa says she doesn't feel like smiling. Marge is firm: "Now Lisa, listen to me. This
is important. I want you to smile today. It doesn't matter what you feel inside, you know.
It's what shows up on the surface that counts. That's what my mother taught me. Take all
your bad feelings and push them down, all the way down, past your knees until you're
almost walking on them. And then you'll fit in, and boys will like you, and you'll be invited
to parties, and happiness will follow."
Lisa, perhaps desperate by now for some relief, follows her mother's advice. And it
works! "Hey," says one boy, "nice smile." Another tells the first boy, "What're you talking
to her for? She'll only say something weird." Lisa just continues to smile. "I used to think
you were some kind of braniac," says one of the boys, "but I guess you're OK." "Why don't
you come over to my house," says the other boy. "You can do my homework." "OK," says
Lisa. The teacher appears and says he hopes Lisa won't have "another outburst of unbridled
creativity." "No sir," Lisa answers, widely smiling.
Watching this scene, Marge recognizes the error of the traditional teaching, and
sweeps Lisa away with squealing tires. "So that's where she gets it," says the teacher,
revealing the deeper truth of the relation between Lisa and her mother. Marge apologizes to
Lisa. "I was wrong. I take it all back. Always be yourself. You want to be sad, honey, be
sad. We'll ride it out with you. And when you get finished feeling sad, we'll still be there.
From now on, I'll do the smiling for both of us."
Hearing this affirmation of her own feelings, Lisa genuinely smiles for the first
time. At Lisa's suggestion, the entire family goes to the club where Bleeding Gums pays
homage to "one of the great little ladies of jazz" and plays Lisa's song. In the company of
her happy and supportive family -- including baby Maggie sucking rhythmically on her
pacifier -- Lisa is beaming. The free, independent, dutiful individual deserves to be happy.
1 For a discussion of Ned's morality see Chapter 14 of this volume.
2 For a discussion of Homer's admirable "love of life," despite his moral shortcomings, see Chapter
1 of this volume.
3 For a detailed examination of hypocrisy see Chapter 12 of this volume.
4 For a feminist critique of Marge see Chapter 9 of this volume.
5 For a discussion of Marge being virtuous, as opposed to dutiful, see Chapter 4 of this volume.
11
The Simpsons:
Atomistic Politics and the Nuclear Family
PAUL A. CANTOR
When Senator Charles Schumer (D-N.Y.) visited a high school in upstate New
York in May 1999, he received an unexpected civics lesson and from an unexpected source.
Speaking on the timely subject of school violence, Senator Schumer praised the Brady Bill,
which he helped sponsor, for its role in preventing crime. Rising to question the
effectiveness of this effort at gun control, a student named Kevin Davis cited an example
no doubt familiar to his classmates but unknown to the Senator from New York: "It
reminds me of a Simpsons episode. Homer wanted to get a gun but he had been in jail twice
and in a mental institution. They label him as 'potentially dangerous.' So Homer asks what
that means and the gun dealer says: 'It just means you need an extra week before you can
get the gun.' "1 Without going into the pros and cons of gun control legislation, one can
recognize in this incident how the Fox Network's cartoon series The Simpsons shapes the
way Americans think, particularly the younger generation. It may therefore be worthwhile
taking a look at the television program to see what sort of political lessons it is teaching.
The Simpsons may seem like mindless entertainment to many, but in fact it offers some of
the most sophisticated comedy and satire ever to appear on American television. Over the
years, the show has taken on many serious issues: nuclear power safety, environmentalism,
immigration, gay rights, women in the military, and so on. Paradoxically it is the farcical
nature of the show that allows it to be serious in ways that many other television shows are
not.
I will not, however, dwell on the question of the show's politics in the narrowly
partisan sense. The Simpsons satirizes both Republicans and Democrats. The local
politician who appears most frequently in the show, Mayor Quimby, speaks with a heavy
Kennedy accent2 and generally acts like a Democratic urban machine politician. By the
same token, the most sinister political force in the series, the cabal that seems to run the
town of Springfield from behind the scenes, is invariably portrayed as Republican. On
balance, it is fair to say that The Simpsons, like most of what comes out of Hollywood, is
pro-Democrat and anti-Republican. One whole episode was a gratuitously vicious portrait
of ex-President Bush,3 whereas the show has been surprisingly slow to satirize President
Clinton.4 Nevertheless perhaps the single funniest political line in the history of The
Simpsons came at the expense of the Democrats. When Grandpa Abraham Simpson
receives money in the mail really meant for his grandchildren, Bart asks him: "Didn't you
wonder why you were getting checks for absolutely nothing?" Abe replies: "I figured
'cause the Democrats were in power again."5 Unwilling to forego any opportunity for
humor, the show's creators have been generally evenhanded over the years in making fun
of both parties, and of both the right and the left.6
Setting aside the surface issue of political partisanship, I am interested in the deep
politics of The Simpsons, what the show most fundamentally suggests about political life in
the United States. The show broaches the question of politics through the question of the
family, and this in itself is a political statement. By dealing centrally with the family, The
Simpsons takes up real human issues everybody can recognize and thus ends up in many
respects less "cartooonish" than other television programs. Its cartoon characters are more
human, more fully rounded, than the supposedly real human beings in many situation
comedies. Above all, the show has created a believable human community: Springfield,
USA. The Simpsons shows the family as part of a larger community, and in effect affirms
the kind of community that can sustain the family. That is at one and the same time the
secret of the show's popularity with the American public and the most interesting political
statement it has to make.
The Simpsons indeed offers one of the most important images of the family in
contemporary American culture, and in particular an image of the nuclear family. With the
names taken from creator Matt Groening's own childhood home, The Simpsons portrays
the average American family: father (Homer), mother (Marge), and 2.3 children (Bart, Lisa,
and little Maggie). Many commentators have lamented the fact that The Simpsons now
serves as one of the representative images of American family life, claiming that the show
provides horrible role models for parents and children. The popularity of the show is often
cited as evidence of the decline of family values in the United States. But critics of The
Simpsons need to take a closer look at the show and view it in the context of television
history. For all its slapstick nature and its mocking of certain aspects of family life, The
Simpsons has an affirmative side and ends up celebrating the nuclear family as an
institution. For television, this is no minor achievement. For decades American television
has tended to downplay the importance of the nuclear family and offer various one-parent
families or other non-traditional arrangements as alternatives to it. The one-parent situation
comedy actually dates back almost to the beginning of network television, at least as early
as My Little Margie (1952-55). But the classic one-parent situation comedies, like The
Andy Griffith Show (1960-68) or My Three Sons (1960-72), generally found ways to
reconstitute the nuclear family in one form or another (often through the presence of an
aunt or uncle) and thus still presented it as the norm (sometimes the story line actually
moved in the direction of the widower getting remarried, as happened to Steve Douglas,
the Fred MacMurray character, in My Three Sons).
But starting with shows in the 1970s like Alice (1976-85), American television
genuinely began to move away from the nuclear family as the norm and suggest that other
patterns of child rearing might be equally valid or perhaps even superior. Television in the
1980s and 1990s experimented with all sorts of permutations on the theme of the
non-nuclear family, in shows such as Love, Sidney (1981-83), Punky Brewster (1984-86),
and My Two Dads (1987-90). This development partly resulted from the standard
Hollywood procedure of generating new series by simply varying successful formulas.7
But the trend toward non-nuclear families also expressed the ideological bent of
Hollywood and its impulse to call traditional family values into question. Above all,
though television shows usually traced the absence of one or more parents to deaths in the
family, the trend away from the nuclear family obviously reflected the reality of divorce in
American life (and especially in Hollywood). Wanting to be progressive, television
producers set out to endorse contemporary social trends away from the stable, traditional,
nuclear family. With the typical momentum of the entertainment industry, Hollywood
eventually took this development to its logical conclusion: the no-parent family. Another
popular Fox program, Party of Five (1994-2000), shows a family of children gallantly
raising themselves after both their parents have been killed in an automobile accident.
Party of Five cleverly conveys a message some television producers evidently
think their contemporary audience wants to hear -- that children can do quite well without
one parent and preferably without both. The children in the audience want to hear this
message, because it flatters their sense of independence. The parents want to hear this
message, because it soothes their sense of guilt, either about abandoning their children
completely (as sometimes happens in cases of divorce) or just not devoting enough
"quality time" to them. Absent or negligent parents can console themselves with the
thought that their children really are better off without them, "just like those cool -- and
incredibly good-looking -- kids on Party of Five." In short, for roughly the past two
decades, much of American television has been suggesting that the breakdown of the
American family does not constitute a social crisis or even a serious problem. In fact it
should be regarded as a form of liberation from an image of the family that may have been
good enough for the 1950s but is no longer valid in the 1990s. It's against this historical
background that the statement The Simpsons has to make about the nuclear family has to be
appreciated.
Of course television never completely abandoned the nuclear family, even in the
1980s, as shown by the success of such shows as All in the Family (1971-1983), Family
Ties (1982-89), and The Cosby Show (1984-92). And when The Simpsons debuted as a
regular series in 1989, it was by no means unique in its reaffirmation of the value of the
nuclear family. Several other shows took the same path in the 1990s, reflecting larger
social and political trends in society, in particular the reassertion of family values that has
by now been adopted as a program by both political parties in the United States. Fox's own
Married with Children (1987-1998) preceded The Simpsons in portraying an amusingly
dysfunctional nuclear family. Another interesting portrayal of the nuclear family can be
found in ABC's Home Improvement (1991-99), which tries to recuperate traditional family
values and even gender roles within a postmodern television context. But The Simpsons is
in many respects the most interesting example of this return to the nuclear family. Though
it strikes many people as trying to subvert the American family or to undermine its
authority, in fact, it reminds us that anti-authoritarianism is itself an American tradition,
and that family authority has always been problematic in democratic America. What makes
The Simpsons so interesting is the way it combines traditionalism with anti-traditionalism.
It continually makes fun of the traditional American family. But it continually offers an
enduring image of the nuclear family in the very act of satirizing it. Many of the traditional
values of the American family survive this satire, above all the value of the nuclear family
itself.
As I have suggested, one can understand this point partly in terms of television
history. The Simpsons is a hip, postmodern, self-aware show.8 But its self-awareness
focuses on the traditional representation of the American family on television. It therefore
presents the paradox of an untraditional show that is deeply rooted in television tradition.
The Simpsons can be traced back to earlier television cartoons that dealt with families, such
as The Flintstones or The Jetsons. But these cartoons must themselves be traced back to the
famous nuclear family sitcoms of the 1950s: I Love Lucy, The Adventures of Ozzie and
Harriet, Father Knows Best, Leave it to Beaver. The Simpsons is a postmodern recreation
of the first generation of family sitcoms on television. Looking back on those shows, we
easily see the transformations and discontinuities The Simpsons has brought about. In The
Simpsons father emphatically does not know best. And it clearly is more dangerous to leave
it to Bart than to Beaver. Obviously The Simpsons does not offer a simple return to the
family shows of the 1950s. But even in the act of recreation and transformation, the show
provides elements of continuity that make The Simpsons more traditional than may at first
appear.
The Simpsons has indeed found its own odd way to defend the nuclear family. In
effect the shows says: "Take the worst-case scenario -- the Simpsons -- and even that
family is better than no family." In fact, the Simpson family is not all that bad. Some people
are appalled at the idea of young boys imitating Bart, in particular his disrespect for
authority and especially his teachers. These critics of The Simpsons forget that Bart's
rebelliousness conforms to a venerable American archetype and that this country was
founded on disrespect for authority and on an act of rebellion. Bart is an American icon, an
updated version of Tom Sawyer and Huck Finn rolled into one. For all his trouble-making
-- precisely because of his trouble-making -- Bart behaves just the way a young boy is
supposed to in American mythology, from Dennis the Menace comics to the Our Gang
comedies.9
As for the mother and daughter in The Simpsons, Marge and Lisa are not bad role
models at all. Marge Simpson is very much the devoted mother and housekeeper; she also
often displays a feminist streak, particularly in the episode in which she goes off on a jaunt
à la Thelma and Louise.10 Indeed she's very modern in her attempts to combine certain
feminist impulses with the traditional role of a mother. Lisa is in many ways the ideal child
in contemporary terms. She is an overachiever in school, and, as a feminist, a vegetarian,
and an environmentalist, she is politically correct across the spectrum.
The real issue, then, is Homer. Many people have criticized The Simpsons for its
portrayal of the father as dumb, uneducated, weak in character, and morally unprincipled.
Homer is all those things, but at least he is there. He fulfills the bare minimum of a father:
he is present for his wife and above all his children. To be sure, he lacks many of the
qualities we would like to see in the ideal father. He is selfish, often putting his own interest
above that of his family. As we learn in one of the Halloween episodes, Homer would sell
his soul to the devil for a donut (though fortunately it turns out that Marge already owned
his soul and therefore it was not Homer's to sell).11 Homer is undeniably crass, vulgar, and
incapable of appreciating the finer things in life. He has a hard time sharing interests with
Lisa, except when she develops a remarkable knack for predicting the outcome of pro
football games and allows her father to become a big winner in the betting pool at Moe's
Tavern.12 Moreover, Homer gets angry easily and takes his anger out on his children, as his
many attempts to strangle Bart attest.
In all these respects, Homer fails as a father. But upon reflection, it is surprising to
realize how many decent qualities he has. First and foremost, he is attached to his own -- he
loves his family because it is his. His motto basically is: "My family, right or wrong." This
is hardly a philosophic position, but it may well provide the bedrock of the family as an
institution, which is why Plato's Republic must subvert the power of the family. Homer
Simpson is the opposite of a philosopher-king; he is devoted not to what is best but to what
is his own. That position has its problems, but it does help explain how the seemingly
dysfunctional Simpson family manages to function.
For example, Homer is willing to work to support his family, even in the dangerous
job of nuclear power plant safety supervisor, a job made all the more dangerous by the fact
that he is the one doing it. In the episode in which Lisa comes to want a pony desperately,
Homer even takes a second job working for Apu Nahasapeemapetilon at the Kwik-E-Mart
to earn the money for the pony's upkeep and nearly kills himself in the process.13 In such
actions, Homer manifests his genuine concern for his family, and as he repeatedly proves,
he will defend them if necessary, sometimes at great personal risk. Often Homer is not
effective in such actions, but that makes his devotion to his family in some ways all the
more touching. Homer is the distillation of pure fatherhood. Take away all the qualities that
make for a genuinely good father -- wisdom, compassion, even temper, selflessness -- and
what you have left is Homer Simpson with his pure, mindless, dogged devotion to his
family. That is why for all his stupidity, bigotry, and self-centered quality, we cannot hate
Homer. He continually fails at being a good father, but he never gives up trying, and in
some basic and important sense that makes him a good father.
The most effective defense of the family in the series comes in the episode in which
the Simpsons are actually broken up as a unit.14 This episode pointedly begins with an
image of Marge as a good mother, preparing breakfast and school lunches simultaneously
for her children. She even gives Bart and Lisa careful instructions about their sandwiches:
"Keep the lettuce separate until 11:30." But after this promising parental beginning, a
series of mishaps occurs. Homer and Marge go off to the Mingled Waters Health Spa for a
well-deserved afternoon of relaxation. In their haste, they leave their house dirty,
especially a pile of unwashed dishes in the kitchen sink. Meanwhile, things are
unfortunately not going well for the children at school. Bart has accidentally picked up lice
from the monkey of his best friend Milhouse, prompting Principal Skinner to ask: "What
kind of parents would permit such a lapse in scalpal hygiene?" The evidence against the
Simpson parents mounts when Skinner sends for Bart's sister. With her prescription shoes
stolen by her classmates and her feet accordingly covered with mud, Lisa looks like some
street urchin straight out of Dickens.
Faced with all this evidence of parental neglect, the horrified principal alerts the
Child Welfare Board, who are themselves shocked when they take Bart and Lisa home and
explore the premises. The officials completely misinterpret the situation. Confronted by a
pile of old newspapers, they assume that Marge is a bad housekeeper, when in fact she had
assembled the documents to help Lisa with a history project. Jumping to conclusions, the
bureaucrats decide that Marge and Homer are unfit parents, and lodge specific charges that
the Simpson household is a "squalid hellhole and the toilet paper is hung in improper
overhand fashion." The authorities determine that the Simpson children must be given to
foster parents. Bart, Lisa, and Maggie are accordingly handed over to the family next door,
presided over by the patriarchal Ned Flanders. Throughout the series, the Flanders family
serves as the Doppelgänger of the Simpsons. Flanders and his brood are in fact the perfect
family according to oldstyle morality and religion. In marked contrast to Bart, the Flanders
boys, Rod and Todd, are well-behaved and obedient. Above all, the Flanders family is
pious, devoted to activities like Bible reading, more zealous than even the local Reverend
Lovejoy. When Ned offers to play "bombardment" with Bart and Lisa, what he has in mind
is bombardment with questions about the Bible. The Flanders family are shocked to learn
that their neighbors do not know of the serpent of Rehoboam, not to mention the Well of
Zahassadar or the bridal feast of Beth Chadruharazzeb.
Exploring the question of whether the Simpson family really is dysfunctional, the
foster parent episode offers two alternatives to it: on the one hand, the oldstyle
moral-religious family; on the other, the therapeutic state, what is often now called the
nanny state. Who is best able to raise the Simpson children? The civil authorities intervene,
claiming that Homer and Marge are unfit as parents. They must be re-educated and are sent
off to "family skills class," based on the premise that experts know better how to raise
children. Child rearing is a matter of a certain kind of expertise, which can be taught. This
is the modern answer: the family is inadequate as an institution and hence the state must
intervene to make it function. At the same time, the episode offers the oldstyle
moral-religious answer: what children need is godfearing parents in order to make them
godfearing themselves. Indeed Ned Flanders does everything he can to get Bart and Lisa to
reform and behave with the piety of his own children.
But the answer the show offers is that the Simpson children are better off with their
real parents -- not because they are more intelligent or learned in child rearing, and not
because they are superior in morality or piety, but simply because Homer and Marge are
the people most genuinely attached to Bart, Lisa, and Maggie, since the children are their
own offspring. The episode works particularly well to show the horror of the supposedly
omniscient and omnicompetent state intruding into every aspect of family life. When
Homer desperately tries to call up Bart and Lisa, he hears the official message: "The
number you have dialed can no longer be reached from this phone, you negligent monster."
At the same time we see the defects of the oldstyle religion. The Flanders may be
righteous as parents but they are also self-righteous. Mrs. Flanders says: "I don't judge
Homer and Marge; that's for a vengeful God to do." Ned's piety is so extreme that he
eventually exasperates even Reverend Lovejoy, who at one point asks him: "Have you
thought of one of the other major religions? They're all pretty much the same."
In the end, Bart, Lisa, and Maggie are joyously reunited with Homer and Marge.
Despite charges of being dysfunctional, the Simpson family functions quite well, because
the children are attached to their parents and the parents are attached to their children. The
premise of those who tried to take the Simpson children away is that there is a principle
external to the family by which it can be judged dysfunctional, whether the principle of
contemporary child-rearing theories or that of the oldstyle religion. The foster parent
episode suggests the contrary -- that the family contains its own principle of legitimacy.
The family knows best. This episode thus illustrates the strange combination of
traditionalism and anti-traditionalism in The Simpsons. Even as the show rejects the idea of
a simple return to the traditional moral-religious idea of the family, it refuses to accept
contemporary statist attempts to subvert the family completely and reasserts the enduring
value of the family as an institution.
As the importance of Ned Flanders in this episode reminds us, another way in
which the show is unusual is that religion plays a significant role in The Simpsons. Religion
is a regular part of the life of the Simpson family. Several episodes revolve around
churchgoing, including one in which God even speaks directly to Homer.15 Moreover,
religion is a regular part of life in general in Springfield. In addition to Ned Flanders, the
Reverend Lovejoy is featured in several episodes, including one in which no less than
Meryl Streep provided the voice for his daughter.16
This attention to religion is atypical of American television in the 1990s. Indeed,
judging by most television programs today, one would never guess that Americans are by
and large a religious and even a churchgoing people. Television generally acts as if religion
played little or no role in the daily lives of Americans, even though the evidence points to
exactly the opposite conclusion. Many reasons have been offered to explain why television
generally avoids the subject of religion. Producers are afraid that if they raise religious
issues, they will offend orthodox viewers and soon be embroiled in controversy; television
executives are particularly worried about having the sponsors of their shows boycotted by
powerful religious groups. Moreover, the television community itself is largely secular in
its outlook and thus generally uninterested in religious questions. Indeed, much of
Hollywood is often outright anti-religious, and especially opposed to anything labeled
religious fundamentalism (and it tends to label anything to the right of Unitarianism as
"religious fundamentalism").
Religion has, however, been making a comeback on television in the past decade,
in part because producers have discovered that an audience niche exists for shows like
Touched By An Angel (1994-).17 Still, the entertainment community has a hard time
understanding what religion really means to the American public, and it especially cannot
deal with the idea that religion could be an everyday, normal part of American life.
Religious figures in both movies and television tend to be miraculously good and pure or
monstrously evil and hypocritical. While there are exceptions to this rule,18 generally for
Hollywood religious figures must be either saints or sinners, either laboring against all
odds and all reason for good, or religious fanatics, full of bigotry, warped by sexual
repression, laboring to destroy innocent lives in one way or another.19
But The Simpsons accepts religion as a normal part of life in Springfield, USA. If
the show makes fun of piety in the person of Ned Flanders, in Homer Simpson it also
suggests that one can go to church and not be either a religious fanatic or a saint. One
episode devoted to Reverend Lovejoy deals realistically and rather sympathetically with
the problem of pastoral burnout.20 The overburdened minister has just listened to too many
problems from his parishioners and has to turn the job over to Marge Simpson as the "listen
lady." The treatment of religion in The Simpsons is parallel to and connected with its
treatment of the family. The Simpsons is not pro-religion -- it is too hip, cynical, and
iconoclastic for that. Indeed, on the surface, the show appears to be anti-religious, with a
good deal of its satire directed against Ned Flanders and other pious characters. But once
again we see the principle at work that when The Simpsons satirizes something, it
acknowledges its importance. Even when it seems to be ridiculing religion, it recognizes,
as few other television shows do, the genuine role that religion plays in American life.
It is here that the treatment of the family in The Simpsons links up with its treatment
of politics. Although the show focuses on the nuclear family, it relates the family to larger
institutions in American life, like the church, the school, and even political institutions
themselves, like city government. In all these cases, The Simpsons satirizes these
institutions, making them look laughable and often even hollow. But at the same time, the
show acknowledges their importance and especially their importance for the family. Over
the past few decades, television has increasingly tended to isolate the family -- to show it
largely removed from any larger institutional framework or context. This is another trend
to which The Simpsons runs counter, partly as a result of its being a postmodern recreation
of 1950s sitcoms. Shows like Father Knows Best or Leave it to Beaver tended to be set in
small-town America, with all the intricate web of institutions into which family life was
woven. In recreating this world, even while mocking it, The Simpsons cannot help
recreating its ambience and even at times its ethos.
Springfield is decidedly an American small town. In several episodes, it is
contrasted with Capital City, a metropolis the Simpsons approach with fear and trepidation.
Obviously the show makes fun of small-town life -- it makes fun of everything -- but it
simultaneously celebrates the virtues of the traditional American small town. One of the
principal reasons why the dysfunctional Simpsons family functions as well as it does is that
they live in a traditional American small town. The institutions that govern their lives are
not remote from them or alien to them. The Simpson children go to a neighborhood school
(though they are bussed to it by the ex-hippie driver Otto). Their friends in school are
largely the same as their friends in their neighborhood. The Simpsons are not confronted by
an elaborate, unapproachable, and uncaring educational bureaucracy. Principal Skinner
and Mrs. Krabappel may not be perfect educators, but when Homer and Marge need to talk
to them, they are readily accessible. The same is true of the Springfield police force. Chief
Wiggum is not a great crime-fighter, but he is well-known to the citizens of Springfield, as
they are to him. The police in Springfield still have neighborhood beats and have even been
known to share a donut or two with Homer.
Similarly, politics in Springfield is largely a local matter, including town meetings
in which the citizens of Springfield get to influence decisions on important matters of local
concern, such as whether gambling should be legalized or a monorail built. As his Kennedy
accent suggests, Mayor Quimby is a demagogue, but at least he is Springfield's own
demagogue. When he buys votes, he buys them directly from the citizens of Springfield. If
Quimby wants Grandpa Simpson to support a freeway he wishes to build through town, he
must name the road after Abe's favorite television character, Matlock. Everywhere one
looks in Springfield, one sees a surprising degree of local control and autonomy. The
nuclear power plant is a source of pollution and constant danger, but at least it is locally
owned by Springfield's own slave-driving industrial tyrant and tycoon, Montgomery Burns,
and not by some remote multinational corporation (indeed in an exception that proves the
rule, when the plant is sold to German investors, Burns soon buys it back to restore his
ego).21
In sum, for all its postmodern hipness, The Simpsons is profoundly anachronistic in
the way it harks back to an earlier age, when Americans felt more in contact with their
governing institutions and family life was solidly anchored in a larger but still local
community. The federal government rarely makes its presence felt in The Simpsons, and
when it does it generally takes a quirky form like former President Bush moving next door
to Homer, an arrangement that does not work out. The long tentacles of the IRS have
occasionally crept their way into Springfield, but its stranglehold on America is of course
all-pervasive and inescapable.22 Generally speaking, government is much more likely to
take local forms in the show. When sinister forces from the Republican Party conspire to
unseat Mayor Quimby by running ex-convict Sideshow Bob against him, it is local sinister
forces who do the conspiring, led by Mr. Burns, and including Rainer Wolfcastle (the
Arnold Schwarzenneger lookalike who plays McBain in the movies) and a Rush Limbaugh
lookalike named Burch Barlow.23
Here is one respect in which the portrayal of the local community in The Simpsons
is unrealistic. In Springfield, even the media forces are local. There is of course nothing
strange about having a local television station in Springfield. It is perfectly plausible that
the Simpsons get their news from a man, Kent Brockman, who actually lives in their midst.
It is also quite believable that the kiddie show on Springfield television is local, and that its
host, Krusty the Klown, not only lives in town but also is available for local functions like
supermarket openings and birthday parties. But what are authentic movie stars like Rainer
Wolfcastle doing living in Springfield? And what about the fact that the world-famous
Itchy & Scratchy cartoons are produced in Springfield? Indeed the entire Itchy & Scratchy
empire is apparently headquartered in Springfield. This is not a trivial fact. It means that
when Marge campaigns against cartoon violence, she can picket Itchy & Scratchy
headquarters without leaving her hometown.24 The citizens of Springfield are fortunate to
be able to have a direct impact on the forces that shape their lives and especially their
family lives. In short, The Simpsons takes the phenomenon that has in fact done more than
anything else to subvert the power of the local in American politics and American life in
general -- namely the media -- and in effect brings it within the orbit of Springfield, thereby
placing the force at least partially under local control.25
The unrealistic portrayal of the media as local helps highlight the overall tendency
of The Simpsons -- to present Springfield as a kind of classical polis; it is just about as
self-contained and autonomous as a community can be in the modern world. This once
again reflects the postmodern nostalgia of The Simpsons; with its self-conscious recreation
of the 1950s sitcom, it ends up weirdly celebrating the old ideal of small-town America.26
Again, I do not mean to deny that the first impulse of The Simpsons is to make fun of
small-town life. But in that very process, it reminds us of what the old ideal was and what
was so attractive about it, above all the fact that average Americans somehow felt in touch
with the forces that influenced their lives and maybe even in control of them. In a
presentation before the American Society of Newspaper Editors on April 12th, 1991
(broadcast on C-SPAN), Matt Groening said that the subtext of The Simpsons is: "The
people in power don't always have your best interests in mind."27 This is a view of politics
that cuts across the normal distinctions between left and right and explains why the show
can be relatively evenhanded in its treatment of both political parties and has something to
offer to both liberals and conservatives. The Simpsons is based on distrust of power, and
especially of power remote from ordinary people. The show celebrates genuine community,
a community in which everybody more or less knows everybody else (even if they do not
necessarily like each other). By recreating this older sense of community, the show
manages to generate a kind of warmth out of its postmodern coolness, a warmth that is
largely responsible for its success with the American public. This view of community may
be the most profound comment The Simpsons has to make on family life in particular and
politics in general in America today. No matter how dysfunctional it may seem, the nuclear
family is an institution worth preserving. And the way to preserve it is not by the offices of
a distant, supposedly expert, therapeutic state, but by restoring its links to a series of local
institutions, which reflect and foster the same principle that makes the Simpson family
itself work -- the attachment to one's own, the principle that we best care for something
when it belongs to us.
The celebration of the local in The Simpsons was confirmed in "They Saved Lisa's
Brain," which for once explores in detail the possibility of a Utopian alternative to politics
as usual in Springfield. The episode begins with Lisa disgusted by a gross-out contest
sponsored by a local radio station, which, among other things, results in the burning of a
travelling Van Gogh exhibition. With the indignation typical of youth, Lisa fires off an
angry letter to the Springfield newspaper, charging: "Today our town lost what remained of
its fragile civility." Outraged by the cultural limitations of Springfield, Lisa complains:
"We have eight malls, but no symphony; thirty-two bars but no alternative theater." Lisa's
spirited outburst catches the attention of the local chapter of Mensa, and the few high-IQ
citizens of Springfield (including Dr. Hibbert, Principal Skinner, the Comic Book Guy, and
Professor Frink) invite her to join the organization (once they have determined that she has
brought a pie and not a quiche to their meeting). Inspired by Lisa's courageous speaking out
against the cultural parochialism of Springfield, Dr. Hibbert challenges the city's way of
life: "Why do we live in a town where the smartest have no power and the stupidest run
everything?" Forming "a council of learned citizens," or what reporter Kent Brockman
later refers to as an "intellectual junta," the Mensa members set out to create the cartoon
equivalent of Plato's Republic in Springfield. Naturally, they begin by ousting Mayor
Quimby, who in fact leaves town rather abruptly once the little matter of some missing
lottery funds comes up.
Taking advantage of an obscure provision in the Springfield charter, the Mensa
members step into the power vacuum created by Quimby's sudden abdication. Lisa sees no
limit to what the Platonic rule of the wise might accomplish: "With our superior intellects,
we could rebuild this city on a foundation of reason and enlightenment; we could turn
Springfield into a Utopia." Principal Skinner holds out hope for "a new Athens," while
another Mensa member thinks in terms of B.F. Skinner's "Walden II." The new rulers
immediately set out to bring their Utopia into existence, redesigning traffic patterns and
abolishing all sports that involve violence. But in a variant of the dialectic of enlightenment,
the abstract rationality and benevolent universalism of the intellectual junta soon prove to
be a fraud. The Mensa members begin to disagree among themselves and it becomes
evident that their claim to represent the public interest masks a number of private agendas.
At the climax of the episode, the Comic Book Guy comes forward to proclaim: "Inspired
by the most logical race in the galaxy, the Vulcans, breeding will be permitted once every
seven years; for many of you this will mean much less breeding; for me, much much
more." This reference to Star Trek appropriately elicits from Groundskeeper Willie a
response in his native accent that calls to mind the Enterprise's Chief Engineer Scotty:
"You cannot do that, sir, you don't have the power." The Mensa regime's self-interested
attempt to imitate the Republic by regulating breeding in the city is just too much for the
ordinary citizens of Springfield to bear.
With the Platonic revolution in Springfield degenerating into petty squabbling and
violence, a deus ex machina arrives in the form of physicist Stephen Hawking, proclaimed
as "the world's smartest man." When Hawking voices his disappointment with the Mensa
regime, he ends up in a fight with Principal Skinner. Seizing the opportunity created by the
division among the intelligentsia, Homer leads a counterrevolution of the stupid with the
rallying cry: "C'mon you idiots, we're taking back this town." Thus the attempt to bring
about a rule of philosopher-kings in Springfield ends ignominiously, leaving Hawking to
pronounce its epitaph: "Sometimes the smartest of us can be the most childish." Theory
fails when translated into practice in this episode of The Simpsons and must be relegated
once more to the confines of the contemplative life. The episode ends with Hawking and
Homer drinking beer together in Moe's Tavern and discussing Homer's theory of a
donut-shaped universe.
The Utopia episode offers an epitome of what The Simpsons does so well. It can be
enjoyed on two levels -- as both broad farce and intellectual satire. The episode contains
some of the grossest humor in the long histoiy of The Simpsons (I have not even mentioned
the subplot concerning Homer's encounter with a pornographic photographer). But at the
same time, it is filled with subtle cultural allusions; for example, the Mensa members
convene in what is obviously a Frank Lloyd Wright prairie house. In the end, then, the
Utopia episode embodies the strange mixture of intellectualism and anti-intellectualism
characteristic of The Simpsons. In Lisa's challenge to Springfield, the show calls attention
to the cultural limitations of small-town America, but it also reminds us that intellectual
disdain for the common man can be carried too far and that theory can all too easily lose
touch with common sense. Ultimately The Simpsons seems to offer a kind of intellectual
defense of the common man against intellectuals, which helps explain its popularity and
broad appeal. Very few people have found The Critique of Pure Reason funny, but in The
Gay Science Nietzsche felt that he had put his finger on Kant's joke:
Kant wanted to prove in a way that would puzzle all the world that all the world was right -- that was
the private joke of this soul. He wrote against the learned on behalf of the prejudice of the common
people, but for the learned and not for the common people.28
In Nietzsche's terms, The Simpsons goes The Critique of Pure Reason one better: it
defends the common man against the intellectual, but in a way that both the common man
and the intellectual can understand and enjoy.29
1 As reported in Ed Henry's "Heard on the Hill" column in Roll Call, 44, no. 81 (13 May 1999). His
source was the Albany Times-Union.
2 The identification is made complete when Quimby says: "Ich bin ein Springfielder" in the episode
"Burns Verkaufen der Kraftwerk." I cite all Simpsons episodes by title, using the information supplied in the
invaluable reference work The Simpsons: A Complete Guide to Our Favorite Family, edited by Ray
Richmond and Antonia Coffman (New York: HarperCollins, 1997).
3 "Two Bad Neighbors."
4 With respect to the show's reluctance to go after Clinton, see the rather tame satire of the 1996
presidential campaign in the "Citizen Kang" segment of the Halloween episode, "Treehouse of Horror VII."
Finally in the 1998-99 season, faced with the mounting scandals in the Clinton administration, the creators of
The Simpsons decided to take off the kid gloves in their treatment of the President, especially in "Homer to
the Max" (in which Homer legally changes his name to Max Power). Hustled by Clinton at a party, Marge
Simpson is forced to ask: "Are you sure it's a federal law that I have to dance with you?" Reassuring Marge
that she is good enough for a man of his stature, Clinton tells her: "Hell, I've done it with pigs -- real no foolin'
pigs."
5 "The Front."
6 An amusing debate developed in The Wall Street Journal over the politics of The Simpsons. It
began with an op-ed piece by Benjamin Stein entitled "TV Land: From Mao to Dow" (5 February 1997), in
which he argued that the show has no politics. This piece was answered by a letter from John McGrew given
the title "The Simpsons Bash Familiar Values" (19 March 1997), in which he argued that the show is political
and consistently left-wing. On 12 March 1997, letters by Deroy Murdock and H.B. Johnson Jr. argued that
the show attacks left-wing targets as well and often supports traditional values. Johnson's conclusion that the
show is "politically ambiguous" and thus appeals "to conservatives as well as to liberals" is supported by the
evidence of this debate itself.
7 Perhaps the most famous example is the creation of Green Acres (1965-71) by inverting The
Beverly Hillbillies (1962-71). If a family of hicks moving from the country to the city was funny, television
executives concluded that a couple of sophisticates moving from the city to the country should be a hit as well.
And it was.
8 On the self-reflexive character of The Simpsons, see my essay "The Greatest TV Show Ever," The
American Enterprise, Vol. 8, No. 5 (September-October 1997), pp. 34-37.
9 Oddly enough, Bart's creator, Matt Groening, has now joined the chorus condemning the Simpson
boy. In 1999 a wire service report quoted Groening as saying to those who call Bart a bad role model: "I now
have a seven-year-old boy and a nine-year-old boy so all I can say is I apologize. Now I know what you were
talking about."
10 "Marge on the Lam."
11 "The Devil and Homer Simpson" in "Treehouse of Horror IV."
12 "Lisa the Greek."
13 "Lisa's Pony."
14 "Home Sweet Homediddly-Dum-Doodily."
15 "Homer the Heretic."
16 "Bart's Girlfriend."
17 I would like to comment on this show, but it is scheduled at the same time as The Simpsons and I
have never seen it.
18 Consider, for example, the minister played by Tom Skerrit in Robert Redford's film of Norman
Maclean's A River Runs through It.
19 A good example of this stereotyping can be found in the film Contact, with its contrasting
religious figures played by Matthew McConaughey (good) and Jake Busey (evil).
20 "In Marge We Trust."
21 "Burns Verkaufen der Kraftwerk."
22 See, for example, "Bart the Fink."
23 "Sideshow Bob Roberts."
24 "Itchy & Scratchy & Marge."
25 The episode called "Radioactive Man" provides an amusing reversal of the usual relationship
between the big-time media and small-town life. A Hollywood film company comes to Springfield to make a
movie featuring the comic book hero, Radioactive Man. The Springfield locals take advantage of the naive
moviemakers, raising prices all over town and imposing all sorts of new taxes on the film crew. Forced to
return to California penniless, the moviemakers are greeted like small-town heroes by their caring neighbors
in the Hollywood community.
26 In his review of The Simpsons: A Complete Guide to Our Favorite Family, Michael Dirda aptly
characterizes the show as "a wickedly funny yet oddly affectionate satire of American life at the end of the
20th century. Imagine the unholy offspring of Mad magazine, Mel Brooks's movies, and 'Our Town'." See
The Washington Post, Book World (11 January 1998), p. 5.
27 Oddly enough, this theme is also at the heart of Fox's other great television series, The X-Files.
28 See Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, sect. 193 (my translation) in Friedrich Nietzsche, Sämtliche
Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe, ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1967-77),
Vol. 3, p. 504.
29 This essay is a substantial revision of a paper originally delivered at the Annual Meeting of the
American Political Science Association in Boston, September 1998. It was originally published in Political
Theory 27 (1999), pp. 734-749, and is reprinted here with the permission of the author and Sage Publications,
Inc.
12
Springfield Hypocrisy
JASON HOLT
You talk the talk, Quimby, but do you walk the walk?
-- Chief Wiggum
From the Ayn Rand School for Tots to Zen Buddhism, The Simpsons runs a gamut
of philosophically interesting subject-matter. One can hardly forget Bart's answer to the
koan: What is the sound of one hand clapping? (He quickly closes the fingers of one hand,
making a slapping noise that approximates applause.) William James would have been
proud. The show is not intended to be "philosophical" in the way that, say, existentialist
literature is. And that's okay. Regardless of the writers' or producers' intentions, The
Simpsons provides much animated grist for the philosopher's mill, often in the form of
illustrative examples. The result is not only reliably entertaining, it is also, on occasion,
illuminating.
The Simpsons satirizes contemporary culture deftly, with Wilde precision and at
Swift extremes. An important recurring theme is the role of morality, or the lack thereof, in
the lives of Springfield citizens. In this respect, The Simpsons is rather like existentialist
literature, both of which diagnose, in different ways, but arguably with equal aplomb, the
moral crisis of the present age. What is the crisis? Well, that's a long story, and a lot
depends on who you ask. Suffice it to say, many people take values less seriously than they
should. With so many different value systems to choose from, it is easy to miss the point of
values, and tough to tell which system, if any, is correct. By what values should one live if
morality has no discernible foundation?
This is a big question, of course, and I do not propose to answer it, much less by
appeal to The Simpsons. But it is worth observing, as the existentialists did, that even if
there is no objective morality, we can still talk in a meaningful way about values. More
precisely, whatever one's values happen to be, one can be judged in a morally significant
way by how those values relate to one's actions. According to some existentialists, we can
be praiseworthy for being true to the principles or values we accept, whatever the values
are and on whatever basis we accept them. Likewise, we can be blameworthy for being
false to those principles or values. We can distinguish, in other words, moral content -- that
is, specific moral principles -- from formal moral properties, in particular being true to
oneself, and practicing what one preaches. Where these smack of consistency, or integrity,
betraying oneself, and failing to practice what one preaches, smack of inconsistency, of
hypocrisy.
Hypocrisy is what I want to talk about, because The Simpsons not only illustrates
many important features of this moral vice, it also reveals how certain things philosophers
have said about it are false. It may seem odd that an animated sitcom could reveal what
experts have missed, but the view from the ivory tower is not the same as the view from
elsewhere, and different views afford different advantages. Still, the ordinary concept is in
need of refinement. What I will do, first, is discuss illustrative examples from The
Simpsons. For my chief philosophical point, I will use Wiggum as a test-case for a view
that gives the hypocrite too much credit. Although hypocrisy is usually an egregious moral
flaw, I will then show how there can be sympathetic, even praiseworthy cases of it. Where
appropriate, I will juxtapose Springfield cases with classic literary examples, the goal
being to sharpen the ordinary concept, as needed, while respecting as much as possible the
view it constitutes.
First, let's get the ordinary concept straight. Hypocrisy is "not practicing what one
preaches." That is, one affirms certain principles or values -- words to live by -- then acts in
violation of those principles or values. If I say that one should abstain from beans, as a
certain group of ancient philosophers did -- It's true, I swear! -- and then I go ahead and eat
beans, I am a hypocrite. If I abstain from beans, as I say one ought to, I am not a hypocrite.
This only works with statements of value, which do not say how the world is, but how it
ought to be. They do not describe facts, they prescribe actions. If I say that the cat is on the
mat but behave as if the cat is not on the mat, or as if there is no cat, I am not a hypocrite but
a liar, a joker, or perhaps I have a very bad memory, or some other cognitive dysfunction.
In hypocrisy, one's actions violate one's own affirmation of values, moral, aesthetic,
professional, rational, or otherwise. The fault is a moral one even if the values in question
are not in the moral sphere.
Now this might sound a touch too academic, but the importance of formal virtues
and vices in everyday life is obvious. We are right to value things like integrity, and to
despise things like hypocrisy, in ourselves as well as in others. In one's own case, integrity
gives a sense of pride, of a strong, self-determined, resolute life, and this sense of pride is
appropriate. Where values clash, as they do in many areas of human interaction, one can
legitimately respect or criticize others for whether they act in accordance with the values
they espouse.
It might seem inapt to use Springfield as a philosophical springboard, but in
addition to my earlier claim that The Simpsons gives a fresh perspective on the matter at
hand -- a four-digit hand, naturally -- there is a further fact to consider. Though
philosophers have discussed hypocrisy to some extent, they have, on the whole, ignored it.
Any useful means of redressing this is warranted. Using The Simpsons, my aim is not only
to illustrate important features of hypocrisy, and to help get a better understanding of it, but
also to redress its relative neglect.
Li'l Lisa Goes to Washington
There are so many examples of clear and borderline hypocrisy in The Simpsons that
it would be pointless to cover the bulk of them. But certain examples are to the purpose,
especially as we associate hypocrisy most readily with corruption in politics, business, and
religion. Accordingly, in this section I will focus on Mayor Quimby, Mr. Burns, and
Reverend Lovejoy. Not all these cases are as clearcut as they might be, but together they
serve to illustrate a number of basic points.
In "Mr. Lisa Goes to Washington," Lisa witnesses Congressman Bob Arnold taking
a bribe. She is rightly upset, for Congressman Arnold acts in deliberate violation of his oath
of office. And it is this that makes him a hypocrite. Mayor Quimby is a similar but more
complex case. Notice the twofold hypocrisy in the following exchange.
WiGGUM: But she broke the law.
QUIMBY: Thanks for the civics lesson. Now listen to me. If Marge Simpson goes to jail, I
can kiss the chick vote goodbye. ("Homer Alone")
Now Quimby is not just a hypocrite: he's a liar, a cheat, weak-willed, prejudiced,
sexist, gullible, base, and, despite a modicum of political savvy, rather dense. It is
important to distinguish his hypocrisy from these other moral, character, and intellectual
flaws. Here Quimby not only decides against upholding the law, he intimates and violates a
publicly presented concern with women's issues.
One might think that hypocrisy is inevitable in politics, and that Mayor Quimby, as
a politician, does not deserve much blame. This is a cynical view. As I will discuss later,
there are certain kinds of forgivable and even praiseworthy hypocrisy. But these are
comparatively rare, and in such cases the objectives are either sympathetic or morally
praiseworthy. Quimby's hypocrisy, on the other hand, like that of many politicians, is not to
serve his constituents, but to use his power for personal gain. His purpose is neither
sympathetic nor praiseworthy. Next to Sideshow Bob, he is the better Mayoral Candidate,
but his hypocrisy is no less egregious for that.
Political hypocrites do not walk the walk they talk in taking oaths of office or, more
narrowly, in toeing party lines. But this does not limit hypocrisy to cases where the values
in question are explicitly affirmed. One can toe the party line without explicitly endorsing
it. In other words, one can be a hypocrite by violating principles one implicitly affirms,
either by toeing party lines in silence, holding a job where values are involved but no
oath-taking is required, or, in a more calculated way, by presenting false public images that
speak to such values. Think of Principal Skinner and Mrs. Krabappel, who as educators are
implicitly committed to certain education-related values, which they often violate and
sometimes flout with abandon.
Another complex case is that of Mr. Burns, who displays a variety of moral
turpitude, often in pursuit of profit. There is nothing wrong with, and indeed much to laud
in, the profit motive and many of its consequences. But not hypocritical public relations,
which Burns illustrates with a will as strong as his body is weak, in particular by presenting
himself, on more than one occasion, as an environmentalist, which he decidedly is not.
This is good PR of course, but Burns's hypocrisy is all too evident.
I figured if one six-pack holder will catch one fish, a million sewn together will catch a million fish. . .
I call it the Burns Omni-net. It sweeps the sea clean. . . I call our product: Li'l Lisa's Patented Animal
Slurry. It's a high-protein feed for farm animals, insulation for low-income housing, and a top-notch
engine-coolant. And best of all, it's made from 100-percent recycled animals. ("The Old Man and
the Lisa")
The case of Li'l Lisa's Patented Animal Slurry might seem the best example, though
here Burns fails to grasp the meaning of his own false front, in stark contrast to his
calculated PR in other episodes. At a company litter cleanup, Burns poses for press
cameras in full cleanup gear, which he casts off disgustedly as soon as the shutters stop
("Mother Simpson"). At a company retreat, he gives a speech on the value of teamwork and
spirited competition ("Mountain of Madness"), while his track-record is not "teamly" but
the worst sort of elitism, his efforts at competition not spirited but conniving, his play not
fair but a cheat at every turn.
From a literary perspective, perhaps the most prominent kind of hypocrite is the
religious hypocrite. A well-known example is Molière's Tartuffe, who uses a pretense of
great piety to insinuate himself into a well-off family. Affirming the value of poverty, he
lives with the family free of charge, and eventually finagles control of all the family's
possessions. Secure in his new power, he acts in clear violation of his presented values, and
is undone. Tartuffe is a classic play, well worth the read. The Simpsons is a different sort of
classic in its own right, well worth the watch. Lovejoy, though, is no Tartuffe. Not that
there's anything wrong with that, for despite Lovejoy's understandable world-weariness,
and somewhat resigned faith, there are certain indications that he may be a hypocrite.
These include having his dog do its "dirty, sinful business" on the Flanders's lawn ("22
Short Films About Springfield"), downplaying the importance of Christian tenets ("Bart's
Girlfriend"), and denying Lisa access to the Good Book ("Whacking Day"). Priesthood of
all believers? Hardly. One might think Lovejoy a clear hypocrite, what with his ardent,
judgmental moments. But we might interpret him more charitably as simply
overinfluenced by the Old Testament.
Although Lovejoy is no Tartuffe, he might be something of a Don Manuel. In
Miguel de Unamuno's St. Manuel the Good, Martyr, Don Manuel loses his faith, but
continues to play the believing priest his parishioners take him to be, a role he deems
necessary for the good of his flock. He doubts the religious basis of what he preaches, and
so is disingenuous to be sure, but he is not a hypocrite, since he continues to practice
accordingly. The difference is, his motivation is not religious but pragmatic. The actions
prescribed are the same. Although his true values belie those presented to his flock, his
actions do not violate either set. Lovejoy may, to a certain extent, be telling a similar noble
lie. His role in the community is far less crucial than that of Don Manuel, but his position is
still one of social benefit. Think of how much he does for the Flanderses, especially Ned,
burdensome as the benefit is. Still, Lovejoy betrays a shallow indifference to his flock ("In
Marge We Trust"), which seems to rule him out as even a diluted sort of Don Manuel.
So far a number of important features of hypocrisy have been illustrated by
Springfield and other cases. In hypocrisy, one acts deliberately in violation of espoused
principles. Or, one affirms principles à la Mr. Burns, in knowing violation of past or
planned actions, the purpose being to minimize evident or conceal secret behavior.
Inconsistency is the key. It is interesting that, with few exceptions, none of the Simpson
family is much of a hypocrite. Bart? Yes, but only by coercion, and rarely at that. Homer?
Not at all. He acts in full -- if unreflective -- accord with the hedonistic values he affirms,
except when faced with a severe moral test, in which case he not only does the right thing,
he does it under the auspices of consistent values.1
The Wiggum Case
Many philosophers understand hypocrisy in a way that strays too far from the
ordinary concept. This misconception is understandable, even natural, but it is a
misconception, and the humorous case of Chief Wiggum shows us why.
The misconception is that hypocrisy is essentially deceptive, that one can be a
hypocrite only by some sort of pretense or misdirection.2 On this view, hypocrisy is a kind
of lying. One presents a false front, a normative veil, or a mask of good intentions. This
serves a dual purpose. It makes known bad actions seem less egregious, and diverts
attention from what might arouse suspicion, or lead to the discovery, of secret bad behavior.
The hypocrite may, by such means, even deceive himself as to his own moral standing.
While I agree that many hypocrites fit this profile, and that the purpose of
hypocrisy is often deceptive or exculpatory, I deny that this captures the essence of
hypocrisy. Sometimes we do not consciously know what our intentions are, and sometimes
we forget, or fail to understand, the values we present to others. If we can fall into
hypocrisy unawares, then hypocrisy is not a matter of conscious deceit. Alternatively, say I
present false values to others but, because I am too timid to act on my true values, I always
act in accordance with those I present. This is not hypocrisy, for in such a case I do walk the
walk. I fail to believe the talk, is all. Similarly, as Don Manuel illustrates, it is possible to
satisfy, at the same time, and by the same actions, one's personal values and those one
presents falsely to others. This is not hypocrisy either. Deceiving others as to one's values
or intentions is not essentially hypocritical. True enough, it is a form of deception. But it is
not at the heart of hypocrisy.
How could a number of thinkers have gotten this wrong, even, as I said, in an
understandable, natural way? Here is my diagnosis. Originally, in ancient Greece,
hypocrisy was understood to be not a moral flaw but a dramatic stage technique -- wearing
a mask. Later, in Medieval times, this metaphor was applied to those who presented false
values. Such misrepresentation was viewed as a serious moral fault. It still is. But this is
markedly different from the modern conception. Misrepresentation of inner values is
deceptive, and it may be a benchmark of hypocrisy, but that's about all. The modern
conception does not even require that hypocrites have inner values to belie in presentation.
So the idea that hypocrisy is inherently deceptive is anachronistic, a throwback to an
outmoded sense of the term. Ignoring present language use altogether is an unwarranted
departure from common sense.
Another reason is that the outmoded sense is superficially supported by certain
prominent historical and literary examples. Sticking with literary cases for a moment, one
thinks of Tartuffe from Molière's Tartuffe, Julien Sorel from Stendahl's Scarlet and Black,
and Uriah Heep from Dickens's David Copperfield. What makes hypocrisy interesting and
rich for literary exploration is to have the hypocrite be intelligent or at least clever. A clash
of moral and intellectual virtues is a delight. But most hypocrisy is duller, more banal. To
take exceptional cases as representing all cases is simply a mistake. In this case, it amounts
to giving the hypocrite too much credit. Most are not so intelligent, and though many use
hypocrisy as a smokescreen, one need not deceive in order to be a hypocrite.
If the point of hypocrisy is deception, then we should expect pointless hypocrisy to
be non-deceptive. What we need in defense of the ordinary concept is an example where
intelligence is absent and the usual deceptive purposes are not in play. The Simpsons
provides an ideal example in the rotund figure of Chief Wiggum, whose actions violate the
principles he presents as one of Springfield's finest. We have to be careful, though, because
being a dirty cop is not the same as being a bad cop, and Wiggum is both.
This is Papa Bear. Put out an APB for a male suspect, driving a. . . car of some sort, heading in the
direction of, uh, you know, that place that sells chili. Suspect is hatless. Repeat, hatless. ("Homer's
Triple Bypass")
We think we're dealing with a supernatural being, most likely a mummy. As a precaution, I've
ordered the Egyptian wing of the Springfield Museum destroyed. ("Treehouse of Horror IV")
I'm sorry, kids. I don't think you're ever gonna get back those greyhounds. Maybe Mr. Burns will sell
you one of the twenty-five he got last night. ("Two Dozen and One Greyhounds")
Here we see Wiggum's professional incompetence. It is unfortunate, but morally
neutral. To serve and protect? Minimally. This owes not only to his incompetence,
however. It owes also to the motivation behind his competent, but morally suspect,
duty-doing.
LOU: There's a couple of guys fighting at the aquarium,
CHIEF WIGGUM: They still sell those frozen bananas?
LOU: I think so.
WIGGUM: Let's roll. ("Brother from the Same Planet")
LOU: That sounded like an explosion at the old Simpson place.
WIGGUM: Forget it. That's two blocks away.
LOU: Looks like beer coming out of the chimney.
WIGGUM: I am proceeding on foot. Call in a code eight.
LOU: (into radio) We need pretzels. Repeat, pretzels. ("So It's Come to This: A Simpsons
Clip Show")
Wiggum is not incompetent here. Nor is he a hypocrite. He answers the call, though
not for the right reasons. His hypocrisy, by contrast, lies in taking bribes, using drugs,
hiring prostitutes, his dereliction of duty, and his abuse of power.
You have the right to remain silent. Anything you say blah blah blah blah blah blah. ("Krusty Gets
Busted")
I'll tear up this ticket, but I'm still going to have to ask you for a bribe. ("A Fish Called Selma")
Aw, can't anybody in this town take the law into their own hands? ("The Secret War of Lisa
Simpson")
All right. Come out with your hands up, two cups of coffee, an auto freshener that says 'Capricorn',
and something with coconut on it. ("Marge in Chains")
Do not be alarmed. Continue swimming naked. Aww, c'mon, continue! Come on! Awww. . . Alright,
Lou, open fire. ("Duffless")
Here we see Wiggum's hypocrisy, large and amorphous as the Chief himself. It is
self-serving, of course, as is most hypocrisy. But it is not deceptive. Think of "The
Springfield Connection," in which Wiggum, Lou and Eddy, and other members of the
force, take evidence against a counterfeit jeans operation -- the jeans -- for themselves,
with the result that there is insufficient evidence for an arrest. The inconsistency is there for
all to see as the police zip up and the Chief delivers his classic closer: "Lookin' good,
boys!" Why is there no deception? Two reasons. There's no need, for one. And besides,
Wiggum's mind is not really up to it.
Wiggum's stripped-down hypocrisy shows that the vice comports much better with
ordinary understanding than more sophisticated cases make it seem. Defenders of the view
I criticize might insist that Wiggum is not a hypocrite, precisely because his practices are
not at all deceptive. But although it is in the philosopher's purview to tailor concepts for
theoretical purposes, this cannot be done arbitrarily, or in unexamined contradiction to
cases which support a more commonsense view. The concept of hypocrisy does need
sharpening, but such refinement must respect the Wiggum case, if not Wiggum himself.
What makes Springfield hypocrisy so funny is that it is, in contrast to more sophisticated
examples, pointless. This is less an elaboration of contemporary culture than many would
admit. Harsh medicine. But one hardly notices the taste for the laughter.
Shh!
Even in its most humorous forms, hypocrisy is typically one of the most
reprehensible moral vices. I say "typically" because sometimes it is excusable, sympathetic,
sometimes even praiseworthy. Look, for laudable cases, to literary characters like
Huckleberry Finn and historical figures like Oscar Schindler. In The Adventures of
Huckleberry Finn, Huck abets the escape of a slave, and although his actions are
praiseworthy, he describes them as immoral. On a grander scale, in World War II Schindler
presented himself as a Nazi, saving, by this deceit and other machinations, the lives of
many Jews. Hypocrisy is praiseworthy when it is a necessary means to a worthwhile moral
end, as in the Finn and Schindler cases. It is excusable when coerced, and sympathetic
when the coercion is unfair. Take Bart's writing "I WILL NOT WASTE CHALK"
repeatedly on the blackboard ("Bart the Genius"), which might seem to be a case of
excusable, if not sympathetic, hypocrisy. It is detention, after all, and there is clear
inconsistency in wasting chalk for the purpose of learning not to waste chalk. But it is not
clear that Bart is making a value claim, even an implicit one, in writing "I WILL NOT
WASTE CHALK." If there is hypocrisy here, it belongs to whoever assigned him the task.
Be it Skinner or Krabappel, they ought to know better.
To my knowledge, there are no examples of praiseworthy hypocrisy in The
Simpsons. But there are sympathetic cases. First off, Apu. Facing unfair deportation, he
presents a false front of "American" values to hide his illegal status, and we are right to feel
sympathy for him and to consider his hypocrisy excusable. When the false front becomes
too much to maintain, Apu's cheerful lip-service falls to incredulity, then angry despair, in
the span of a single sentence.
What is the infinite compassion of Ganesha next to Tom Cruise and Nicole Kidman staring at me
with their dead eyes? ("Much Apu about Nothing")
Second, Lisa. Finding herself isolated, punished for her virtues, she decides to win
friends by disavowing, and even violating, the values she normally and honestly affirms.
LISA: My goony brother's always going to libraries. I usually hang out in front.
ERIN: Oh, you like hangin' out, too?
LISA: Well, it beats doin' stuff.
ERIN: Yeah. Stuff sucks. ("Summer of 4 ft. 2")
The coercion here is milder, a form of psychological duress. But Lisa's predicament
is still a sympathetic one. Her hypocrisy is guided by an intelligent selfishness. It is pretty
much harmless, unlike the crude selfishness of other Springfield hypocrites and most in
real life.3
I have left a lot of meaty philosophical issues, pace Homer, untouched. Just the
same, I want to make a few niggling remarks. Is one a hypocrite by falling short of an
espoused ideal? No, because the idea is to practice what you preach. Where practice is
needed, there is not yet perfection. What happens if values conflict? Order them
hierarchically and act in accordance with the dominant value. Otherwise hypocrisy is
unavoidable. Is hypocrisy always bad? Yes, provided it is not coerced, or a necessary
means to moral action. Is integrity the opposite of hypocrisy? No. Integrity is acting in
accordance with one's true values, not one's presented values. This means it is possible,
oddly enough, to have integrity as a hypocrite.4 What is hypocrisy again? A formal vice,
intended or unintended inconsistency between deliberate actions and values espoused
tacitly or explicitly. Mmm. . . meaty.5
1 For more on the idea that there is something admirable about Homer see Raja Halwani, "Homer
and Aristotle," in this volume.
2 Variations on this theme are found in Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson,
1949), p. 173, Jonathan Robinson, Duty and Hypocrisy in Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1977), p. 116, Bela Szabados, "Hypocrisy," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9
(1979), p. 197, Eva Kittay, "On Hypocrisy," Metaphilosophy 13 (1982), p. 278, Judith Shklar, Ordinary
Vices (1984), p. 47, Jay Newman, Fanatics and Hypocrites (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1986), p. 109,
Christine McKinnon, "Hypocrisy, With a Note on Integrity," American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1991), p.
321, Ruth Grant, Hypocrisy and Integrity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 67, and Bela
Szabados and Eldon Soifer, "Hypocrisy After Aristotle," Dialogue 37 (1998), p. 563. This is a representative
sample, not an exhaustive list.
3 Two borderline cases worth mentioning here are Lisa's decision not to reveal the truth about
Jebediah Springfield ("Lisa the Iconoclast"), and Marge's attempt to become a member of the Springfield
Glen Country Club ("Scenes from the Class Struggle in Springfield"). If Lisa's silence is hypocritical, then it
is arguably, contrary to my earlier claim, a case of praiseworthy hypocrisy. Marge's attempt to join the
country club is somewhat sympathetic, although, like Lisa's silence, it is not obviously hypocritical. For
reminding me of these examples I thank William Irwin and Adam Muller respectively.
4 For more on the idea that integrity is not always a good thing see Robert A. Epperson, "Seinfeld
and the Moral Life," in William Irwin, ed., Seinfeld and Philosophy: A Book About Everything and Nothing
(La Salle: Open Court, 2000), pp. 165-66.
5 Thanks to Rhonda Martens and the editors for comments on an earlier draft. Thanks also to Carl
Matheson and Adam Muller for spirited discussion, and for the infiltration of Bar Italia, long overdue.
13
Enjoying the So-called "Iced Cream":
Mr. Burns, Satan, and Happiness
DANIEL BARWICK
What true Simpsons fan has never rubbed his hands together and said in a slow,
breathy voice: "Excellent. . ."? Monty Burns's expression of joy is familiar to all who watch
The Simpsons, and it's regarded by Simpsons fans as the ultimate indication that all is well
with the world. But despite the frequency with which he uses the expression, Mr. Burns
finds little in the world to be pleased about. He is not a happy man, and the source of his
unhappiness is none of the more familiar features of his character. Burns's unhappiness lies
not in his advanced age, his decrepit physical condition, his long list of diseases, his
support of slavery, his slaughter of thousands of animals (for sport or for wardrobe), his
maltreatment of his employees, nor his rejection by the townspeople in general and women
in particular. Rather, his unhappiness lies in a particular way of looking at the world, a way
that cripples him emotionally and is echoed increasingly in the way we interact with our
own world. We have a lot to learn from Mr. Burns about how not to spend a life; but this
cautionary essay is not about kindness or greed, or wealth or power. Instead, it is about
enjoying the cool smoothness of ice cream and the happiness it brings.
How could it be that Mr. Burns is unhappy? He has his own Xanadu (who wouldn't
like his or her own Xanadu, complete with hounds to be loosed on Girl Scouts and other
visitors?), a nuclear power plant that he runs with an iron fist, a chauffeur-driven
Rolls-Royce, control of the local Republican Party, an extensive wardrobe made from
hard-to-find materials, an assistant who dotes on him, and sixteen prize-winning
greyhounds. Monty is the owner of Burns Construction Company, the Burns Slant-Drilling
Company, the owner and founder of "Lil' Lisa's Patented Animal Slurry" Plant, and the
inventor of Burns's Omni-net. He owns King Arthur's "Excalibur," the only existing nude
photo of Mark Twain, and that rare first draft of the Constitution with the word "suckers" in
it. He was even reunited with his precious teddy bear, Bobo. What, then, might the problem
be?
Mr. Burns has three problems that stand in the way of his happiness. I shall focus on
the third, but the first two bear mentioning because they are an integral part of
understanding his psyche. First, he is a creature of gross excess. Everything about him is
big: his house, his fortune, his power (and abuse of that power), his ambition, his robotic
Richard Simmons. As Springfield's richest man, he is "free to wallow in his own
crapulence," as Mr. Burns gleefully admits. Although there is a rich tradition in philosophy
that condemns such excess and advocates a life of moderation, surely the reader does not
need the philosophic canon to see that none of Mr. Burns's excesses bring him much
happiness. Despite being surrounded by people, he is alone. Despite his vast wealth, he
wants ever more.
Second, because he sees everything in abstract terms, because he sees everything as
a symbol of something else, he attaches unnecessary importance to everything around him
and does not enjoy things for what they are. In "Team Homer," winning a worthless
bowling trophy is much more important to him than the sweet, albeit momentary, pleasure
of a group of jocular friends enjoying a game, bonding as a team, and drinking Duff Beer.
Instead, winning the trophy becomes a singular achievement, and the problem with this
approach is that when everything matters, nothing gets a chance to really matter. Mr. Burns
sees everything in a symbolic fashion. He sees everything in an important symbolic way.
As such, everything has the same level of importance, and so in the end everything bores
him.
But this problem is common. We are all guilty, to a greater or lesser extent, of
attaching ridiculous importance to the events in our own lives. It is often amazing to
become aware of the unimportant things about which we become angry or glad, and
equally amazing to recognize the truly important things to which we are indifferent. But
Burns's problems are parasitic upon a third, more fundamental problem. This problem is
the symbolism that he attaches to everything; the result is that the original thing that is
symbolized ceases to exist, at least in any pleasurable way. Unfortunately for Mr. Burns, it
is the original thing that he truly needs for happiness. Allow me to explain.
Scene One: HELL1
Scorned by a woman, Satan took council with his chief tempters in Pandemonium.
"What," he asked the assembled Principalities and Powers, "are we doing to hasten the
dehumanization of man?"
One by one, they reported. Formidable Senior Vice-Presidents in charge of Envy,
Pride, and Avarice gave glowing accounts; the Chiefs of the Bureaus of Lust and Sloth read
lengthy bills of particulars. Lawyers lectured on loopholes. Satan, however, was not
pleased. Even the brilliant report from the Head of the War Department failed to satisfy
him. He listened restively to the long treatise on nuclear proliferation; he fiddled with
pencils during the section on the philosophy of guerilla warfare.
Finally, Satan's wrath overcame him. He swept his notes from the table and leapt to
his feet. "Self-serving declarations!" he roared. "Am I doomed to sit forever listening to
idiots try to hide incompetence behind verbiage? Has no one anything new? Are we to
spend the rest of eternity minding the store as we have for a thousand years?"
At that point, the youngest tempter rose. "With your permission, my lord," he said,
"I have a program." And as Satan sat down again, the demon launched into his proposal for
an interdepartmental Bureau of Desubstantialization. He claimed that the dehumanization
of man was going so slowly because their infernal strategy had failed to cut man off from
one of the chief bulwarks of his humanity. In concentrating on offenses against God and
neighbor, it had failed to corrupt his relationship to things. Things, the tempter declared, by
their provision of unique delights and individual astonishments, constituted a continuous
refreshment of the very capacities Hell was at pains to abolish. As long as man dealt with
real substances, he would himself tend to remain substantial. What was needed, therefore,
was a program to deprive man of things.
Satan took evident interest. "But," he objected, "how shall we proceed? In an
affluent modern society man has more 'things' than ever. Are you saying that in the midst of
such abundance and possessed by such materialism he simply will not notice so obvious
and so bizarre a plot?" "Not quite, my lord," said the tempter. "I do not mean to take
anything from him physically. Instead, we shall encourage him mentally to alienate himself
from reality. I propose that we contrive a systematic substitution of abstractions, diagrams,
and spiritualizations for actual things, actual beings. Man must be taught to see things as
symbols -- must be trained to use them for effect, and never for themselves. Above all, the
door to delight must remain firmly closed.
"It will not," he continued, "be as difficult as it seems. Men are so firmly convinced
that they are materialists that they will believe anything before they suspect us of
contriving their destruction by spiritualization. By way of a little insurance, however, I
have taken the liberty of arranging for an army of tele-vangelists who will continue, as in
the past, to thunder against them for being materialists. Humanity will be so busy feeling
delightfully wicked that nobody will notice the day when we finally cut them loose from
their reality altogether."
And at that, Satan smiled, sat back and folded his hands. "Excellent. . . ," he said.
"Let the work go forward."
I could stop the essay there, because we find immediate confirmation of my
hypothesis (or at the very least a very credible hint) in the episode "Rosebud" in which the
Springfield Shopper headline reads:
BURNS BIRTHDAY TODAY
CREDITS LONG LIFE TO SATAN
But consider:
Scene Two: The Bowling Alley
BURNS: [walking in] Look at them, Smithers, enjoying their embezzlement.
SMITHERS: [dramatic] I have a much uglier word for it, Sir: misappropriation. Simpson!
[Homer sees them and tosses his ball away; someone screams]
BURNS: [menacing] Listen here. . . I want to join your team.
HOMER: You want to join my what?
SMITHERS: You want to what his team?
BURNS: I've had one of my unpredictable changes of heart. Seeing these fine young
athletes, reveling in the humiliation of a vanquished foe. . . mmm, I haven't felt this energized since
my last. . . er. . . boweling.
[Later, after winning the championship]
HOMER: Woo hoo! We won! We won! [Homer, Apu, and Moe dance while the Pimple-Face
Kid gets the trophy from the case. Homer holds it, hut Burns snatches it away]
BURNS: You mean, I won.
APU: But we were a team, sir.
BURNS: Oh, I'm afraid I've had one of my trademark changes of heart. You see, teamwork
will only take you so far. Then, the truly evolved person makes that extra grab for personal glory.
Now, I must discard my teammates, much like the boxer must shed roll after roll of sweaty, useless,
disgusting flab before he can win the title. Ta! [He leaves] ("Team Homer")
First, Burns sees inclusion on the bowling team as not what it is first and foremost:
a recreational activity with "friends" and lots of beer. He does not see these things at all.
Rather, he sees only "these fine young athletes, reveling in the humiliation of a vanquished
foe." Winning the trophy causes Homer, Apu, and Moe to dance with the joy of the
moment, but for Mr. Burns there is no moment to enjoy. He has none of Homer's "in your
face humanity" or "lust for life."2 Instead, he thinks not about the win, but about his
relationship to his teammates, discarding them like the flab around the waist of Wiggum.
What Burns calls one of his "trademark changes of heart" is not a change of heart at all. He
is merely following his heart: seeing each event, person, and thing as nothing but a sign for
something else. We see this throughout The Simpsons. Some examples:
What does his son mean to him?
Well, son, delighted to have met you. It's good to know that there's another kidney out there
for me. ("Burns, Baby Burns")
On his similarities to Holocaust hero Oscar Schindler:
Schindler and I are like peas in a pod: we're both factory owners, we both made shells for
the Nazis, but mine worked, dammit!" ("A Star is Burns")
On his public image:
SMITHERS: I'm afraid we have a bad image, sir. Market research shows people see you
as something of an ogre.
BURNS: I ought to club them and eat their bones! ("Two Cars in Every Garage and Three
Eyes on Every Fish")
On our sun:
No, not while my greatest nemesis still provides our customers with free light, heat, and
energy. I call this enemy. . . the sun." ("Who shot Mr. Burns? Part One")
On our feathered and four-legged friends:
I call it Li'l Lisa's patented animal slurry. It's a high-protein feed for farm animals, insulation
for low-income housing, a powerful explosive, and a top-notch engine coolant. And best of all, it's
made from one hundred percent recycled animals! ("The Old Man and the Lisa")
On pieces of fine art:
Let's just take them. We'll all be rich, rich as Nazis! ("The Curse of the Flying Hellfish")
Is my thesis merely that Mr. Burns has lost his inner child? Perhaps. But when we
give some thought to the way children see the world, we find that they too engage in a great
deal of symbolism, or at least representationalism. When a child plays a game, say toy
soldiers, he envisions the toy soldiers as standing for real soldiers and the battle as being
much more important than it really is. When a little girl plays dress-up, she envisions
herself or the dolls she is dressing as attending some important social function, much more
important than the game which the girl is playing.
So I am not merely suggesting that Mr. Burns is no longer a child or no longer
behaves like a child. In fact, it is Mr. Burns's exclusive use of symbolism that, in the end,
fails him in his quest for happiness. Why? There is a widely held conception of happiness
that explains happiness has two components. The first (the component we won't discuss) is
the occurrence of a certain set of emotions experienced during, following, or in anticipation
of a markedly favorable set of circumstances. The second is dispositional: in order to be
happy it is necessary that one like, or be satisfied with, those parts of one's total life pattern
and circumstances that one thinks are important, without which one would would be
substantially different.3
But of course we all know that Mr. Burns wishes that his life were substantially
different. He is permanently in search of a new life for himself, whether it be as an athlete,
a governor, an innocent child, or whatever. Whenever Burns has an idea to improve his life,
it is always to become something; or, more accurately, to become a certain type of thing.
Nothing is enjoyable or funny or desirable to him unless it can be seen as standing for or
representing something else, something bigger and more important.
Why can't such representationalism lead to happiness? If we leave aside for a
moment the speculation that Mr. Burns's representationalism is the product of Satan's
attempt to cut him off from his humanity, we find some more interesting philosophical
grounding for my claim. There is a distinction, familiar to most undergraduate philosophy
majors, between intrinsic goodness and instrumental goodness. Things which are
instrumentally good are good only insofar that they lead to, or are in some way related to,
other things which are good. Those things which they lead to are either also instrumentally
good, or intrinsically good. (Instrumental goodness is sometimes referred to as extrinsic
goodness.) Intrinsically good things are things which are good in themselves; not because
they lead to something good, but because they themselves are valuable; not because they
produce any result, or lead to something good, or lead to something pleasurable, or perhaps
have any results at all. Rather they are good because of the kind of thing they are. They
need no further justification for their goodness other than what they are.
Consider pleasure. We find that pleasure may be instrumentally good or
intrinsically good. For example, instrumentally good pleasure might be the pleasure my
dog feels when I praise him for doing a trick -- the reason I say it's instrumentally good is
that the pleasure my dog feels makes it more likely that he will perform that trick later
when I ask him to do so. But the pleasure he feels may also be intrinsically good, that is, it
seems almost odd to ask "Well, what's good about pleasure?" Explaining the intrinsic
goodness of pleasure will mostly just be explaining what pleasure is. Now notice, of course,
pleasure can be instrumentally bad while being intrinsically good. For example, let's say I
decide to shoot heroin. The pleasure I experience may itself be intrinsically good while at
the same time being instrumentally bad, since the pleasure I derive from taking that drug
may lead to problems -- health problems, psychological problems, financial problems, and
so forth.
But the interesting question is: Can there be such a thing as instrumental goodness
without there also being intrinsic goodness? Can we have instrumental goodness, that is,
something we recognize as good, while being mindful of something else good that the
thing will bring, while at the same time believing there is no such thing as intrinsic
goodness? No, this would be impossible. Goodness is a bit like a check one writes to pay
off a debt. If Homer writes a check and has the money to cover the check, then the check is
actually worth the money. But if Homer writes a check and the check is only good if
Barney's check clears in Homer's account, then it seems that Homer's check is only good if
Barney has the money. What if Barney only has the money if Moe's check clears in
Barney's account? Each person is dependent on someone else to close the loop, so to speak.
Isn't it obvious that no one has any money? That is, if everybody is always dependent on
someone else coming up with money, isn't it true that no one has any money? Instrumental
goodness is the same, in the sense that something that is instrumentally good is only good if
it leads to something else that involves goodness. Instrumental goodness is problematic in
the sense that it seems as if we can never talk about, for example, money being intrinsically
good in virtue of its bringing about, for example, a Squishie, without some appeal to
intrinsic goodness. If we only had instrumental goodness, it would seem that money is only
good if it brings about the instrumentally good Squishie and a Squishie is only good if it
brings about the instrumentally good sugar high, . . . and so on. It has to go on forever since
instrumental goodness is always goodness in relation to something that is being produced
or something that has some relationship to another thing. This seems to generate an infinite
regress in which it is not clear that the goodness is ever grounded, that there is ever any
foundation to the claim that money, for example, is a good thing. So in Mr. Burns's world,
when everything is a representation of something else, when everything serves as a symbol
of something else, and everything only takes on meaning in light of something else, it
would seem as if nothing would have any meaning. It would seem as if nothing would have
any real power, nothing would stand for anything real. If everything is what it is only in
virtue of its relationship to something else, for example winning the bowling trophy is what
it is only in virtue of its relationship to being a spectacular victory, then this generates a
problem similar to intrinsic vs. instrumental goodness.
You have noticed, of course, that if everything is what it is in relationship to
something else, as it appears to be in Mr. Burns's world, then the spectacular victory that
underpins the act of winning the bowling trophy must have itself some sort of
underpinning. . . and all these underpinnings are required for the act to have real meaning.
Unless we arrive at something that has meaning in itself, something which in a sense is
simple and foundational, not symbolic, not representational. Nothing in Mr. Burns's world
can have any meaning, and it isn't a very big leap from there to say that, in the end, without
anything meaningful in Mr. Burns's life he cannot be particularly happy. One of the
hallmarks of the unhappy life is meaninglessness, and one of the hallmarks of the happy
life is its meaningfulness.
There is a related problem with Mr. Burns's way of seeking happiness. Mr. Burns
never enjoys anything beyond what that thing represents, and what that thing represents
often lies in the past or in the future. Such representationalism guarantees that Mr. Burns
loses the value of the moment in favor of a method for finding happiness. The method he
prefers is looking beyond the objects of the moment for the happiness those things will
bring. But this method has never yielded happiness. There is a saying of Eastern origin:
"There is no way to happiness. Happiness is the way." Mr. Burns's representationalism,
although habitual by now, is an activity designed to bring him happiness. It exemplifies Mr.
Burns's belief that happiness must be sought deliberately. But people who are happy (and
not merely momentarily happy) do not seek happiness or a way to happiness; they did not
arrive at being happy after a series of steps or as a result of some deliberate action. This is
because happiness in the classic sense is not merely an emotional aftereffect; rather, it is a
dispositional state.
What are Mr. Burns's prospects for finding happiness? There is no logical
impossibility involved in old Monty finding happiness. Indeed, we see him finding
momentary happiness throughout the series, hence the title of this essay. When Mr. Burns
is tasting ice cream at the local festival and says to Mr. Smithers, "I'm really enjoying this
so-called 'iced cream'," we see the seed of happiness in Mr. Burns; we see him enjoying
something merely for what it is; enjoying the physical pleasure of the cold clean ice cream
("Bart's Inner Child"). This is Mr. Burns at his best (although not of course at his most
entertaining); for a moment he is not mean. At this moment he is displaying his ignorance
of things common and blue-collar, that in which man takes pleasure. The scene is
significant in that it shows that Mr. Burns is indeed capable of engaging in ordinary
pleasure without attaching to it a high degree of symbolism and representationalism. So Mr.
Burns can in fact experience happiness.
But this isn't saying very much. There are very few people, even unhappy people,
who don't experience moments of happiness, moments where in the case of Mr. Burns he
simply forgets to be himself. He forgets to engage in the symbolizing habit he has engaged
in all of his life. But does this mean that he can be happy in the long term? Can he evolve
from a person who finds no real meaning in his life into a person who can feel real pleasure,
real happiness, who can enjoy the so-called iced cream on a permanent basis? The answer
to this is, of course, no -- not likely. Although stories such as Dickens's A Christmas Carol
may go a long way toward convincing us that mean old people can change their ways, the
fact is that is highly doubtful that a 104-year-old man,4 steeped in malice, hatred, regret,
anger, revenge, desire for money, lust for power, and with a nasty habit of casting away the
immediacy of experience, will be able to change (even if the producers would let him).
1 This story is borrowed, strangely enough, from a cookbook: Robert Farrar Capon's The Supper of
the Lamb (New York: Doubleday, 1969), pp. 106-107.
2 See Chapter 1 of this volume.
3 This account and others like it can be found in many accounts of happiness. See K. Duncker, "On
Pleasure, Emotion, and Striving." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 1 (1941), pp. 391-430.
The most concise formulation may be found in Richard B. Brandt's article on happiness in the Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, p. 414.
4 Monty Burns was a member of Yale's class of 1914. Assuming that he graduated at the usual age of
around 22, Mr. Burns would have been born in 1892. That would confirm his age as 104 in 1996, when this
episode aired. (Although an earlier show pegs his age at 72, the writers must have realized that no 72-year
olds are as decrepit as Mr. Burns.)
14
Hey-diddily-ho, Neighboreenos:
Ned Flanders and Neighborly Love
DAVID VESSEY
"Love your neighbor as yourself" (Matthew 19:19) is the centerpiece of Christian
ethics. Yet what it means and what it requires -- like many good moral principles -- is
ambiguous. Among all Ned Flanders's acts that exemplify "love your neighbor," the one
most philosophically interesting occurs in the episode "Home Sweet
Homediddly-Dum-Doodily." In this episode the Flanderses are acting as a foster family for
Bart, Lisa, and Maggie. During a Bible study game, Ned discovers from Lisa that the
Simpson children haven't been baptized and immediately rushes to perform the sacrament.
The reason to have them baptized is obvious: Flanders believes that without baptism they
cannot be saved. Oddly, his sense of obligation does not seem to extend beyond the
household. He has never before tried to have Bart, Lisa, or Maggie baptized (perhaps
because he hasn't known), nor does he continue afterwards. Nor does his sense of
obligation ever seem to extend to the clearly non-Christian characters. So the philosophical
question raised is: To what extent is "loving your neighbor" consistent with tolerating your
neighbors' beliefs and practices when you think that holding those beliefs will cause them
eternal suffering? How can you properly love others without acting to prevent them from
meeting such a fate? This becomes even more complicated when we consider the full
principle "love your neighbor as yourself." After all, a clear feature of self-love is that you
act to prevent your own eternal suffering when possible. So if you are required to love your
neighbor as yourself, and a consequence of loving yourself is that you work to avoid
suffering (including eternal suffering), then it would seem you are required to work to
prevent the eternal suffering of others. And that requirement would include working to
baptize them. But Ned does not try to do that except when it concerns children in his care.
So our task here is to provide a possible justification for Ned's actions given his beliefs.
Philosophy and Fictional Characters
Now it should be acknowledged at the outset that this is an odd project. What does
it mean to talk about the beliefs, or possible beliefs, of a fictional character? Ned Flanders
is only that which Matt Groening and his staff make him to be. It doesn't really make a
whole lot of sense to say "Ned should have said or done x, or should believe y," or even
"these arguments justify Ned's actions" because, quite obviously, Ned has no beliefs and
does not actually act. So how are we to understand the project in front of us?
One way would be to hypothesize Ned as an actual person. Our claims would then
be of the form, "If Ned were real, and Ned acted this way, how might he philosophically
justify his actions?" This doesn't work either. We are not seeking hypothetical "If Ned were
real" conclusions, but a genuine understanding of the possible justification of certain
actions. And this justification should hold regardless of whether the actions are performed
by a real-life person, or simply depicted by the character Ned. Really, in the end it's the
actions we want to focus on -- not Ned the character or even Ned as potentially real -- and
thus we should think of the character as representing certain kinds of actions: actions that
can be reflected upon independently of their enactment. To do so will make our
investigations more philosophical, as opposed to belonging more to cultural or literary
analysis.
We must also clarify that we are not out to explain the actions, but to provide a
possible justification for the actions. What is the difference? The only thing that really
explains Ned's "actions" is the fact that he was written that way. Though it makes some
sense to say that Ned did something because he believed it was necessary, and so forth, as
we have seen, strictly speaking, Ned has no beliefs. Explaining actions is a complicated
and sometimes futile undertaking. For example, what explains the shooting death of an
innocent man? The question is horribly indeterminate because what counts as an
explanation is horribly indeterminate. There are many possible legitimate answers: society,
madness, mistaken identity, pulling the trigger of a loaded gun aimed at the victim, the
bullet, the hole, the lack of oxygen to the victim's brain, or, of course, the ubiquitous
explanation: God's will. So which really explains the action? It's not clear there is a single
answer to that question. At any rate, notice that the answers tend towards psychological,
sociological, and biological (and even theological!) explanations. Our issue here is what
justifies an action. What kind of reasons could we provide that would make these actions
and these beliefs consistent?
The Responsibility to Save Lives
So we're concerned with a set of actions represented by Ned Flanders in "Home
Sweet Homediddly-Dum-Doodily." What actions? Not Ned's attempt to baptize the
Simpson children when they were under his care. That action does not raise a particularly
difficult philosophical question. Providing a possible justification is fairly simple. You
should always act in the best interest of those in your care. For what could it mean to care
for others if not to enable them to pursue their best interests? And when others are in your
care, as children are in parents' care -- and as the Simpson children are in their foster
parents', the Flanderses, care -- this means not only helping them achieve their goals, but
helping them to acquire the proper goals as the guardian or parent sees them. Even though
Bart and Lisa didn't think being baptized was in their best interest, it is the responsibility of
the guardians to act in the children's interest regardless of their beliefs.
The issue we need to confront is this: given the belief that without baptism eternal
life is unattainable, and the belief that you should love your neighbor as yourself, why
wouldn't Ned always be working to baptize the unbaptized as an act of love? To love
someone would seem to require you to act to save his or her earthly life -- or at least to try
to save his or her life. Indeed many would think this requirement is not limited to those you
love; you should try to save someone's life even if you have no connection to that person. It
would seem, then, that you are even more morally bound to try if you love that person. But
if you are morally required to save someone's earthly life when you believe it is endangered,
then it would follow that you are morally required to save his or her eternal life if you think
it is endangered. That is, if you hold the beliefs represented by Ned Flanders, then you are
morally required to work for the baptism of all persons at least as hard as you would to save
someone's life. But, Ned clearly doesn't. And, in fact, most people who hold these beliefs
don't. Are they simply inconsistent? To put our question in more general terms, could you
be justified in not working to save someone's eternal life if you thought it was endangered?
That is the action (or lack of action) that requires justification. Clearly it is a much more
difficult question than whether the Flanderses were justified in trying to baptize the
Simpson children. Let us spell the argument out in more detail, deriving it from the central
principle of "Love your neighbor as yourself." Notice that the obligation always focuses on
trying to save someone's life, not necessarily succeeding (as this may be impossible).
1. You should love your neighbor as yourself.
2. Loving someone requires trying to save his or her life.
3. If you are morally required to try to save someone's life, you are morally required
to try to save someone's eternal life.
4. If you are morally required to try to save someone's eternal life, you are morally
required to try to provide what is necessary for him or her to receive eternal life.
5. Baptism is necessary for eternal life.
6. Therefore, you are morally required to try to baptize everyone out of love, for the
sake of saving their eternal life.
Premises 1 and 5 are taken as given, and surely they are beliefs represented by Ned
Flanders. Premise 2 seems trivially true, but we will have to see if there are cases when you
would, out of love, not try to save someone's life. Premise 3 also seems trivially true. Line
6 is the conclusion, and follows from the other premises. Premise 4 is something we
haven't discussed yet, and needs our attention.
Are there cases in which you are required to act for an end, but not required to bring
about the means to that end? It would seem unlikely, but let's consider two scenarios. First,
you have a moral obligation to save somebody, but it would be physically impossible for
you to save that person (perhaps because that person is on the other side of the world from
you). Now since you are not morally obligated to do something physically impossible, you
have a situation where you are obligated to an end, but not the necessary means. In this case,
the error is in thinking that you can still perform an action even if you physically cannot
perform the necessary means to that action. You can only perform an action if the
conditions necessary for the action are in place. As you are not morally obligated to
perform impossible acts, you are not morally obligated to perform the end. So in fact you
are only obligated if you can realize the means.1 In the second scenario, you have a moral
obligation to save somebody, but in order to do it, you need to act immorally. Since you
cannot be morally required to act immorally, again we have a case where the end is
required, but not the means. The question here is what happens if the means are themselves
immoral. If it's the case that it might be immoral to baptize someone under certain
circumstances, then the proof would fall apart. But what might those circumstances be?
Certainly there may be ways of getting someone baptized which are recognizably immoral.
Two examples would be tricking someone into being baptized (somehow) or forcing
someone to be baptized against his or her will. But all we need conclude from this scenario
is that some ways of baptizing someone are more moral than others. This is not a surprising
conclusion and not one which really jeopardizes the argument.2 A greater concern is that,
since baptism provides for the possibility of eternal life, the ends justify the means. The
immorality of the means is overshadowed by the possible good that can come from the
action. Perhaps so, but we'll not solve this problem until we understand under what
conditions you could morally refrain from trying to facilitate someone's salvation through
having him or her baptized. What we will find is that the solution to the original problem
also addresses the challenge that the end may justify the means. For the time being, let's
accept premise 4 and turn directly to the possibility of justifiably not trying to save
someone's eternal life, in the name of love.
Understanding the Command to
Love Your Neighbor as Yourself
First, I think we need to look closely at the basic moral principle at work here:
"Love your neighbor as yourself." Let's take "neighbor" to mean, as it is commonly
understood, all human beings, and not simply those living next door (though of course the
narrow reading would still apply to the Flanderses and the Simpsons).3 This principle
shares a feature with the Golden Rule ("Do unto others as you would have them do unto
you"): both commands derive the appropriate action from your own relation to yourself. As
you love yourself, so should you love others; as you want done to you, so should you do to
others. The concern following all such theories is that they open up what we will call "The
masochist problem." In the case of the Golden Rule, what if what the person wants done to
him- or herself is to have pain inflicted for the sake of sexual arousal? Is he or she morally
required to inflict pain on others in order to sexually arouse himself or herself? This is a
problem for some versions, but interestingly it is less a problem for the "Love your
neighbor" principle. We are to love our neighbors as we love ourselves. Since the
obligation turns on a projection of our self-love to love of others, we are restricted from the
start. Willing is much broader than loving, and not everything willed upon oneself is
consistent with loving oneself. One could easily argue that masochism can't be consistent
with proper self-love, but of course this raises the question of the distinction between
proper and improper self-love. Consider one particular form of self-love: narcissistic
self-love (excessive pride, which the Medievals thought the worst of all vices and the
source of the rest). This form of self-love is not the self-love of the principle of "love your
neighbor as yourself." We know this from simply looking at the form of the principle. The
principle calls on us to treat others as we treat ourselves, but narcissistic self-love precludes
precisely this other attentiveness. If we are narcissistically self-loving, we are incapable of
loving others, much less loving them as ourselves. Clearly this is a morally improper form
of self-love. Self-love of this sort can't be universalized to apply to others, therefore if the
principle is going to avoid self-contradiction, it must call for a form of self-love other than
narcissistic self-love.
What, then, are we to make of the notion of self-love? At the very least self-love
requires this: that we aim to provide the means necessary for advancing the nobler aspects
of our selves. Of course it will involve much more than this -- for example, striving for
self-realization has to be balanced with self-acceptance -- but at the very least, to love
oneself is to work to perfect oneself as a person. That never involves simply following
one's immediate wants and desires. Rather it always involves evaluating those desires and
integrating those desires into a complete and fulfilling life. Thus to love others as yourself
is, at the very least, to work to promote the perfection of others as human beings -- to
promote others' development of their nobler aspects. And note well that these nobler
aspects may not only be independent of self-interest, they may be antithetical to it. One of
the noblest traits we recognize in people is their willingness to act on principle above and
beyond their personal, selfish desires. Indeed, we praise those who not only act against
their selfish desires, but who sacrifice themselves for the sake of acting morally. Loving
others, then, involves encouraging them to act on principles which may not be connected to
their desires. Notice this is appropriate given our discussion of the principle "Love your
neighbor as yourself." That very principle requires us to act on principles like it. That is, the
commands of the principle to love others as yourself preserve the idea of acting on
principle rather than on narcissistic self-love.
At this point we can return to something we saw earlier. Recall that premise 2 in the
argument was "Loving someone requires trying to save his or her life." We can now see
there are cases where, out of love, we should refrain from trying to save someone's life. If
we allow that love for others requires us to encourage others to act on principles more
noble than merely following their wants and desires, then we realize there may be cases
where a person is willing to risk death for one of these principles. If we are privileging
some principles over interests, then we should privilege them over the ultimate interest:
self-preservation. It would seem then that the principle "Love your neighbor as yourself"
may, in fact, lead us into a situation where the appropriate action is not to act to save
someone's life. That is, in cases where people are acting on a principle which, when
realized, advances nobler aspects of themselves and perfects them as persons, and the
following of which jeopardizes their lives, then you should not intervene. A clear example
would be if someone -- recognizing it might mean his or her death -- refuses on principle to
follow orders to kill innocent civilians.
Now an obvious objection is that no one on The Simpsons is represented as holding
such principles. Not even the most principled character, Lisa, could be said to belong to
that category, so the argument is moot. But again, we are not concerned with Ned and the
characters per se, but only with them as representatives of a certain set of actions, and we
are inquiring as to how those actions could be justified. On first glance, it would seem that
they are rarely, if ever, justified. Still, we have arrived at a sketch of a solution to the
problem, but only a sketch. Those familiar with the history of philosophy will have
recognized by now that our conclusions approach those arrived at independently and for
different reasons by Immanuel Kant. Let's look at his account of autonomy as a guide for
fleshing out the view that is emerging.
Kantian Autonomy
At this point our view has two elements: acting on principle, and acting
independently of interests. Kant held both of these factors to be crucial for an action to be
moral.4 The first he considered trivial. Every action, he claims, whether we know it or not,
has some principle behind it: a maxim. The moral worth of an action, then, depends on the
nature of the maxim guiding it. Some maxims reflect personal interests ("Act in such a way
as to maximize your pleasure" is a common one), while others do not. We've seen that
"Love your neighbor as yourself" is an example of a maxim which does not reflect personal
interests. According to Kant, an action will be moral only if the motivation for the action is
simply morality itself. We do it because it's the right thing to do. The same movements
might be done for different reasons, but they are only fully moral if they are done for moral
reasons. This is not to say the actions can't also fulfill our interests, just that our
self-interests can't be the motivation of the action if the action is to be considered a moral
action.
But when aren't actions done from self-interest? Kant acknowledges that it is
difficult to tell. In fact he says it's impossible to tell when you are genuinely acting morally,
but the key here is that it is possible to act morally. You can act on principles independent
of your interests. In addition to merely acting on the principles, however, you must be
aware of what you are doing for the action to be a properly moral action. At least you need
to be aware that you are trying to act according to the principle you've chosen. To act
morally, then, you yourself need to make the moral principle your principle. Certainly it is
praiseworthy when someone acts benevolently out of instinct, but to fully act morally
means to decide to make the moral guiding principle the principle to be followed. You give
yourself the principle, you determine for yourself how you should act, and you act on that
principle. Only then have you freed yourself from merely imitating others and according to
Kant, only then are you genuinely free.5 Kant refers to this genuine freedom as autonomy,
and it is different from what we will call metaphysical freedom. Metaphysical freedom is
the ability to initiate new causal chains: the ability to, say, move your arm at will without it
being moved by something external to you. Autonomy, however, is the ability to legislate
your own actions by choosing the principle of your actions. It is taking responsibility for
the maxim of your action.
Consider this feature of Kantian autonomy in the context of our guiding question.
We have been developing a possible moral justification for 1. believing you should love
your neighbor and 2. believing that without being baptized your neighbor will suffer
eternally, and 3. still not acting to baptize your neighbor. And a picture of the conditions of
such an action to be legitimate have started to emerge. If someone is acting on principle --
a principle that perfects him or her -- and that principle leads him or her to jeopardize his or
her life (including his or her eternal life), you might be required to refrain from interfering
on the basis of loving your neighbor. But surely if it's possible to be acting on principle
without really adopting that principle consciously, then we are given pause. If someone has
not consciously adopted the principle of his or her action and made it his or her own, then it
would seem that there is an obligation to intervene "on his or her behalf" (so to speak). If
self-love requires you to pursue principles of action that perfect yourself, then loving
others means enabling them to do the same. But this must mean enabling them to choose
these principles for themselves, and only in such conditions might "love your neighbor"
obligate you to respect their decision. So the central feature of Kant's theory of autonomy,
self-legislation of moral principles, seems to be required for our account as well.
Yet how do we come across these principles and make them our own? How do we
distance ourselves from our inclinations enough to make this possible? Kant's answer is
reason. Consider our three criteria for a moral action: 1. acting on a principle, 2. which is
independent of our interests and 3. which we have given to ourselves. Reason is necessary
for all three. Reason is what lets us step back from our immediate desires and inclinations,
and it is reason which allows us to think through the principles and decide if the action we
are going to make is being done for moral reasons (or selfish reasons). More importantly
for our case, it is reason that ultimately allows us to judge that a person is risking his or her
eternal life on the basis of what the person takes to be a more noble principle. For Kant,
reason becomes the key to understanding how to formulate the ultimately proper moral
principle. Reason abstracts us from our particular interests and, in doing so, universalizes
our judgment. This universalization is the key to what Kant calls the categorical imperative
-- a principle which will tell us when our maxims are moral. Act only on the maxims which
can be willed to be universal laws.6 We don't need to follow Kant to this extreme formalism,
but we have already seen his concerns for universality at play in our interpretation of the
meaning of self-love. At the very least we should agree with Kant that a condition of
autonomy is rationally standing back from your desires in order to reflectively embrace a
principle of action. Promoting your reasoned stance towards your desires is perfecting the
nobler aspects of yourself. At least, the principle of "Love your neighbor" requires you to
perfect your ability to use reason in this way.
So our conception of autonomy is complete. Loving your neighbor does not require
you to try to save someone's eternal life when he or she is acting autonomously.
Autonomous agency, we've concluded with Kant's help, has four parts. You must be acting
on principles that are independent from your interests and that you have consciously given
to yourself. The principles must aim to perfect yourself and must be the result of rational
reflection about how to act. In such a case Ned's actions would be justified. Under these
conditions, premise 2 from our earlier argument -- "Loving someone requires trying to save
his or her life" -- turns out to be sometimes false and the argument no longer holds.7
Conclusion:
Autonomy vs. Choice
Still, doesn't this simply boil down to the commonsense reaction that you should
not interfere in the choices of others? Where does the argument differ? Although it is true
that if a person has consciously chosen his or her ends, the person meets one of the criteria,
there is still the concern for choosing principles which function independently of desires. If
a person is acting out of his or her interests rather than on principles independent of his or
her interests, then there is never a case where the preservation of life is sacrificed to higher
interests. Well, unless of course that interest is the interest in eternal life, but this is
precisely the point. If people act out of interest rather than out of principle, then helping
them attain eternal life is consistent with their aims, whether they realize it or not. So it is
not the case that choices are tolerated simply because a person made them. Only some
choices people make -- rational, principled choices that are independent of interests -- free
someone like Ned Flanders from trying to facilitate his or her salvation through baptism in
the name of "loving your neighbor as yourself." Perhaps, then, it is especially appropriate
that at the end of the episode Flanders has only succeeded in baptizing one person, the
character most driven by immediate pleasures, his neighbor, Homer Simpson.
1 When we consider our example, the problem dissolves even more. According to most
interpretations, only God can really provide eternal life. So the end is not in your power. What is in your
power is trying to provide some of the necessary means to salvation, in this case baptism. So in this case it is
really the means that you are required to try to provide, not the end itself.
2 There is also the issue of baptizing infants before they can have a choice in the matter. We
addressed this briefly above when we argued that guardians have a moral responsibility to act as they see
would be in the best interest of the children in their care. Moreover, especially in the case of infants, baptism
is not forcing the children to adopt any particular religious beliefs. They are free to renounce their parents'
beliefs as they grow older.
3 Needless to say, "love" here is not meant as a feeling, as if the feeling of being in love could be
obligated, but as a way of relating to others.
4 Kant, surprisingly, rarely discusses at length the command to love your neighbor as yourself.
Here's what he does say in Part II of The Metaphysics of Morals. "The saying 'you ought to love your
neighbor as yourself' does not mean that you ought immediately (first) to love him and (afterwards) by means
of this love do him good. It means, rather, do good to your fellow human beings, and your beneficence will
produce love of them in you (as an aptitude of the inclination to beneficence in general)" (Immanuel Kant,
Practical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. p. 531). Later in the same work he
writes, "The duty of love for one's neighbor can, accordingly, be also expressed as the duty to make others'
ends my own (provided only that these are not immoral). . . In accordance with the ethical law of perfection
'love your neighbor as yourself,' the maxim of benevolence (practical love of human beings) is a duty of all
human beings toward one another, whether or not one finds them worthy of love" (Practical Philosophy, pp.
569-570).
5 But note that simply making the principle your own doesn't make it a moral principle, it must be
the right kind of principle. That is, the morality of the principle is independent of your willing the principle.
We will see more of this as Kant's views unfolds. Of course we could not come close to presenting Kant's
moral theory in all its complexity here. For a good presentation of Kant's ethics see Allan Wood's Kant's
Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
6 Kant gives a couple of versions of the categorical imperative. Perhaps the most relevant version for
our emphasis on autonomy (moral self-legislation) is the principle to act "on the idea of the will of every
rational being as a will giving universal law" (Practical Philosophy, p. 81). Which is to say, treat all as
capable of being autonomous agents. In effect, this and the principle of benevolence (help others perfect
themselves) is the content we've given to the "love your neighbor" principle. We should recognize all as
capable of autonomy and help them achieve that end.
7 Although we've moved away from the question of the Simpson children, there is a concern about
how this reasoning would apply to all children, not just those in your care. Kant thought everyone was
capable of acting autonomously, however not everyone realized this capacity. Children rarely act
autonomously; so the argument may still hold that one should try to baptize all children in your care or
otherwise. There isn't room to develop a fuller response to this concern, but I think one of two tracks (or both)
would be successful. One might argue that you should respect the judgments autonomous people make for
those in their care; or one might argue that the conclusion is that loving your neighbor requires you to work
for your neighbor's salvation or to work for your neighbor's realization of his or her autonomy.
15
The Function of Fiction:
The Heuristic Value of Homer
JENNIFER L. MCMAHON
Though people might expect a philosophic argument concerning the heuristic
function of fiction to allude to the works of Homer, renowned epic poet of ancient Greece,
it's likely that references to Homer Simpson in such a context would come as a surprise.
While not a conventional choice, the popular television show The Simpsons illustrates
some general claims made by philosophical writers about fiction. It's well-suited to
illustrate these claims because of the accessibility of its characters and scenes, the
pertinence of its subject matter amidst its levity, the unique nature of its medium, and its
mass appeal. Because I am interested in determining how fiction instructs, I shall focus
more on why The Simpsons can educate than on what it teaches. While I shall offer
examples, it is not my intention to articulate precisely what The Simpsons has to convey.
In a number of the other chapters of this book, my coauthors discuss some of the
pertinent benefits of viewing The Simpsons. Among other things, they suggest it can
cultivate cultural literacy and inform us about American values. However, because we
could not enumerate every insight that The Simpsons has to offer, we hope simply to
inspire people to look with greater seriousness at a show that seems to be more about
entertainment than education.
Most Americans are familiar with Matt Groening's The Simpsons. Indeed, given
that the show is televised in a host of foreign countries, so are many non-Americans.
Whether one likes The Simpsons or not, the show's popularity and longevity have made it a
part of contemporary culture. Avid viewers tune in weekly to watch the latest fiasco in the
lives of Homer, Marge, Bart, Lisa, and little Maggie. They watch latenight re-runs,
cultivating a mental index of favorite lines and scenes. For better or worse, famous phrases
from the show have even become part of colloquial English. Stationed in Springfield -- the
city without a state -- the Simpson family parodies the stereotypical American one. It
entertains us with its hysterical situations, its combination of comic dialogue and physical
humor, as well as its skillful allusion to other popular comedies like The Three Stooges,
The Honeymooners, and The Flintstones.1 The question is, however, how does it help us
learn?
While most people would find the proposition that we can learn from art
uncontroversial, philosophers do not. Indeed, since Plato offered his critique of art in the
fifth century B.C., philosophers have debated whether art can educate. Today, the
philosophical debate continues. A focus of that debate is the heuristic function of fiction.
While people have used stories as a means of instruction for centuries, philosophers have
traditionally been suspicious of the educational value of literature. Recently however,
many philosophers have come to laud its instructive ability. Arguably, Martha Nussbaum
is the most well-known advocate of this claim.2 In Love's Knowledge, Nussbaum offers the
bold assertion that certain truths can be conveyed adequately only in art. While her insights
have broad implications, Nussbaum focuses on literature's inimitable ability to disclose
moral truths. Using Nussbaum's work as a point of departure, I shall further explore the
instructive capacity of fiction. Specifically, I shall examine how engaging with fiction
prompts greater reflection on the part of the individual, reflection that can compel not only
the development of a keener understanding, but also moral improvement. I shall use the
popular television show The Simpsons to illustrate my claims regarding the function of
fiction. While these same features might first be thought to compromise its heuristic
function, I shall demonstrate that The Simpsons is well suited to illustrate my claims
because of the caricatured ordinariness of its characters and setting, its levity, its animated
medium, and its mass appeal.
Laying the Foundation for Fiction
Before offering my views regarding fiction generally and The Simpsons in
particular, it is necessary to discuss their foundation, namely Nussbaum's position and the
skeptical argument to which Nussbaum responds. Typically, those who deny that literature
can instruct ground their skepticism in doubts about fiction's capacity to represent reality,
as well as in concerns regarding the power of artful words to undermine rational thought.
They claim that stories about characters and events that are not real cannot offer us
worthwhile information about the real world. They propose that the feelings literature
typically elicits frustrate, rather than facilitate, clear thought. In Love's Knowledge,
Nussbaum responds to both of these concerns.
Contrary to the assertion that fictions do not depict reality and thus cannot serve as
vehicles for truth, Nussbaum contends that "certain truths about human life can only be
fittingly and accurately stated in the language and forms characteristic of the narrative
artist."3 Nussbaum elevates the language and forms of the narrative artist because she
believes that "the world's surprising variety, its complexity and mysteriousness, its flawed
and imperfect beauty. . . [can only] be fully and adequately stated. . . in a language and in
forms themselves more complex, more allusive, more attentive to particulars" (LK, 3).
Concerning the assertion that literature arouses emotions that impair our ability to think
clearly, Nussbaum asserts that emotions are essential to good judgment. She states,
"emotions are not simply blind surges of affect. . . they are discriminating responses [that
are] closely connected with beliefs about how things are and what is important" (LK, 41).
Nussbaum begins her case for literature with a critique of conventional philosophic
prose. While philosophers have tended to view literary narrative as an inadequate tool for
the conveyance of truth, they have seen their medium of expression as ideally suited to the
task of describing the true nature of things. Nussbaum gives us cause to question this
assumption. She contends that conventional philosophic prose is limited because of its
tendency toward abstraction and its privileging of reason at the expense of emotion.
As Nussbaum explains, when a style that is abstract and cleansed of emotion is
employed to describe a reality that is concrete, complex, and infused with feeling,
problems inevitably result. She asserts, "only the style of a certain sort of narrative artist
(and not, for example, the style associated with the abstract theoretical treatise) can
adequately state certain important truths about the world, embodying them in its shape and
setting up in the reader the activities that are appropriate for grasping them" (LK, 6). In
particular, Nussbaum contends that conventional philosophic prose is stylistically
unsuitable for the expression of our moral situation. She maintains that this style
misrepresents our situation and encourages misunderstanding regarding how we ought to
live in it. She concludes that conventional philosophic prose is not sufficient to disclose the
nature of our situation in a way that could educate us morally. She claims that literature is
an essential supplement to conventional philosophic works when it comes to the study of
moral philosophy and moral education generally.
Nussbaum continues her case for literature by enumerating the features of the
narrative style that make it conducive to the articulation of our moral situation. She
contends that literature is more capable of expressing the nature of our moral situation
because it prioritizes particulars (for example, acknowledging the inherent worth and
incommensurability of individuals) and recognizes the significance of emotion. These
features are important because they are stylistically consistent with the depiction of a
reality that is inherently variegated and replete with emotion. In Nussbaum's view, our
moral situation is extraordinarily complex and painfully ambiguous. While we may want it
to be simple, it is anything but simple. In order to offer an accurate depiction of our moral
situation, one needs to use a style that is attentive to detail, appreciative of complexity, and
committed to the articulation not only of the facts, but also of our feelings. She argues that
the absence of any of these features will result in an incomplete rendering of our moral
terrain.
In addition to affording a more accurate representation of our moral situation,
Nussbaum asserts that reading literature has other benefits. In order for a person to be
moral, an individual must not only be aware of the significance of individuals and emotion,
she must also possess certain habits and sensitivities. Nussbaum believes that reading
literature cultivates such morally relevant habits and sensitivities. Where abstract styles
direct our attention away from the concrete, literature's characteristic emphasis on
particular people and events conditions readers to develop a corresponding appreciation of
the inherent worth and inescapable uniqueness of individuals and situations. Likewise,
literature's careful depiction of the diversity and influence of emotion encourages readers
to appreciate the role that emotions play in our lives as well as the intellectual and ethical
consequences of the presence and absence of specific emotions. Finally, literature's
solicitation of emotion contributes to what Nussbaum calls the "shaping of sympathy" (LK,
44). She believes that the ability to feel for fictional characters is a morally relevant
capacity that engenders feeling for others in our ordinary lives.
Ultimately, Nussbaum sees literature as unique in its heuristic ability because it
both embodies in its style, and encourages in its readers, an attentiveness to the particular
that is a condition for being moral. With her critique of conventional philosophic prose,
Nussbaum draws her readers' attention to the deleterious effects of a style of writing that
has been celebrated as the medium of truth. Nussbaum maintains that this style is
unsuitable for representations of our moral situation because it promotes a simplistic
understanding of our moral experience as well as an undesirable degree of emotional
detachment. She feels literary works are more capable of generating moral understanding
and improvement because they offer a more accurate depiction of our moral situation and
encourage greater sensitivity in their readers.
Continuing the Case for Fiction
While the previous section summarizes Nussbaum's argument for literature,
Nussbaum's work is not the intended focus of this chapter. Rather, the objective of this
piece is to utilize Nussbaum's work as a basis for my own argument regarding the heuristic
relevance of The Simpsons. As I depart from Nussbaum in some respects, it is important to
make explicit what I draw from her argument as well as what I see as its shortcomings.
Like Nussbaum, I believe that literature possesses unique heuristic properties. Like
Nussbaum, I believe that literature is uniquely able to convey certain information and that
it can compel important cognitive and affective responses. I share Nussbaum's opinion that
literature often provides a more accurate depiction of our moral situation than conventional
philosophic prose. I agree that reading literature can help encourage the basic attention to,
and concern for, individuals that is a prerequisite for being a moral person. Finally, I share
the belief that literary works should be incorporated into the study of moral philosophy and
moral education generally.
While I am in agreement with most of her major points, Nussbaum's argument has
several shortcomings. Several of these are relevant to our subsequent consideration of The
Simpsons. First, in her argument for literature, Nussbaum alludes almost exclusively to
classic novels and plays from the Western canon. While she does not exclude the
possibility that other varieties of fiction can instruct, her clear preference for canonical
authors and forms serves to promote the elitist -- and erroneous -- assumption that only
such elevated works have educational value. This assumption must be dispensed with if
one is to appreciate the heuristic value of works that fall outside of the literary canon,
including popular fictions like The Simpsons.
Second, while it is perhaps a result of her unqualified enthusiasm for what literature
can provide, Nussbaum seems insufficiently attentive to the potential that fiction has to
distort our understanding and foster disturbing sensitivities. While literature can influence
us positively, it also can exert a negative effect. It can compel ignorance and morally
repugnant attitudes as easily as understanding and moral improvement. It can have these
effects because individuals do not encounter literature generally; they encounter individual
works of literature. These individual works may paint erroneous pictures of the world.
They may foster disturbing attitudes and allegiances.4 While fiction's potential to distort
our understanding and compel moral corruption led Plato to advocate wide-ranging
censorship, the benefits it can provide make censorship an unacceptable option. However,
it seems both insufficiently critical and somewhat irresponsible to fail to address the
possible untoward effects of indiscriminate exposure to fiction. Such effects are especially
pertinent when one recognizes that popular fictions like The Simpsons have the potential to
affect large audiences.
Third and finally, Nussbaum grounds her argument regarding the laudatory effects
of fiction exclusively in literature's capacity to offer accurate representations of reality and
cultivate sympathy. Though these features certainly contribute to its heuristic function,
there is more going on in our relationship with fiction than astute representation and the
promotion of sympathy. We learn from fiction not only because it offers accurate
representations of individuals and promotes feelings for those individuals, but also because
it promotes identification. Such identification clearly occurs with characters like Homer
and Marge Simpson whose lives bear similarity -- albeit caricatured -- to those of many
viewers.
Ultimately, the heuristic function of fiction is rooted in the unique opportunities it
provides. Fiction's distinctive emphasis on particulars not only makes it more capable of
depicting reality accurately, it also positively affects readers' or viewers' patterns of
attention by encouraging them to become more attentive to individual people and
circumstances. Likewise, fiction's unparalleled emphasis on emotion makes it capable of
soliciting feeling in ways that educate peoples' emotions.5 Fiction's heuristic success also
issues from the activity of identification that it encourages. As most individuals who read
or view fiction attest, one of the most engaging properties of fiction is the way that it
prompts identification. When we read or watch good fictions, we become absorbed. We
become absorbed largely because these fictions compel us to slip into the situations they
represent. Unlike other literary forms, works of fiction are structured in ways that
encourage readers or viewers to project themselves imaginatively into the text. Fictions
transport us into the worlds they create, encouraging us not only to feel as if we are present
to the actions taking place, but also to identify with individual characters. This involvement
yields unique heuristic effects.
First, fiction offers readers or viewers a fuller understanding of the reality
represented by getting them inside it. Our imaginative involvement with fiction makes the
situations depicted "available as it were from within, on the most intimate footing."6 By
prompting our imaginative identification, fictions afford us "a sense of what it is like to feel,
see, and live in a certain way" (TCS, 84). This imaginative identification provides a more
intimate understanding than we would achieve without it. Susan Feagin agrees, asserting
that fiction promotes simulation, a process that provides a fuller understanding than the
memorization of prepositional information. She argues that when we engage imaginatively
with a fiction we intellectually and affectively simulate what it would be like to be in the
situation represented. Because it forces the individual to shed her conventional orientation
and try on another, Feagin contends that simulation "enriches and deepens [one's]
understanding of the represented situation and makes one better able to deal with a
situation that bears similarity to it."7 Simulation educates by disclosing to the individual
who practices it "what it is like to be such a person or to be in a certain situation" (RF, 112).
It supplements the more superficial outsider's perspective obtained from being told a story
with the more in-depth insider's one obtained through identification.8
The process of identification that fiction encourages has a second benefit. It gives
us access to experiences that would not be available under normal empirical conditions.
Through our identification with fictional characters, we can experience situations and
perspectives that we could not access otherwise. By encouraging us to slip into the
characters and worlds it represents, fiction helps us glean an understanding of what it
would be like to live in other times and places, hold different beliefs, have different values,
and be different people. As Nussbaum states, "our experience is, without fiction, too
confined and too parochial. Literature extends it, making us reflect and feel about what
might otherwise be too distant for feeling" (LK, 47). Wayne Booth agrees, stating, "in a
month of reading, I can try out more lives than I could test in a lifetime."9 By encouraging
imaginative identification, fiction gives individuals the opportunity to explore a greater
range of experiences than are actually available. These vicarious experiences are
instructive insofar as they shift people out of their conventional perspective, compelling a
more genuine appreciation of alternative outlooks, contexts, and ways of being.
The vicarious experiences we have in relation to fiction are also instructive in that
they offer a medium with which people can more adequately assess alternative attitudes,
courses of action, and the consequences of each. While not without risk, this opportunity to
test out outlooks and actions is of unique cognitive value because it is relatively safe.
Through identification with fictional characters we can find out what it is like to do or
believe certain things without actually doing or believing them. In this way, fictions can
help inform our decision-making by giving us an experiential sense of the effects of
particular choices before we actually make those choices and experience those effects.10
Lastly, our identification with fictional characters educates us emotionally. One of
the things our identification with fictional characters does is elicit emotion. Gregory Currie
describes our relationship to fictional characters as an "empathetic re-enactment"11
wherein readers or viewers simulate the emotional and intellectual states of particular
characters. In addition to giving people the positive opportunity to vent emotions,12 this
re-enactment also educates individuals about themselves and others. It can increase an
individual's degree of self-knowledge by disclosing sensitivities or opinions that she was
unaware of having.13 Though not always pleasant, such knowledge is essential to
self-understanding and informed agency. Identification also contributes to the generation
of genuine understanding of, and compassion for, others. Only by slipping imaginatively
into the shoes of others do we become truly appreciative of the agony of their conflicts, the
depth of their joys, and the weight of their losses. By encouraging individuals to identify
with characters, fictions encourage not only the admirable activity of sympathy, but also
the morally relevant ability to empathize.
Philosophers have been reluctant to admit that fictions can educate because of the
paradox associated with them (e.g., how could one obtain information of real worth from
works that are, by definition, about things that are not real?). However, learning from
fiction only generates a paradox if one draws a radical line of demarcation between fiction
and reality. If one sees fiction as a creative endeavor that is grounded in the real and draws
all its material from it, the idea that fiction can educate is unproblematic. Fictions sketch
hypotheticals. Their illustrations can inform us because the places and problems of which
they speak resemble our own.
While it may not be paradoxical that we learn from fiction, there is something
paradoxical about our relationship to it. Indeed, I contend that fiction's heuristic ability
issues largely from the paradoxical nature of our engagement to it. One has to reflect only
momentarily to recognize the paradox. As much as fiction draws us in, it keeps us out.
Though fictions encourage us to identify with particular characters and project ourselves
imaginatively into their worlds, we can never be those characters or enter those worlds.
Likewise, while our engagement with fiction arouses real emotions, we cannot do the same
things with the emotional responses we have to fiction that we do with the ones we have in
response to real people and situations. Because they are not real, the relationships we have
to the characters and situations represented in fiction are qualitatively different from the
ones we have with real people and events. The fact that the characters and situations in
fiction are not real at once facilitates and frustrates our engagement with them.
The fact that characters and contexts depicted in fictions are not real facilitates
readers or viewers imaginative involvement because it gives them a sense of safety. When
we project ourselves imaginatively into fictions we can operate without consequence and
be intimate without risk. We enter worlds we can abandon if the going gets tough. Without
requiring us to move off the couch, our engagements with fiction allow us to explore
different worlds and adopt different personas. We slip into fictions easily because they do
not have the weight of being real. Though we know they can affect us, we relish letting
ourselves go with fictions because we know that the characters and events they depict
aren't real, our immersion in their virtual worlds is not permanent,14 and our identification
with their characters is not complete. Because of the safely the form affords us, we allow
ourselves to experience things in fiction that we could not, or would not, in actuality.
Fiction thus expands our knowledge base by letting us learn from experiences we would
not have in real life.
At the same time that fiction invites our involvement, the fictionality of the
characters and events it represents frustrates our habitual modes of response. For example,
even if we sense something is amiss in a fictional situation, we know we cannot change it.
Similarly, if the picture of the world offered by a fiction does not correspond to our own,
we are not at liberty to alter it. While we enter fictions imaginatively, we cannot change
them. We can stop reading or watching but we cannot adjust a work to suit our wants.
Likewise, when we respond emotionally to fictions, the fictionality of the characters and
events prevents us from acting upon our emotions the way we do normally. The fictionality
of the characters and events frustrates my habitual responses, forcing me to examine why I
am so affected by something that is not real.
The inalterability of the characters and contexts of fiction, the fact that we can
become immersed in them but not alter them, prompts us to reflect. The way fiction
frustrates our engagement with it is central to its heuristic function. It is central because it is
this thwarting of habitual response that prompts readers or viewers to reflect on the fiction,
assess the fictional world and its characters critically, and compare a particular fictional
rendition to other fictional or actual ones. It prompts readers or viewers to contemplate the
message of the representation. It prompts them to ponder their affective responses and the
fictional circumstances that generated them. Such reflective activities can yield greater
general understanding as well as moral improvement.
Ultimately, fiction has the unique ability to let us inside the characters and
situations it represents without ever letting us forget our separateness from them. It
generates what can be called frustrated identification. Our identification with fictional
characters is instructive because it lets us experience a wealth of different periods,
perspectives, and situations vicariously. Our assimilation of the information our
identification provides is then facilitated by our differentiation from characters.
Specifically, insofar as we know we are not the fictional characters with whom we identify,
they remain objects to be analyzed, objects from which we have a critical distance, objects
we are likely to view with less bias than we do ourselves. It is fiction's simultaneous
promotion of identification and dissociation, of intimacy and difference, that allows it to
educate us so well. Where we are often too close to ourselves and our situation to see
clearly, our ever-present knowledge that the characters and situations represented in fiction
are separate from us allows us to view them with greater impartiality. However, because
the process of identification helps reveal how characters are like us, it can increase our
self-understanding by prompting us to recognize that our situation, general attitudes, or
habitual reactions are comparable to that of a specific fictional character.
Enough *&!#?@ Already!
What About Homer?
Ultimately, The Simpsons operates like other fictions in the way it draws our
attention to individuals and both depicts and solicits emotion. Interestingly however, it is
The Simpsons' combination of several other features, features that may incline some people
against the show, that augment its educational effect.
The first feature is the ordinariness of the characters and setting of the show. While
extremely caricatured, the characters and context of The Simpsons are undeniably average.
Homer is the somewhat dim but endearing working class father. He's not the idealized
figure of Father Knows Best or Leave It to Beaver. Instead, he's the dysfunctional dad who
drinks cheap beer and burps intermittently and unapologetically while complaining about
work. Marge is the exasperated housewife who runs interference between Homer and the
kids, admonishes family members for their frequent scrapes, and consoles Homer
unfailingly despite his sometimes absurd behavior. Homer's and Marge's children, Bart,
Lisa, and Maggie, each exemplify the individuality, ingenuity, and egoism of your average
kid. Moreover, their relationships with one another illustrate all the conflict, conniving,
and competition that occurs in normal sibling relations. Finally, the setting of Springfield
and the Simpson family home are alike in their innocuous averageness. It's not a scene out
of Lifestyles of the Rich and Famous, or the pampered setting of Beverly Hills 90210.
Instead, The Simpsons presents us with the station wagon in the driveway, dirty dishes in
the sink, middle-class suburban environment with which so many of us are familiar.
Though familiar to most, the commonplace quality of The Simpsons' characters
and setting may lead some to conclude that the show has little to offer educationally
speaking. People may question whether important truths could issue from such a pedestrian
context. Of course, if truths cannot be ordinary, then The Simpsons might not offer much.
However, it seems that oftentimes it is the ordinary truths that elude us.15 Though it
exaggerates things in order to achieve its satirous effect, The Simpsons isn't far off the mark
in its rendering of contemporary suburban life.16 The bickering between Homer and Marge,
Bart's mantra, "I didn't do it!," Lisa's know-it-allness, the petty conflicts between neighbors,
Homer's perpetual disenchantment with his job, the characters' predictability coupled with
their capacity to surprise, these all ring true. While these truths aren't particularly elevated,
they resonate with viewers, reminding them of ubiquitous nature of such phenomena.
Ultimately, viewers' recognition of the omnipresence of certain aspects of ordinary
life is facilitated by the commonplace quality of the characters and contexts of The
Simpsons. The show's characters and setting are ones with which most viewers can easily
identify. For example, though we might not act like him, we can empathize with Homer's
irascibility and imprudence. Likewise, most viewers can relate to Marge's practicality and
maternal forbearance as well as her tendency to remain passive until a situation escalates to
a point where it positively demands her intervention. Rather than representing people with
whom we have little in common, individuals whose experience may seem too foreign to be
relevant, The Simpsons presents us with caricatures of ourselves. It depicts individuals who
-- like us -- possess both serious flaws and admirable qualities. We can learn from these
farcical figures because our ready identification with them, coupled with our recognition of
their qualities, encourages us to admit that we possess some of the same tendencies that
they do. Moreover, things like identifying vicariously with Homer's escapades afford both
a safe indulgence of our impetuous and often vengeful desires, and an object lesson in the
dangers of such caprice.17
The second feature of The Simpsons that contributes to its heuristic value is its
humor. You don't have to watch The Simpsons for very long to appreciate its levity. It
combines slapstick comedy seamlessly with sophisticated humor, creating a complex
comic fabric that appeals to a diverse audience. While the genre of comedy may be
unrivaled in its capacity to entertain, people have doubted its ability to instruct more than
any other literary form. Perhaps because it isn't serious, comedy hasn't been taken as
seriously as other genres when it comes to the question of education. This is unfortunate.
While there is always a place for seriousness, comedy is a tremendous pedagogical tool.
Indeed, by displacing certain anxieties and disabling habitual resistances, comedy can
bring to light things that might otherwise be too uncomfortable to acknowledge. For
example, not many of us like to admit that we suffer from paranoia or the fits of idiocy that
it can prompt. However, we find Homer funny in large part because he manifests these
tendencies so unabashedly. We laugh at Homer because we see some of ourselves in him.
In laughing at him, we learn a little more about ourselves.
Comedy is also beneficial because it allows for the examination of serious -- but
often disconcerting -- subjects in a more comfortable forum. Among other things, The
Simpsons has addressed pertinent subjects like racism, gender relations, public policy, and
environmentalism. Unfortunately, formal discussions of these topics often end up in
shouting matches or soap-boxing. Most people aren't especially interested in hearing either
one. Comedy is a useful way to broach such difficult subjects because it diffuses some of
the tension that surrounds them. In most cases, comedy can direct people's attention to a
topic, and even offer opinions about it, without inciting too much antagonism or appearing
too heavy-handed.18 Where people might tune out other mediums, their openness to
comedy and the pleasures it provides allows it to prompt their consideration of subjects
they might otherwise resist. Whether it be legalized gambling ("Springfield,"), allowing
women to enroll in military academies ("The Secret War of Lisa Simpson"), or animal
rights ("Lisa the Vegetarian"), The Simpsons has certainly compelled many Americans to
think more deeply about such topics.
A third feature of The Simpsons that aids its ability to instruct is its animated
medium. Like the genre of comedy, the medium of animation has not been taken as
seriously as mediums like film and verse. Perhaps because it reminds us of our childhood
and Saturday mornings in front of the TV, we tend to see the medium of animation as
unsophisticated. These associations may lead us to dismiss animated works from the class
of fictions we think can provide heuristic benefits. This would be a mistake. While not all
cartoons are equal (or educational), the form itself is instructive. Ultimately, the form of
animation offers an explicit reminder to the reader or viewer of the fictionality of the
characters and situations it depicts. One simply isn't going to mistake a cartoon character
for a real one. Through their form, animated works offer us a powerful reminder that we are
not the characters with whom we identify. As a result, such works are more decisive in
encouraging our reflection about the characters they describe, the situations they depict,
and the feelings and thoughts they elicit.
The final feature of The Simpsons that needs to be addressed is its mass appeal.
Like the previous attributes, the broad appeal of The Simpsons might lead some to doubt its
heuristic value. This doubt is grounded in the widespread assumption that popular works
cannot educate. Conveniently forgetting that literary icons like Shakespeare and Dickens
were popular authors, intellectuals often attempt to secure the ivory tower by claiming that
popular works are didactically vacuous and derive their popularity solely from their appeal
to the vulgar tastes of the masses. While this criticism may apply to a variety of popular
works, the wholesale dismissal of a class of fiction is not only inadvisable, it is illogical.19
The mass appeal of The Simpsons should not lead us to deny its heuristic
significance, it should compel us to consider it more carefully. Unlike more elite -- and
typically more revered -- forms of fiction, The Simpsons influences an extraordinarily large
and diverse audience. Not only can it convey important truths and prompt the consideration
of salient issues, it can offer these truths to, and compel increased reflection in, a huge
number of people. While The Simpsons may not be heuristically superior to Tolstoy, its
heuristic effects ought to be considered due to its wide appeal.20
Ultimately, a wise person is one who recognizes that she can learn something from
virtually every experience. Unfortunately, we are not always very wise. Rather than open
ourselves to what individual experiences can offer, we often inhibit the learning process by
prejudging certain experiences as cognitively irrelevant. While we take things from these
experiences nonetheless,21 we do not let ourselves learn much as we might from
experiences we do not regard as educational. With this essay, I have tried to show that
opportunities for learning exist in the largely unforeseen context of popular fiction.
Specifically, I have suggested that we can learn from The Simpsons. In drawing attention to
The Simpsons I do not mean to suggest that this fiction is formally or functionally superior
to classic works like those of Shakespeare or Sophocles. I do not believe it is. I simply want
to draw readers' attention to an opportunity they have to learn from a Homer they might
have overlooked.22
1 See Chapter 6 of this volume for a thorough account of the role and effects of allusion in The
Simpsons.
2 While she is the most well-known, Nussbaum is not the only philosopher making claims regarding
the heuristic function of fiction. Other authors who discuss this topic include Wayne Booth in The Company
We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988), Susan Feagin in Reading
with Feeling (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), David Novitz in Knowledge, Fiction, and Imagination
(Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987), and Jenefer Robinson in her article titled "L'Education
Sentimentale" in the Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73:2 (1995).
3 Martha Nussbaum, Love's Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), p. 5. Subsequent
references to this work will be indicated in parentheses accompanied by LK and a page number.
4 For further discussion of how fiction can promote problematic attitudes and allegiances, see
Cynthia Freeland's Realist Horror in Philosophy and Film (New York: Routledge, 1995). Here, the author
examines the effects of the eroticization and glamorization of the villain that occurs in many realist horror
films. In films like Silence of the Lambs and Freeland's example, Henry, viewers are encouraged to
sympathize with serial killers. As Freeland explains, the cultivation of such sympathy is not necessarily
negative. Indeed, if a viewer is cognizant of her sympathy and the problematic nature of it, the cultivation of
such sympathies can prompt reflection and heightened understanding. However, the generation of such
allegiances in uncritical and highly suggestible viewers may not result in such a positive outcome.
5 An example from The Simpsons that illustrates fiction's ability to educate our emotions occurs in
the episode titled, "The Raging Abe Simpson and his Grumbling Grandson." At the end of this episode,
viewers' hearts are warmed when Bart hugs his grandfather publicly. Though Grandpa Simpson thinks Bart
will be too embarrassed to hug him in public and Bart does become self-conscious during the hug, initially
Bart doesn't have any reservations about showing his affection in this way. Indeed, Bart declares that he
doesn't care who knows he loves his grandpa. While we often temper our behavior in order to achieve a
certain appearance, our satisfaction with Bart's action reminds us that concerns about appearances should
take a backseat to earnest expressions of feeling.
6 Flint Schier, "Tragedy and the Community of Sentiment in Philosophy and Fiction" (Aberdeen:
Aberbeen University Press, 1983), p. 84. Subsequent references to this work will be indicated in parentheses
accompanied by TCS and a page number.
7 Susan Feagin, Reading with Feeling (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), p. 98. Subsequent
references to this work will be made in parentheses accompanied by RF and a page number.
8 The benefit of fiction lies in its ability to provide readers or viewers with both the insider's and
outsider's perspective. We all know from our own experience that the insider's view is not necessarily the
clearest. Sometimes we're too close to things to see them objectively. At the same time however, the
outsider's or observer's perspective is not always sufficient. Fiction gives individuals a luxury that they do not
tend to have in life, namely the luxury of having access to both the insider's and the observer's point of view.
9 Wayne Booth, The Company We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1988), p. 485. Subsequent references to this work will be indicated in parentheses accompanied by
CWK and a page number.
10 Admittedly, the perception gleaned is virtual not actual. Thus, its accuracy cannot be guaranteed.
However, having the opportunity to evaluate an action or situation in fiction that bears similarity to an action
or situation one is entertaining seems preferable to not having that opportunity.
11 Gregory Currie, "The Moral Psychology of Fiction," Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73:2
(1995), p. 256. Subsequent references to this work will be made in parentheses accompanied by MPF and a
page number.
12 Here, I am referring in more common terminology to the process of katharsis, or purgation of
negative emotion, that fiction can prompt. Figures like Aristotle stress that the kathartic venting of emotion
that fiction often encourages is one of its most positive effects because it provides a safe venue for the
expression of disagreeable or destructive emotions.
13 For example, while reading a novel or watching a film I might have a powerful reaction to a
character, a reaction I find surprising because I did not expect to feel so strongly. The solicitation of this
strong feeling can serve as a catalyst for reflection. Specifically, in an effort to discern the basis for my
reaction, I reflect carefully upon the fictional circumstances that generated it, perhaps uncovering a belief or
feeling I did not know I had.
14 What is horrifying -- or "harsh" -- about the virtual worlds depicted in works like The Matrix and
Harsh Realm is that characters either cannot, or typically do not, escape from them.
15 In Being and Time (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), German philosopher Martin Heidegger
demonstrates that what is the most immediate is not always the best understood. Heidegger reveals that we
are often the most confused about what is closest to us, including who and how we are.
16 Arguably, the effect of satire cannot be accomplished without such accuracy. People must
recognize what is being satirized in order for the effect to be achieved.
17 While we may relish Homer's indignant attitude and absolute lack of concern for consequence
when he does things like throw his boss out a window, given that Homer's schemes usually back-fire and
leave him looking stupid, Homer typically illustrates what not to do in a similar situation.
18 Though there are exceptions, comedy tends not to seem too heavy-handed because it's comedy.
By its nature, it lacks the sobriety of other mediums. Even when it is deadly serious, its style lightens the load,
allowing it to convey content that might otherwise be met with opposition.
19 Just as it is illogical to conclude that all people love chocolate because some people do, one cannot
conclude that all popular fictions are vacuous because some of them are.
20 Also important is the consideration of negative effects that might result from exposure to The
Simpsons and other popular fictions. Because of their range of influence, we must seriously consider the
potential that popular fictions have to generate negative effects. Individuals should be made aware of the
effects that reading or viewing fiction can have so that they can be discriminating in their selection, and
critical in their appropriation, of such works. Presently, the assumption, "It's just fiction!" thwarts most
concern about fiction's influence. However, we could make better use of what fiction has to offer and be less
vulnerable to untoward effects if we recognize the actual influence it exerts.
21 As discussed previously, fiction affects us whether we know it or not. For example, the process of
reading fiction encourages shifts in our patterns of attention whether or not we recognize that these shifts
have taken place. It instructs us to be more attentive to details. This increased attention can certainly be
beneficial. However, this is not the only positive effect fiction can have. Other effects require greater
receptiveness on the part of the individual. For example, if one chooses to view the story about the hare and
the tortoise as just an entertaining tale about animals, it is likely that this is all that it will be. However, if one
is open to the idea that the story can both entertain and instruct -- as children are -- it serves both functions.
Here, I am simply trying to draw attention to how our attitudes can inhibit our acquisition of knowledge.
22 Special thanks to B. Steve Csaki for his help in the preparation of this essay as well as to Dr.
Carolyn Korsmeyer, Dr. James Lawler, Dr. Kah-Kyung Cho, and Dr. Kenneth Inada for their help in the
preparation of my dissertation, the work from which much of this essay derives.
Part IV
The Simpsons and
the Philosophers
16
A (Karl, not Groucho) Marxist
in Springfield
JAMES M. WALLACE
"Humor," E.B. White warned, "can be dissected, as a frog can, but the thing dies in
the process and the innards are discouraging to any but the pure scientific mind."1 A
Marxist dissection, performed by the dour scientific socialist, is almost certain to kill the
humor in any joke as it lays bare the ugly entrails of ideology in the body of bourgeois
comedy. "Reds are such glum, serious people," Tommy Crickshaw (Bill Murray) remarks
in Cradle Will Rock. He's probably right.
It's not that Marxists don't enjoy a good joke; Marx himself tried his hand at writing
comedy, most notably a novel in the style of Tristram Shandy. But humor presents a
difficult challenge for anyone concerned with justice and equity: what's so funny, after all,
in a country where five percent of the people control ninety-five percent of the wealth? Is it
a betrayal of Marxist principles to know that 20 workers are murdered and 18,000 assaulted
each week at their jobs in the United States and to laugh anyway when Apu, the
bullet-scarred convenience store owner, tells Homer, "I won't lie to you. On this job you
will be shot at"? Perhaps The Simpsons' Rabbi Krustofsky is right: "Life is not fun; life is
serious."
But The Simpsons is fun, and the comedy pulls in so many different directions -- the
"something for everyone" phenomenon -- that it may be impossible to watch and not laugh
despite your political or economic point of view. And given that the show is often touted as
"subversive," we might expect it especially to appeal to anyone critical of prevailing
ideologies and interested in how art might be used to shake the foundations of social power.
Recognizing that humor can be very subjective and that an analysis will dampen the
comedy just a bit, let's consider how The Simpsons accomplishes the comic subversion for
which it is so well known.
Thoughtful Laughter
The show could be used in a comedy seminar to define one of the most fundamental
notions of what makes something funny -- incongruity. We tend to laugh hardest at the
linking together of ordinarily incompatible elements, the yoking of ideas, images, feelings,
and beliefs that we normally keep separate in our minds, the disruption of what we consider
usual and conventional, and the thwarting of expectations, or, in Kant's words, "a strained
expectation being suddenly reduced to nothing":2
HOMER: "Oh, my God. Space aliens! Don't eat me! I have a wife and kids. Eat them!" ("Treehouse
of Horror VII")
HOMER: "Oh my God. I got so swept up in the scapegoating and fun of Proposition 24 [to deport
illegal immigrants from Springfield], I never stopped to think it might affect someone I cared about.
You know what, Apu? I am really, really gonna miss you." ("Much Apu About Nothing")
In both of these examples, the comedy derives from the difference between what
we would expect someone to say in similar situations and what actually gets said. Our
expectations depend, of course, on our being familiar with the conventions of behavior
among fathers and friends. A father using his family to plead for his life would normally,
we assume, assert that his family depends on him, not that they could substitute for him.
When the situation is reversed and the family is in danger, the father, according to the
conventional behavior of brave and noble fathers, says "Take me instead." The usual and
expected selflessness of a father is in one mental flash both linked to and contradicted by
Homer's selfish, but hilarious remark. The comedy depends, of course, on the "unreality"
of art; a father who literally sacrifices his children for his own survival is hardly funny. To
be sure, it might be said that a father betraying a son in any context is not comical either,
but in the realm of an art that depends on comic incongruity and "shock," our assumptions
and conventions are brought into relief with the result that we are, perhaps for the first time,
made conscious of them if we pause momentarily to consider why we laughed. Subversion
is possible only after recognition, and The Simpsons, like all comedy based on incongruity,
asks us to at least think about how we normally see the world. In our "normal" view of the
world, fathers should be selfless, loyal providers committed at all costs to the preservation
of their families.
In the second example, Homer's epiphany is completely dissolved when he tells
Apu he will "really, really miss" him. In fact, his emphasis makes the line all the more
comical since it suggests that Homer really, really misses the contradiction between, on the
one hand, the sudden realization that he is partly responsible for his friend's deportation
and, on the other, the kind gesture of telling Apu he'll miss him. In Homer's mind, of course,
there is no contradiction between these two sentiments: he's merely saying "I didn't realize
you'd be leaving; goodbye." But for viewers, brought up learning the conventions of
friendship and expecting the usual introspection and perhaps apology that comes from
someone who has just recognized his complicity in a wrongful act, the line surprises. The
joke would not be funny in a society with values greatly different from our own.
While the humor of the passage depends on our awareness of conventional
behavior and attitudes, the passage is funny on another level as well since it points to some
of the shortcomings of "conventional" thought and behavior, which includes scapegoating
and stereotyping, forgetting that abstract political views have consequences for individuals,
and failing to see the contradictions between our personal and public lives, all of which
Homer is guilty of. In other words, Homer's complicated statement contains several
insightful comments on social behavior and relationships, which we understand to be
satirical comments since we recognize that a more perfect world would contain neither
stereotyping, scapegoating, inconsistent behavior, and so forth. When Homer says, "I got
so swept up in the scapegoating and fun. . .," we see it as comical because the conventional
or common now clashes with the ideal, and we're surprised at the truth in Homer's
comment. After all, people seldom so cavalierly admit to unethical behavior or illogical
thinking. Homer's casual reference to a common practice that no one should be proud of is
comical. As in all satire, an attack against the vice or shortcomings of humankind
presupposes a better world where humans act according to the author's notions of what is
right and proper. In this case, the incongruity serves to draw our attention to common
human behavior (including, perhaps, our own) and to raise doubts about the
appropriateness of that behavior. Such satire often challenges us to question "ordinary"
practices, habits and perspectives and to reflect on how the world might be improved, in
this case to eliminate stereotyping and scapegoating.
Because satire operates at a more intellectual level than, say, slapstick, it requires
more from viewers who are expected, first, to understand what's being ridiculed and,
second, to know what the ideal world is supposed to look like. Anyone familiar with
Swift's "A Modest Proposal", one of the most ingenious satires ever written, knows the
pitfalls of missing the satire and assuming that, in this case, Swift was honestly advocating
eating Irish children rather than calling attention to how the English landlords had,
metaphorically, "devoured" the Irish citizenry and land. The reader or viewer has to "get
it," or the satire fails to make its point. All comedy makes demands of the reader, and satire
perhaps more than any other form. George Meredith, Marx's contemporary and a leading
novelist of the late Victorian age, believed with many writers of the period that literature,
especially drama, should provide lessons regarding the social order and that comedies
which evoked "thoughtful laughter" could draw attention to humanity's foibles and
contribute finally to the amelioration of social ills.3 Aside from "A Modest Proposal" we
might also consider from an earlier age Jonson's Volpone and "Vanity of Human Wishes,"
as well as, later, Byron's Don Juan, in a long list of memorable satires in this vein. While
many modern theorists no longer believe that literature can or should correct society's
problems, most comedies -- even those on television -- still follow the pattern of either
reconstructing society according to a more humane blueprint, or, in the case of satire,
pointing out the habits, vices, illusions, rituals, and arbitrary laws that impede movement
toward a better world.
In the tradition of comedy, then, a subversive satire such as The Simpsons would
aim -- and apparently does aim -- to expose the hypocrisy, pretense, excessive
commercialism, gratuitous violence, and so forth that characterize modern society and to
suggest that something better lies beyond. In Marxian terms, then, satirical comedy like
The Simpsons, it might be argued, distances us momentarily from the prevailing ideology
of capitalist America. The term ideology, as Michael Ryan defines it, "describes the beliefs,
attitudes, and habits of feeling which a society inculcates in order to generate an automatic
reproduction of its structuring premises. Ideology is what preserves social power in the
absence of direct coercion."4 In other words, the selflessness and loyalty we expect of
fathers and the humility and contrition that we expect will follow from hurting our friends
are part of ideology, as are the attitudes that lead to stereotyping and scapegoating and the
values that support our current social relationships or economic conditions. The truly
subversive satire, and especially one that, like The Simpsons, contains so much
misdirection and incongruity, asks us to distance ourselves momentarily from ideology
either to objectify the elements of that ideology (loyalty, humility, contrition) or to "laugh
thoughtfully" at the beliefs, attitudes and habits of feeling that characterize modern society.
Primarily, however, laughter -- which requires intelligence, recognition and distance --
would, for a Marxist, help an audience resist the inculcation of an ideology intended "to
generate an automatic reproduction of its structuring premises" and "to preserve social
power." The habits of competition and of measuring the worth of individuals by
appearances, for example, ingrained in the capitalistic value system, lead to stereotyping.
The comic writer can draw our attention to these habits as habits, not as natural ways of
acting and believing, thereby encouraging us to resist them. The Simpsons' many
stereotypes could be seen, therefore, not as a malicious depiction of ethnic groups, but as a
caution against our tendency to stereotype.
Unlike more traditional and "realistic" shows that reflect and propagate ideology,
The Simpsons offers us a chance to liberate ourselves from it and from the "structuring
premises" -- such as competition, consumerism, blind patriotism, excessive individualism,
and other assumptions -- upon which capitalism is built. In fact, because The Simpsons is a
cartoon, its writers can do things that producers of realistic television cannot do, which
allows them even more room to shatter the illusions of reality and rattle viewers' belief that
capitalism provides the only and natural way of life. Shows that "imitate" life too closely
give the impression that the reality depicted is inescapable and natural. It may not be too
great a stretch, therefore, to suggest that The Simpsons is a sort of Brechtian television
show. Much in the same way that Bertolt Brecht rejected the artificial elements of drama --
the unified plot, sympathetic characters, universal themes -- for techniques that "alienated"
or distanced the audience, The Simpsons scrambles reality, keeping us on our intellectual
toes so that we avoid the stultifying habit of identifying with characters and continue to
assess the ideological content of what we are seeing. The Marxist critic Pierre Macherey
might find in The Simpsons a prime example of "de-centered" art, which scatters and
disperses ideological content, effectively revealing the limits of that ideology.
As just one example of The Simpsons' subversive challenges to capitalist dogma,
which is accomplished through incongruity, the following exchange, which may be too
good to sully with analysis, is among the best in the series:
LISA: If we don't get to the convention soon, all the good comics will be gone!
BART: Ah, what do you care about good comics? All you ever buy is Casper the Wimpy
Ghost.
LISA: I think it's sad that you equate friendliness with wimpiness, and I hope it'll keep you
from ever achieving true popularity.
BART: [showing comics of Casper and Richie Rich] Well, you know what I think? I think
Casper is the ghost of Richie Rich.
LISA: Hey, they do look alike!
BART: Wonder how Richie died.
LISA: Perhaps he realized how hollow the pursuit of money really is and took his own life.
MARGE: Kids, could you lighten up a little? ("Three Men and a Comic Book")
In a radical satire, especially one that contains an exchange like that or the
unrelenting, biting portrayal of the evil Mr. Burns, one might expect a consistent
undercutting and exposure of bourgeois ideology, a long line of barriers against the
inculcation of repressive values. Unfortunately, it doesn't happen.
De Haut en Bas
Because political and social satire in a society built on capitalist values would
almost by definition question those values, a Marxist should feel right at home on
Evergreen Terrace. But that's apparently not the case. In fact, if in the public mind Marxism
is synonymous with Communism (and obviously there is good reason to relate the two),
many fans of The Simpsons will know that Marxists are not welcomed in Springfield.
When Itchy and Scratchy moves to another show, Krusty is forced to substitute a cartoon
featuring "Eastern Europe's favorite cat-and-mouse team, Worker and Parasite," a gloomy
and boring look at the exploitation of the working class that immediately clears Krusty's
television studio. In "Brother From the Same Planet," a recruiter from the Springfield
Communist Party addressees the crowd before the start of a football game. Unfortunately
for the decrepit old recruiter, it's "Tomato Day," and the crowd pelts the recruiter with their
free tomatoes. In "Homer the Great," Grampa Abe Simpson searches his wallet for proof
that he's a member of the fraternal organization, The Stonecutters:
ABE: Oh, sure. Let's see. . . [going through his wallet]. . . I'm an Elk, a Mason, a
Communist. I'm the president of the Gay and Lesbian Alliance for some reason. Ah, here it is -- The
Stonecutters.
Apparently the Communist Party has hoodwinked another confused old man into signing
up, or perhaps the point is that Communism is an old and feeble system, the demise of
which everyone, including the members of Spinal Tap, celebrates:
DEREK: I can't think of anyone who's benefited more from the death of Communism than
us.
NIGEL: Oh, maybe the people who actually live in the Communist countries.
DEREK: Oh yeah, I hadn't thought of that. ("The Otto Show")
While that spoilsport Karl Marx may not be welcomed in Springfield, Groucho
Marx has been spotted in several episodes, either in person (in the crowd around Dr.
Hibbert in "Boy Scoutz 'N the Hood") or in paraphrase in -- of all episodes! -- "Scenes from
the Class Struggle in Springfield." Marge, finally realizing that she has alienated her family
in her attempt to be accepted as a member at the local country club, rejects the country club
set with a version of Groucho's famous line. "I wouldn't want to join any club that would
have this me as a member," Marge declares. The allusion is certainly warranted since the
Marx brothers made a living exposing the pretensions and hypocrisy of high society. But
the paraphrase is truly brilliant. While Groucho was sarcastically renouncing
organizations with standards low enough to admit him, Marge is rejecting one whose
standards allow only "this" Marge, the one who has spent her savings on an impressive
dress, parked the car out of sight, and aggressively ordered her family to suspend their
normal behaviors and to "just be good." It's not a version of Marge she's comfortable with,
and she renounces an ideology that would force her to sacrifice her true identity, her true
essence. Groucho, no stranger to subversion but certainly no Marxist, supplies the
inspiration for Marge's triumphant renunciation of the snobbish country clubbers; and,
even though Karl's ilk are banned from town, she shows a true Marxist sensibility when she
asserts her freedom from a repressive ideology.
But for a Marxist reader there is something disturbing about the final scene in "The
Class Struggle in Springfield." While the upper class has been soundly lampooned, the
episode ends with the Simpson brood back in their place, the more familiar surroundings of
the Krusty Burger:
PIMPLE-FACED KID: [mopping the floor] Hey, did you guys just come from the prom?
BART: Sort of.
MARGE: But, you know, we realized we're more comfortable in a place like this.
PIMPLE-FACED KID: Man, you're crazy. This place is a dump!
While the family wisely turned its back on the cruel and insincere members of the country
club ("I hope she didn't take my attempt to destroy her too seriously," one of them says of
Marge), the Simpson family's defiance against the propertied and golfing class seems
impotent and ineffectual. In fact, the infirmity of their protest had been foreshadowed
earlier in the episode when Lisa, seeing Kent Brockman's daughter huff at a waiter who
brings her a baloney sandwich rather than abalone (which she insists she asked for), is
incensed but immediately becomes distracted at the sight of a man riding a pony, her
favorite animal. Later she is seen riding a pony; "Look, Mom," she yells, "I found
something more fun than complaining."
If Lisa's tirade against insolence and the mistreatment of employees is nothing
more than "complaining" and if she can be silenced by a pony, what are we to make of her
superb comment later in the episode when she approaches the initiation dinner at the club
("I'm going to ask people if they know their servants' last names, or in the case of butlers,
their first") or her astounding Richie Rich comment or any of the ideology-pricking
comments she's made over the years? Certainly, as a little girl, Lisa can be easily distracted
by a favorite animal, so perhaps we shouldn't make too much of her vacillation. But the
episode is indicative of the show's constant undercutting of what comes precariously close
at times to a left-leaning worldview, or to any political stance for that matter, as if the
writers were careful at every step to avoid what could be seen as a consistent political or
social statement. What might have been at least a thorough skewering of the moneyed class
becomes a defeat for the Simpson family's class, the "upper-lower-middle class," as Homer
describes it ("The Springfield Connection") -- that group of people who, though they may
not be the factory workers and miners of the proletariat, must worry about where the
money comes from and how it gets spent. At the end of "The Class Struggle in
Springfield," order is restored at the expense of the Simpsons, who return to their proper
place, the "dump" where they have learned to live "comfortably." It's not clear at the end
who, exactly, is the target of the satire or what better world lies outside the context of the
struggle between one class and another. With the writers' attitude toward Marxism, perhaps
the whole notion of class struggle is being ridiculed. In any case, despite the occasional jab,
usually from Lisa, at capitalism's destructive tendencies, it's Marge's own bourgeois
ideology that accounts for her being "comfortable" in a dump like the Krusty Burger. She
came close to a revolutionary moment, but she's fallen back to a conditioned and quiet
acceptance of things as they are.
The show's subversive label has started to fade, unless of course we are meant to
sympathize with the Simpsons in the final scene. Engels himself noted in an often-cited
letter to a young writer that an author "does not have to serve the reader on a platter the
future historical resolution of the social conflicts which he describes."5 Readers -- or in this
case, viewers -- can do some of the work themselves. But the writers of The Simpsons seem
to have taken pains to avoid earning our sympathy for the family or for anyone who suffers
or endures. In their apparent refusal to pick a side, ridicule is equally distributed among the
powerful and the helpless. While Groucho's banana peels were placed squarely under the
heels of the affluent, the pretentious academics, the corrupt politicians, The Simpsons' are
placed there and everywhere else, so that immigrants, women, the elderly, Southerners,
homosexuals, the overweight, the studious, the politically committed, and every other
marginalized or maligned group take as hard a tumble as the evil captains of industry. No
one seems safe from derision or ridicule.
Take the portrait of workers, for example. Lisa's comment aside, we might expect
those writers who lampooned the golf crowd to then side with the workers, not an
unreasonable assumption given the dismissal of the former group. Throughout The
Simpsons, no such sympathy or empathy is extended; indeed the portrait of workers
suggests that for the writers and producers of this show, subversion does not include
rebelling against unfair labor practices or struggling to improve the condition of the
working class. In "Last Exit to Springfield," the union (the "Brotherhood of Jazz Dancers,
Pastry Chefs, and Nuclear Technicians"), led by workers Lenny and Carl (Lenin and
Marx?) don't give a moment's thought before trading their union's dental plan for the
promise of a keg of beer at every union meeting. A strike ensues, and although the union
wins back the plan by the show's end, it does so only through the stupidity of both Mr.
Burns and union president Homer. In another show about striking employees, teachers
carry picket signs reading "A is for Apple, B is for Raise," and "Gimme, Gimme, Gimme."
The theme of the Springfield Auto Show is "We salute the American worker -- now 61
percent drug free." Many of the characters are defined and identified by their occupations,
and it's hard to think of any, beside Frank Grimes (and he was dispatched in short order),
who isn't a bungler, a loser, inept, crooked, lazy, sycophantic, uneducated, unethical,
criminal, or just plain dumb, Homer, of course, being the obvious example. In one
memorable episode, Homer saves the Shelbyville Nuclear Power Plant from meltdown by
choosing the correct button in a game of eenie-meenie.
It's almost impossible with such a free-floating, top-to-bottom attack to know
precisely what The Simpsons is intended to satirize. It's as if Jonathan Swift, having
shamed the English for devouring the Irish poor, had turned his contempt on the poor
themselves. Because the target is so ill-defined or so all-encompassing, viewers have in
individual episodes apparently missed the intended point. When the Catholic Church took
offense to a parody of Super Bowl commercials, the show's executive producer revised a
key line in re-runs of the episode. The pressure to rewrite hints at the corporate control over
even supposedly subversive shows, but it also points to the fact that in a satire with no
vision of what the world should be, revision is easily accomplished. The show has targeted
pretty much anything its sponsors and its audience will let it get away with. Everything is
fair game.
Without some core value, some vision of what a better world might look like, The
Simpsons does little more than string together isolated and transitory comical moments that
in the aggregate add up to no discernible, consistent political point of view, let alone a
subversive one. In fact, because episodes like "The Class Struggle in Springfield" end with
a restoration of the social order, with the country club set happily in their place and Marge's
family content in their dump, the show subverts its own subversion and merely propagates
rather than tears down the very institutions and social relationships it supposedly attacks.
Class antagonisms, exploited for the humor, are merely propped back up. While the jokes,
taken individually, can be exceptionally funny -- incongruous, surprising, challenging --
taken together in the totality of The Simpsons, they add up only to a view that is at once
nihilistic (everything is a target) and conservative (the traditional social order endures).
The satire collapses in a shower of individual jokes, and we are left with what we had to
start with -- a world of exploitation and struggle. The emphasis is clearly on the joke, on the
one-liner, the comical juxtaposition, the occasional shocking truism in the mouth of a child.
But the greater concerns, such as a consistent political or social philosophy, are ignored.
When Homer utters one of the most memorable lines in the entire series during a quarrel
between his daughter and an Albanian exchange student --
Please, please, kids, stop fighting. Maybe Lisa's right about America being the land of opportunity
and maybe Adil has a point about the machinery of capitalism being oiled with the blood of workers.
("Crepes of Wrath")
we're left wondering how we should respond. Can we take anything Homer says seriously,
or is this just another witty remark in a show filled with witty remarks? Does Homer's
insight have the same weight as some of his other comments?
Aw, Dad, you've done a lot of great things, but you're a very old man, and old people are useless.
("Homer the Vigilant")
"Lisa, if you don't like your job, you don't strike. You just go in every day and do it really half-assed.
That's the American way." ("The PTA Disbands")
Most viewers would know that a wise, sensitive and dialectically minded character might
voice the first sentiment as a mark of universal understanding, but the same character could
not utter the second and third. The inconsistency in Homer's character makes him nothing
more than a conduit for the writers' lines. Each joke is funny in its own small context, but
taken together, the individual jokes amount to very little either in terms of a vision for
improvement or in terms of art that accurately reflects the truth of how people live and act.
Certainly The Simpsons is not realistic television, but an audience has no way of
identifying with a character who, to save a good line for the writers, becomes even less
human and more chameleon. In this case, the writers' sole claim to subversion is to subvert
characterization. Only the joke survives. Nothing is really all that important. The kids have
lightened up. To paraphrase Marx, all that is solid melts into laughter.
It Gets Worse
While The Simpsons -- unlike traditional satire -- hints at no concept of a better
world, it can perhaps be viewed from a Marxist perspective as an accurate reflection of life
in America at the turn of the millennium. Rather than challenge the prevailing ideology,
The Simpsons, like all cultural products, develops from and reflects the material and
historical conditions of the age in which it was created; reflects, in other words, the
ideology of capitalism in late twentieth-century America. That the series in its entirety
ultimately embodies an ideology rather than disrupts it is especially supported by the fact
that this television series is produced not by a single individual writer, although one person
does most of the writing for each episode, but by a team of at least sixteen writers and many
other workers. Because consistency and continuity are difficult for even a single writer
working on a single text, it's surprising that The Simpsons is as uniform as it is. But with so
many minds at work on the show, it can be assumed that the series reveals not the genius
and vision of one person, but the labor of a collective body creating a show in accordance
with the viewpoint of one person (Matt Greening) and intended for mass consumption by a
public attuned to staccato images, disjointed themes and fragments of meaning.
In fact, as the high water mark of postmodern television, this stew of literary
references, cultural allusions, self-reflexive parody, shotgun humor, and absurdly ironic
situations is the inevitable result and perfect depiction of the fragmented, disjointed,
contradictory world of capitalism, where wholeness and consistency are replaced by
increasing disparity not just between the "haves" and "have nots," but between the social
and the individual, the public and private, family and work, the general and the particular,
the ideal and the concrete, word and deed; and where "rebellion" and "revolution" are used
to sell Dodge trucks, promote the Oprah Winfrey show or drum up membership in the
Republican Party. In The Simpsons, as under capitalism, all opposition is absorbed, and
criticism is co-opted. Janis Joplin now sells Mercedes Benz, and the Comic Book Guy
writes to the producers of Itchy and Scratchy in mockery of Internet users who critique The
Simpsons. In The Simpsons everything is up for laughs; under capitalism everything is up
for sale.
If the show is seen to manifest capitalist ideology, then, the vacillating attitude
toward workers in The Simpsons might reflect the ambiguous attitude toward workers
under capitalism, which professes to respect the individuality of every human being but
strips workers of their individuality through alienating work. Perhaps the objectifying of
characters who become stereotypes and mouthpieces for jokes can be seen as a reflection
of capitalism's tendency to reduce social relations to the quality of objects. Although some
Marxist critics such as Georg Lukács, and perhaps even Marx and Engels themselves,
might reject The Simpsons for the unrealistic nature of its characters who are little more
than abstract impersonation of real beings, it might be argued that the show is a more
accurate depiction of the capitalist ideology, in which human beings matter less for their
individual qualities than what they can be used for.
For a Marxist in a good mood, then, The Simpsons could be seen as the creative
embodiment of a particular ideology, so that laughing at the show would be a way of
laughing at the contradictions of capitalism. But, of course, that's not why people are
laughing. Such an interpretation requires an audience attuned to Marxist criticism and
predisposed to see capitalism as a flawed and alienating system. In fact the opposite
appears to be true. The Simpsons is most often praised in such places as Time, The
Christian Science Monitor, The New York Times, National Review, and The American
Enterprise as a show that celebrates the American family, "who stick with one another
through thick and thin"6 or "love one another, no matter what,"7 or that presents characters
who, in their bungling attempts to endure, are ones we can all identify with, or that extols
American values such as rebellion. It's tempting to suggest that these writers have missed
the point of The Simpsons, or to say that of course the family endures else there's no show
next week, or that Bart's rebellion is the kind of safe pestering that the ruling class tolerates
as a safety valve to prevent more serious rebellion. But these writers are actually on the
mark: The Simpsons -- despite its barbs at commercialism and corporations -- not only
reflects, but conserves and propagates a traditional bourgeois ideology. And its success
must be considered at least partly responsible for the trend in television sitcoms and
cartoons toward focusing less on character development and satire and more on one-liners
and often mean-spirited humor that includes no hope for progress.
The popularity of The Simpsons and its acceptance by conservative critics, finally,
proves just how content we are with the ideology of modern America. When Monty Burns
says,
Listen, Spielbergo, [Oskar] Schindler and I are like peas in a pod: we're both factory owners, we
both made shells for the Nazis, but mine worked, dammit! ("A Star is Burns")
we laugh, probably because we are shocked at his blindness to what he is admitting. But
knowing this about him, viewers can continue to laugh at him only because in the broader
context, the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries, we're content and satisfied with
the state of affairs. Auden helps to make the point:
Satire flourishes in a homogenous society with a common conception of the moral law, for satirist
and audience must agree as to how normal people can be expected to behave, and in times of
relative stability and contentment, for satire cannot deal with serious evil and suffering. In an age
like our own [the 1940s and 1950s] it cannot flourish except in private circles and as an expression
of private feuds; in public life, the serious evils are so importunate the satire seems trivial and the
only suitable kind of attack prophetic denunciation.8
For Auden, satire cannot flourish in times of evil and suffering. The Simpsons
flourishes because suffering is not taken seriously. In other words, we can laugh at Mr.
Burns only because we're not terribly bothered by the damage done by the class he
represents. In the world that created The Simpsons, there is no better world and nothing,
really, to worry about. Homelessness, racism, arms sales, political corruption, police
brutality, an ineffective educational system can all be grist for the comedy mill, with the
apparent message that current conditions are simply to be endured, not changed. Of course,
we laugh at things in a cartoon that we wouldn't find funny in "real life," but our
willingness to find The Simpsons funny demonstrates, a Marxist might contend, that if we
truly recognized the violence done to workers, the human costs of stereotyping and
scapegoating, the devastation sanctioned in the pursuit of profit, we couldn't possibly find
The Simpsons comical. In fact, The Simpsons would have to be considered the worst kind
of bourgeois satire since it not only fails to suggest the possibility of a better world, but
teases us away from serious reflection on or criticism of prevailing practices, and, finally,
encourages us to believe that the current system, flawed and comical as it sometimes is, is
the best one possible. A Marxist, even if he or she laughs, has to be disheartened.
The Simpsons is funny. It catches us off guard, setting us up for foiled expectations,
taking us for a joy ride down a fast, straight road and cutting sharply right (sometimes left)
without warning. Often the show challenges and provokes, keeps us alert and attentive,
questions established authority, and exposes the emptiness of many bourgeois values. But
for all its wonderful moments of incongruity and misdirection and its skewering of isolated
sacred cows, the show offers no consistent satire against prevailing ideology, no hope of
progress toward a more just and fair world where the best rather than the lowest
possibilities of humankind are realized. Its contradictions and inconsistencies reflect a
world opposite the integrated, harmonious world Marx envisioned. In the end the show
promotes the interests of the class that maintains economic power over the masses, selling
them T-shirts, key chains, lunch boxes, and video games. Its lack of vision and its equitable
distribution of antagonism make it static and immune to criticism; it can absorb and co-opt
any dialectical challenge and defend itself by appealing, with a wink and a nudge, to the
supremacy of the joke. The jokes may be funny, but in The Simpsons, where no one grows
up and lives never improve, laughter is not a catalyst for change; it is an opiate.9
1 E.B. White, "Some Remarks on Humor." In The Second Tree from the Corner (New York: Harper,
1954), p. 174.
2 Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgement, trans. James Creed Meredith (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1952), p. 199.
3 George Meredith, An Essay on Comedy and the Uses of the Comic Spirit (New York: Scribners,
1897), p. 141.
4 Michael Ryan, "Political Criticism," Contemporary Literary Theory, eds. Douglas Atkins and
Laurie Morrow (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1989), p. 203.
5 Frederick Engels, Letter to Minna Kautsky. In Marx and Engels on Literature and Art (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976), p. 88.
6 Richard Corliss, "Simpsons Forever," Time (2 May 1994), p. 77.
7 M.S. Mason, "Simpsons Creator on Poking Fun," Christian Science Monitor (17 April 1998), p.
B7.
8 W.H. Auden, "Notes on the Comic," Thought 27 (1952), pp. 68-69.
9 I am grateful to Louis Rader for his many suggestions on the numerous drafts of this essay.
17
"And the Rest Writes Itself":
Roland Barthes Watches The Simpsons
DAVID L.G. ARNOLD
In 1978 the publication of Fiske and Hartley's Reading Television solidified the
fledgling field of television studies, using as its foundation the concept of semiotics, the
methodological examination of signs and sign systems. In making this connection Fiske
and Hartley were trying to suggest not only that television shared some of the properties of
language and was thus analyzable using some of the same tools, but also that it was worth
studying at all, that the close analysis of the things television was showing us was
worthwhile, even important. In their introductory chapter they state:
We shall try to show how the television message, as an extension of our spoken language, is itself
subject to many of the rules that have been shown to apply to language. We shall introduce some of
the terms, originally developed in linguistics and semiotics, that can help us successfully decode
the sequence of encoded signs that constitutes any television programme. The medium itself is
both familiar and entertaining, but this should not blind us to its singularity. . . In other words, we
should not mistake an oral medium for an illiterate one.1
In the twenty-two years since this seminal work appeared, the field of television
studies has matured considerably, though it still faces, surprisingly, a great deal of
resistance from mainstream scholars who consider it lowbrow and beneath the dignity of
analysis or even thought. On the other hand, a large part of the serious work currently being
done on television still takes as its starting point a generally structuralist approach. Ellen
Seiter, in "Semiotics, Structuralism, and Television," suggests that the vocabulary of
semiotics allows us to "identify and describe what makes TV distinctive as a
communication medium, as well as how it relies on other sign systems to communicate."2
She goes on to suggest that "By addressing the symbolic and communicative capacity of
humans in general, semiotics and structuralism help us see connections between fields of
study that are normally divided among different academic departments in the university.
Thus they are specially suited to the study of television."3 The versatility that Seiter
describes makes semiotics and structuralism especially useful in the analysis of a complex
text like a television cartoon, despite the limitations now generally recognized in the
structuralist approach.
In this essay I want to examine the insights semiotic analysis can provide into a
complex "text" like The Simpsons. This show, like most contemporary TV shows,
confronts us with a dizzyingly rapid series of messages, and by breaking down these
messages into a simple, repeatable sequence of codes we can begin to see how the show
makes meaning. The art of The Simpsons, though, lies somewhat beyond what
structuralism or semiotics alone can describe, in the way it seems to disrupt the stable,
easily-interpretable diet of images and ideas that television viewers generally expect, and
that the medium tends to encourage. Part of the show's ability to do this lies in the
mechanics of the cartoon itself, a medium that at once suggests and confutes the impression
of verisimilitude. Because it frees the writers from the physical and representational
constraints involved in the use of live actors, the cartoon encourages both creative and
interpretive play. Further, because viewers rightly or wrongly associate cartoons with
childish, harmless, intellectually empty entertainment, the medium is well-situated to
deliver what Douglas Rushkoff calls a "media virus," a subversive or even revolutionary
message conveyed in an apparently innocent, neutral package.4
Semiotics -- Images -- Television
Structuralism emerged in France in the 1950s in the works of thinkers such as
anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss and philosopher-critic Roland Barthes. Early
proponents of structuralism sought to move beyond the subjectivity and impressionism of
earlier schools of criticism by insisting that we see texts as a complex intersection of social,
political, and textual "structures," often expressed as two-sided or binary oppositions like
high/low, self/other, or nature/culture. These structures, they argue, arise from our way of
perceiving reality, and some more radical structuralists suggest that they are in fact
responsible for how we perceive. The bottom line of this method of analysis is its
suggestion that meaning is not inherent in objects themselves but resides outside, in their
relationships to other structures.
We can find an early sustained application of these ideas in Roland Barthes's 1950
work Mythologies.5 In this slender book Barthes lays out the principles of semiotics in an
essay called "Myth Today" and applies them to various phenomena of French popular
culture like professional wrestling, wine, the new Citroen, and gladiator movies. The
central concept of semiotics is the relationship of signs to the objects or ideas they
represent, and the combination of signs into systems called codes. The key to Barthes's
method of analysis is the division of every sign (and, by extension, every message or act of
communication) into components: the "signifier" and the "signified." The signifier is the
element that makes the statement or delivers the message (a word on a page; a note of
music; a photograph), and the signified is the content or idea delivered. Although we can
separate these two elements for analysis, we normally experience them simultaneously as
the "sign." For example, when we go to cross the street we pull up short at the red flashing
outline of the hand. The picture itself is the signifier, a vehicle or delivery system for a
message. We understand the message itself, the signified, because of previous experience
with this symbol. "STOP!" or "Don't cross now!" are the messages the flashing hand
delivers to us, though the words themselves aren't used. The picture (and also its red color
and insistent flashing) is the signifier, and the message we understand is the signified, but
when we come to the crosswalk we don't normally play out this little act of analysis:
signifier and signified act on us simultaneously as what Barthes calls the sign.
This formulation draws on the work of Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure,
whose 1915 Course on General Linguistics is a model for much structuralist thought.
Saussure developed this method of analysis to study language, making the point that the
signifier in a system like language is generally arbitrary or "unmotivated"; that is, unlike
the flashing red hand, the words we speak or write have no organic relationship to the
concepts they denote and function only when the users of the system recognize the codes
being deployed. It is our familiarity with these conventions or codes that allows the sign to
have meaning for us. Certain signifiers, like photographs or realistic portraits, bear or seem
to bear a more direct relationship to their signifieds. These signs are called "iconic" or
"motivated" signs; no special knowledge on our part (knowledge of a certain language, or
of the conventions of portraiture) is required to understand them. But when making sense
of a sign requires an understanding of conventions or codes, the culturally specific aspect
of sign systems starts to move to the fore. Saussure used the term langue to denote the
reservoir of codes in a given system, for instance, the vocabulary of a given language. Each
individual use of the codes from this reservoir is called parole. Thus for speakers of French
the French language represents langue, and a discreet work drawing from that reservoir,
such as a novel by Hugo or Dumas, is an example of parole. These utterances make sense
only to people who are familiar with the codes that make up the French language. Because
the signifier in a language system has little or no organic relationship with the concept it
signifies (except in special cases like onomatopoeia), meaning depends wholly upon
convention, upon recognizing the codes that comprise the act of signification.
As suggested above, applying this method to more complex signifiers like
photographs or teleplays involves deciphering the ways such images become "encoded" or
loaded with meaning. Barthes addresses this question in his 1964 essay "The Rhetoric of
the Image." In this essay he examines a print advertisement for a particular brand of pasta
to show the ways an image functions on both "denotative" and "connotative" levels. Part of
the problem with "reading" images, according to Barthes, is that they function by apparent
analogy rather than by the combination of phonemes (as in written language). In other
words, they appear to be motivated or iconic signifiers. We understand what a picture
"means" partly because we recognize that it looks like something. This is its denotative
meaning. However, he contends that "we never encounter (at least in advertising) a literal
image in the pure state."6 No drawing or photograph in this context comes to us except as
part of a message, part of someone's attempt to communicate something. This is the
image's connotative meaning, a culturally specific message superimposed on the image's
already-present denotative meaning. To decipher this message one must first determine
how it has been "encoded," that is, the degree to which what is otherwise a sign in its own
right (a photograph of a bag of pasta) has been pressed into service to suggest things
beyond its denotative value (the qualities of the pasta that the advertiser wants to highlight
as desirable). Barthes mentions the color scheme of the ad and the presence of green
peppers, fresh tomatoes, and garlic, which he reads as denotation of "Italianicity," an
important quality, we suppose, in choosing which brand of pasta to buy. He also suggests
that the apparent randomness and casualness with which these staples are seen to spill out
of their string-mesh shopping bag suggests a kind of profusion and abundance, designed to
remind the shopper of happy, prosperous homes and well-stocked tables. These features
are part of the constructedness of this photograph, choices made by the advertiser and the
photographer that enhance this "natural" image's power to suggest and persuade.
Thus the photographic image gives rise to a kind of paradox, since as Barthes says,
"the photograph. . . by virtue of its absolutely analogical nature, seems to constitute a
message without a code. . . for of all the kinds of image only the photograph is able to
transmit the (literal) information without forming it by means of discontinuous signs and
rules of transformation."7 Written language works because we know that the letters
represent sounds and that the sounds, when combined according to certain rules, denote
certain concepts. The photograph, on the other hand, appears to be a natural, unmediated
kind of signifier, a straightforward, unaltered representation of the object or concept it
signifies. "In the photograph" Barthes continues,
the relationship of signifieds to signifiers is not one of 'transformation' [as it is in written language]
but of 'recording', and the absence of a code clearly reinforces the myth of photographic
'naturalness': the scene is there, is captured mechanically, not humanly (the mechanical here is a
guarantee of objectivity). Man's interventions in the photograph (framing, distance, lighting, focus,
speed) all effectively belong to the plane of connotation.8
Thus only when we focus on the way a photograph is in fact a product of human
actions and decisions does its coding, its connotative aspect, begin to become clear. And
for Barthes, the unique quality of the photographic message is its ability to silence its own
coding, to make us forget that it has been constructed to bear a message:
to the extent that it does not imply any code. . . the denoted image naturalizes the symbolic
message, it innocents the semantic artifice of connotation. . . Although the Panzani poster [the
photograph advertising pasta] is full of 'symbols', there nonetheless remains in the photograph. . . a
kind of natural being-there of objects: nature seems spontaneously to produce the scene
represented. A pseudo-truth is surreptitiously substituted for the simple validity of openly semantic
systems; the absence of code disintellectualizes the message because it seems to found in nature
the signs of culture.9
The photograph confronts us with a message whose obvious constructedness we
somehow (perhaps willfully) fail to recognize. The result is a signifying system, a way of
making meaning, that seems to us to spring from nature and therefore to represent truth, as
opposed to rhetoric or "semantic systems."
Barthes's purpose in this essay is to reveal the constructedness of what at first
glance seems natural, and to suggest how a constructed image, much like a word or a
sentence, can become encoded or charged with meaning. These ideas apply equally to the
images we see on television, images that are substantially manipulated, constructed,
fabricated, and distorted, but which we tend to receive very passively, as reliable indices of
nature and reality.10
Semiotics and The Simpsons
Most television images qualify as indexical signs, as apparently natural
representations of something that has actually happened. The fact remains, though, that
such images are almost always dictated by convention and are susceptible to extensive
modification by their producers. The original physical object may or may not have been
photographed, but through sophisticated manipulation viewers can be convinced that it
was. According to Barthes cinematic (and by extension televisual) drama functions less
like an indexical sign than photographs because the function of narrative, of storytelling,
tends to stylize and regularize the images we see; they become less motivated, less
"natural," and more mediated by conventions.
This is where our discussion of the signifying aspects of a narrative cartoon like
The Simpsons begins. Animated television narratives still function to some small degree as
indexical signs, but the representations are extensively mediated, fully conventionalized.
Nonetheless, a sign system like a cartoon can't work without at least a nod toward
verisimilitude. Indeed, The Simpsons gets its energy precisely from the conflict between
our recognition of the signifiers as highly mediated, as un-realistic, and our understanding
that they nonethelsss resemble a reality we recognize. The show's satiric power, indeed its
very coherence, depends on this sometimes-tenuous resemblance.
This aspect of the television cartoon, and specifically of The Simpsons, will come
out in our discussion, but I would like to begin our analysis of an episode of the show with
a more traditional structuralist approach and demonstrate both what this can reveal about
televisual narratives, and what its limitations might be.
As I suggested earlier, the structuralist tends to see in narratives or texts a series of
generalized binary oppositions, larger structures of which the individual signs are
manifestations, and to make inferences from this about a specific culture's world-view and
habits of perception. In the Simpsons episode titled "The Front" a number of these
binarisms suggest themselves immediately. In this episode Bart and Lisa decide, after
watching "a rather lifeless" episode of their favorite TV cartoon Itchy and Scratchy, that
they could write better cartoons themselves. After having their script rejected they
resubmit it under Grampa's name because they suspect that, as children, they aren't being
taken seriously. A structuralist would see a number of binarisms operating in this situation.
The first is the opposition between reality and fiction. As they register their disappointment
with the Itchy episode Lisa says, "The writers should be ashamed of themselves."
"Cartoons have writers?" Bart asks, puzzled. "Well, sort of," Lisa says. This exchange
suggests that the distinction between constructed narratives and experienced reality
operates only very limitedly in Bart's mind, a blurring of boundaries that is in fact one of
the show's central tropes.
Another binary opposition suggested by this initial setup is that between youth and
inexperience on one hand and age, experience, and wisdom on the other. This is, arguably,
the structure on which this particular episode is largely based, and we will explore it in
detail. Beyond this, we can also see a fundamental, indeed a classic, binarism at work in the
Itchy genre itself: the cat-mouse opposition. A genre critic might examine this traditional
structure of children's cartoons in terms of its long history, from Tom and Jerry through
Pixie and Dixie and beyond. We might also ask what underlies this conception of the
relationship between cats and mice, and why in traditional cat and mouse cartoons the
mouse is cast as positive and the cat negative.11 Structuralists, however, are less concerned
with the historical or generic implications of these structures, and would likely focus
instead on the implied distinction between the natural (animals) and the cultural (speech
and human-like emotions) and how the cat and mouse cartoon tends to blur them.
Let us examine the episode's central structure, the opposition between youth and
experience. It is evident from the outset that this fairly standard conception is to be offered
up for examination and satire. Before Bart and Lisa's foray into cartoon writing is even set
up we witness an inverted vision of the traditional, "natural" relationship between parents
("wise," "experienced") and their children ("naïve," "untutored") when we see Homer
moaning because he's got a plunger stuck on his head. The basic signifiers being deployed
here are the father figure, supposed generally to represent authority and sagacity, and the
toilet plunger, clearly reductive of that authority. In fact, the combination of the two
signifiers suggests a radical, scatological undermining of the concept of parental authority.
No explanation is given for Homer's predicament except that he says "Marge, it happened
again." This suggests that this is a recurring problem, and that Homer seems unable to learn
from the experience (in fact, the last scene of the episode shows him as an old man arriving
at his 50th high school reunion suffering from the same problem). Bart and Lisa, on the
other hand, appear to have the situation summed up and dealt with. "What are you
changing your name to when you grow up?" Bart asks. The children have determined that
the way to overcome the genetic tyranny that identifies them as Homer's experiential
inferiors is to opt out of their family heritage altogether. Thus the episode's first scene
presents us with a traditional structure and its refutation.
As the children confront the inadequacy of TV writing and storm the citadel of
corporate cartoon production, they are faced again with the traditional binary opposition
between age and youth that causes the grownups in charge to undervalue their efforts. At
every turn the narrative works to undercut this binarism's validity. We discover that
Grampa, whose name they use as a signifier of age and authority, doesn't even know his
name, and has to check his underwear for confirmation. Again, this pair of signifiers (the
wise old man and the underwear) effects a scatological reduction of the traditional
age-youth binarism. Once Grampa is (fraudulently) installed as a staff writer at Itchy &
Scratchy Studios, the president, Roger Meyers, introduces him to the other writers, whom
Meyers excoriates as a pack of Ivy-League "eggheads" with no real-life experience. One
pipes up: "Actually, I wrote my Master's thesis on life experience. . ." but Meyers silences
him and asks Grampa to expound on his own fascinating life. "I worked for forty years as a
night watchman in a cranberry silo," Grampa says. Meyers seems impressed, but we pick
up on the implied absurdity of valuing this kind of deadening, definitively tedious labor as
educative or empowering.
A structuralist reading of this episode would, then, focus largely on the ironic
treatment of this binary opposition and reach the conclusion that the narrative draws satiric
energy from the apparent reversal of our expectations about age and youth. As I suggested
above, though, this approach is limited by the scope of the questions it chooses to ask. With
a text like The Simpsons, we can profit by a more detailed analysis not only of the structural
oppositions the signifiers imply, but what those signifiers actually are and how they
operate.
The Animated Signifier
Recalling Barthes's comments about the signifying power of the image, we would
say that a drawing like a Simpsons character displays a high degree of conventionalization;
that is, we must supply a fair amount of cultural knowledge for these images to make sense.
Despite their similarity to human beings, most of the members of the Simpson family are
highly stylized drawings, really only suggestions of the human form. Nonetheless we do
recognize them as representations of a certain segment of American society: the drawings
and characterizations are accurate enough that they can function as satire. Homer's weight
problem and beer consumption and Bart's spiky, bad-boy haircut and skateboard are
recognizable features of a late twentieth-century landscape, and they help us understand
how these signifiers are supposed to function, what they're supposed to be making fun of.
But the fact that the characters are patently not quite human increases their ability to
function as satiric signifiers. Physical attributes, habits, and actions we could not accept as
possible for a human (or a drawing supposed to represent a human) become a regular part
of The Simpsons' repertoire, allowing them to venture further into the realm of the
ridiculous than human actors or realistic drawings.
One example of this drawn from "The Front" is Grampa's method of verifying his
identity. When he whips off his underwear to check on his name he doesn't bother to
remove his pants. The children are stunned and ask how he managed such a feat, and he
shudders and says, "I don't know." It is frankly difficult to pin down exactly what this
combination of signifiers might mean beyond what we discussed above, but what is clear is
that the scene moves the status of these signifiers as signifiers to the fore. The narrative is
insisting here that we remember that these are cartoon characters. This, I think, is the key to
the rhetoric of these images. The writers are having it both ways: by insisting up front that
verisimilitude is not an issue, by exploiting the absurd and the fantastic, they can satirize
American society more effectively. Because they can dislocate the relationship between
signifier and signified, they gain unlimited latitude in what they can depict or suggest, and
this renders the show, predictably, more suggestive. Freed from the mundane restrictions
of live action or realistic representation, the animation nevertheless retains an
always-foregrounded referentiality. Comments about Marge's unfeasible blue hair or the
family's yellow skin remind us regularly that the characters aren't real, and this enhances
our reception of them as signifiers: their capacity to represent things is never clouded by
the impression that they might also be real people. Nothing but the show's own
self-referentiality intrudes on our suspension of disbelief.
Beyond this, the very status of The Simpsons as a television cartoon affects the way
its signifiers operate. Our responses are conditioned because we know it's "only" a cartoon.
This is precisely the fate of other "adult" cartoons like The Flintstones and Wait 'Til Your
Father Gets Home. Originally intended as prime-time shows for grownups, these were
relegated, to a large extent by an imperceptive audience, to the realm of children's
programming. The medium here obviates the message. We also see this in the way old
movie theater cartoons like Bugs Bunny, originally short features intended to entertain
adults, descended inevitably to Saturday morning. The Simpsons (as well as many of the
newer generation of "postmodern" cartoons like Beavis and Butthead, Ren and Stimpy,
Family Guy, and others) capitalizes on this misperception, flying under the radar, as it were,
of our rational minds. Cartoons are safe, childlike, part of the world of play as opposed to
more overtly serious television fare like soap operas or newscasts. Virus-like, the show
lulls us into lowering our intellectual defenses, then infects us with satiric, subversive
ideas.
The way signifiers are used in The Simpsons and their apparent dislocation from the
kinds of signifieds we expect takes us slightly beyond the realm in which structuralism
proper can answer our questions. Barthes, in the later, post-structural phase of his career,
discusses this kind of textual play in his 1970 book S/Z. In this work, an in-depth semiotic
analysis of a short story by Balzac, he defines what he calls a "classic text," one that is
closed to the possibilities of connotation. Such a text works on a purely denotative level,
and the reader is never encouraged to speculate beyond what the narrator or other authorial
voice asserts. According to Barthes, this implies a kind of law or religion of "right" reading:
the text cannot be "written" or added to substantively by the reader. Reading it is
essentially a passive activity, and hence Barthes calls these "readerly" texts. The opposite
of this classic or readerly text is the "writerly" or "plural" text, one that encourages free
play on the part of both reader and writer and is richly connotative, is in fact open-ended
with regard to its ultimate meaning. "To read," according to Barthes, "is to find meanings,
and to find meanings is to name them; but these named meanings are swept toward other
names; names call to each other, reassemble, and their grouping calls for further naming: I
name, I un-name, I rename: so the text passes: it is a nomination in the process of becoming,
a tireless approximation, a metonymic labor."12 Reading is thus an activity that
paradoxically effects its own undoing as the "tireless approximations" compound and are
swept away by new associations. For Barthes, in this later phase of his career, the more
valuable activity is not making meaning but forgetting it:
. . . reading does not consist in stopping the chain of systems, in establishing a truth, a legality in the
text, and consequently in leading its reader into "errors"; it consists in coupling these systems, not
according to their finite quantity, but according to their plurality. . . : I pass, I intersect, I articulate, I
release, I do not count. Forgetting meanings is not a matter for excuses, an unfortunate defect in
performance; it is an affirmative value, a way of asserting the irresponsibility of the text, the
pluralism of systems. . . : it is precisely because I forget that I read.13
The Simpsons, I submit, is precisely an "irresponsible" text, one rich in associations
and connotations and perversely unwilling to have those connotations pinned down. It is
"postmodern" in the sense that it comes together as a self-parodic, self-referential pastiche
of previous texts. It is satiric in that it occupies the signifiers of the culture it wishes to
lampoon and amplifies that culture's foibles up to and beyond the point of absurdity. But it
is irresponsible in that it cheerfully resists, indeed makes fun of, even the kind of friendly
analysis we're attempting here.
To solidify this point, let us take a final look at "The Front," this time specifically
the Itchy and Scratchy episode that Bart and Lisa write because they find the ones being
produced so unsatisfying. They choose a barbershop as the setting and Lisa invents a
scenario in which Itchy cuts off Scratchy's head with a razor. "Aw, too predictable," Bart
says: "The way I see it, instead of shampoo, Itchy covers Scratchy's hair with barbecue
sauce, opens a box of flesh-eating ants, and the rest writes itself." What happens next, the
part that "writes itself," deserves some attention. After the flesh-eating ants have stripped
Scratchy's head to a bare skull, Itchy activates the lift on the barber chair, sending Scratchy
crashing through the ceiling and through the bottom of a television set on the floor above.
An Elvis impersonator is watching the television, and after staring at Scratchy's skeletal
head for a beat he says, "Aw, this show ain't no good," pulls out a revolver, and shoots the
television.
What I find interesting about this, beyond the plethora of bafflingly rich signifiers,
is specifically the idea that such a scene could "write itself," that it could spring as it were
unbidden from a reservoir of common, easily accessible cultural codes. That Itchy should
ram Scratchy through the ceiling is in keeping with The Itchy and Scratchy Show's rhythm
of ever-escalating violence, but the presence of the Elvis impersonator seems less
predictable. Bart's comment implies, though, that Elvis impersonators using handguns as
TV remote controls are an organic part of the culture he's writing from; they are, to his eye,
stable, reliable, easily-recognizable signifiers.
Signifiers of what? The television set is a familiar image in The Simpsons, and its
presence at the forefront of Bart's imagination is not surprising. Each episode of the show,
in fact, is preceded by what is called a "couch gag," a scene in which the family rushes into
the living room to begin the evening ritual of TV watching. Directly following this scene
the final frame of opening credits appears framed by a TV set, complete with VCR and
rabbit ears, giving the impression that we and the family are watching the same TV. This
occurs, as I mentioned, before every episode, and serves as a kind of index, a reminder that
the show is formally concerned with television, and with it own status as television. In
Bart's script for the Itchy and Scratchy episode the centrality of television is foregrounded
when Scratchy becomes a television character (a cat in a cartoon) forced into the role of a
television character (an image in/on the Elvis impersonator's TV). The Elvis
impersonator's critique of this "program," his judgment that "this show ain't no good" and
his decision therefore to shoot his television, takes this act of mirroring one step further by
replicating Bart and Lisa's original dissatisfaction with Itchy and Scratchy. Our own status
as viewers and critics completes this circle and situates the discourse firmly on television
and the many ways we consume it.
The presence of the Elvis impersonator is harder to pin down. We can read him,
perhaps, as a signifier of our society's willingness to commodify and commercialize
personality, an example of the potential of mass-produced star power to sell products
across many media. Beyond this, of course, is the aura of obsessive craziness surrounding
this icon of American popular culture. Elvis Presley the performer brought the genre of
rock 'n' roll to the attention of the nation and the world, making up with energy what its
detractors claimed it lacked in cultural significance. His work signaled, in the orgiastic
adoration of the fans, some kind of turning point in the battle between high and low
cultures. In the decades since his death his continued "presence," in the form of numerous
"Elvis-sightings" and of the thriving industry of Elvis impersonators, testifies to the weird
energy and durability of his memory.
The King, random handgun use, business-as-usual violence, and the ubiquity of
television map out Bart's conception of his culture. He has acquired this culture, the show
suggests, as a result of careless and misguided parenting, a slipshod educational system, an
all-encompassing environment of consumerism and commodification, and, of course,
television. Ultimately, this new Elvis narrative and its creation invite us to consider the
cultural act of creating (televisual) texts: writing is a social activity, a way of having a
voice. One of the specific signifieds of this segment is the search for quality television and
the logical response to lo-grade TV (either shoot it or write something better).
The fact that we see Bart's text as more sophisticated than the Itchy and Scratchy
being produced by Ivy-League graduates is itself richly suggestive. Our structural analysis
of "The Front" discovered that its aim was to satirize the easy binarism that privileges age
over youth, but we must also now question the very signifiers themselves, not just the
structures they imply. We might argue that this text satirizes a society in which such
signifiers are readily available, where Elvis writes himself. Implicitly, the perfection of an
Itchy and Scratchy episode has to do with arabesques of violence, specifically creative,
intriguing violence. Merely to see a mouse strike a cat on the head with a hammer is too
pedestrian, a readerly as opposed to a writerly situation, a classic text. Bart's text is more
open to connotation, less stable.
Perhaps, then, we can define the richness of a Simpsons text as a matter of openness
to connotation, an openness to the allure of free-floating signifiers that coalesce and
disperse apparently randomly, "data," as Barthes puts it, "seemingly lost in the natural flow
of discourse."14 The apparent randomness with which The Simpsons cites particular
signifieds defines its method of signifying. Of this kind of randomness of association
Barthes says:
This fleeting citation, this surreptitious way of stating themes, this alternating of flux and outburst,
create together the allure of the connotation; the semes appear to float freely, to form a galaxy of
trifling data in which we read no order of importance; the narrative technique is impressionistic: it
breaks up the signifier into particles of verbal matter which make sense only by coalescing: it plays
with the distribution of a discontinuity (thus creating a character's "personality"); the greater the
syntagmatic distance between two data, the more skillful the narrative; the performance consists in
manipulating a certain degree of impressionism: the touch must be light, as though it weren't worth
remembering, and yet, appearing again later in another guise, it must already be a memory; the
readerly is an effect based on the operations of solidarity (the readerly "sticks"); but the more this
solidarity is renewed, the more the intelligible becomes intelligent. The (ideological) goal of this
technique is to naturalize meaning and thus to give credence to the reality of the story.13
In a "classic" text, in The Honeymooners, in All in the Family, even in The
Flintstones, the signifieds eventually coalesce into "meaning." In The Simpsons that
coalescence is deferred indefinitely. The classic text loses its plurality because we expect
all the actions (eventually) to be coordinated; like an ear trained to hear the predictable
cadences and resolutions of western music, the readerly eye demands an eventual
uniformity. Like the narrative in a novel by Dickens, the storyline in an episode of Dynasty
or Fresh Prince of Bel-Air takes us in a very predictable direction and culminates in a
satisfying sense of resolution. The writerly or plural text like The Simpsons, however,
resists this push to conform. By foregrounding its signifiers and cheerfully dislocating
them from stable, predictable signifieds, the show permits a freer, more richly associative
kind of reading, and effects a more penetrating social satire. Barthes's "galaxy of trifling
data" aptly describes Bart's world of Elvis-impersonators and flesh-eating ants, the world
with which The Simpsons presents us, the skill of the narrative arising, as Barthes suggests,
from the "distance between" the data, between denotation and connotation, between
signifier and signified. It's a random, absurd world; to admit that it is really our own, to
admit that we have to this extent lost control of the mechanisms of stability and meaning
would be too embarassing. We find instead that we must laugh, if only in self-defense.
1 John Fiske and John Hartley, Reading Television (London: Methuen, 1978) pp. 16-17.
2 Ellen Seiter, "Semiotics, Structuralism, and Television" in Robert C. Allen, ed., Channels of
Discourse Reassembled: Television and Contemporary Criticism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Press, 1987), p. 31.
3 Ibid., p. 32.
4 Douglas Rushkoff, Media Virus: Hidden Agendas in Popular Culture (New York: Ballantine,
1994).
5 Roland Barthes, Mythologies, trans. Annette Lavers (London: Paladin, 1973).
6 Roland Barthes, Image-Music-Text, trans. Stephen Heath (New York: Noonday, 1977), p. 42.
7 Ibid., pp. 42-43, my emphasis.
8 Ibid. p. 44.
9 Ibid., p. 45.
10 Barthes makes the comment that applying these ideas about the rhetoric of a photograph to cinema,
which is after all just a rapid sequence of photographs, can be more difficult because of the exaggerated sense
of immediacy, of "a being-there of the thing." We experience cinema (and television moreso, I suggest) as
more immediate, more directly involving. Barthes suggests that "the photograph must be related to a pure
spectatorial consciousness and not to the more projective, more 'magical' fictional consciousness on which
film by and large depends." Although Barthes suggests that this imposes a "radical opposition" between film
and photographic images, we can still, I believe, productively apply his ideas about the meaning-power of
images to a discussion of animated television shows, perhaps more so because the television cartoon, unlike
the large-screen movie drama, in certain tantalizing ways works against the "projective," "magical"
suspension of disbelief upon which cinema depends (Ibid., p. 45).
11 We could speculate at great length about The Itchy and Scratchy Show's relationship to this genre,
and in fact this is a matter of some extended discussion in The Simpsons. See for instance "The Day the
Violence Died" in which Bart meets Chester J. Lampwick, creator of Itchy and Scratchy and self-proclaimed
father of cartoon violence; see also "Itchy and Scratchy: The Movie" in which we see a history of Itchy and
Scratchy.
12 Roland Barthes, S/Z, trans. Richard Miller (New York: Hill and Wang, 1974), p. 11.
13 Ibid., p. 11.
14 Ibid., p. 22.
15 Ibid., p. 23.
18
What Bart Calls Thinking
KELLY DEAN JOLLEY
"What is called thinking?" At the end we return to the question we asked at first when we
found out what our word "thinking" originally means. Thanc means memory, thinking that recalls,
thanks.
But in the meantime we have learned to see that the essential nature of thinking is
determined by what there is to be thought about: the presence of what is present, the Being of
beings.
-- Martin Heidegger
Once more and they think to thank you.
-- Getrude Stein
Cowabunga, dude!
-- Bart Simpson
Introduction
Strange, I guess, to take Bart Simpson as Muse. Stranger still, I guess, is taking Bart
as the Muse for philosophy. (There is no Muse for philosophy -- and if there were, it
wouldn't be Bart Simpson!)
I take Bart as my Muse because of a feature of Bart's engagement with the world,
whether that engagement is reflective or active. Bart's world, the world, just ain't in Bart's
head. Bart's world is out there. This omnipresent out-thereness (for lack of a better term) is
what makes Bart a Heideggerian thinker. Bart's world is a world of faces, not facades; it is
a world personified. And Bart's thoughts go out to meet it. But all this needs to be made
clear.
I shall begin by discussing a philosophical example that deserves the fame of
Socrates's triangle in the dirt, Descartes's lump of wax, or Price's red tomato -- Heidegger's
tree in bloom. Discussing the tree will clarify what Heidegger calls thinking. I shall finish
by showing Bart Simpson as a Heideggerian thinker.
Since what is to follow is difficult, I want to say a few things by way of setting the
stage. Arthur Schopenhauer opens his The World as Will and Representation by claiming
that the beginning of philosophical wisdom is recognizing that the world is idea.
Schopenhauer glosses this by claiming that the philosopher recognizes that the world is in
his head. By 'the world' Schopenhauer means everything. I think Schopenhauer has put his
finger on the live nerve of much philosophizing: the philosophical thought par exellence is
that all I am acquainted with is the insides of my head. Everything else I get to by some
type of wishful thinking -- inferring, guessing, postulated causal connections. What I do
here is trace out a response to the philosophical thought par exellence, a response that looks
as radical as what it responds to. I want to trace out a way of thinking about thought itself
on which not only is the world not inside our heads, but our thoughts are not inside our
heads. Put it this way: when we think, our thoughts are wherever what we are thinking
about is.
One helpful hint for following my discussion: the backbone of the discussion is the
series of quotations from Heidegger, Schopenhauer, and Frege. And the most crucial of
these is the one from Frege. Both Heidegger and Frege are trying to dislodge thoughts from
inside the head. I try to show how Heidegger and Frege are akin, and how they are different.
Getting clear about that will show both what Heidegger and Frege reject in Schopenhauer,
and what Heidegger rejects in Frege. And that will lead us back to Bart.
Heidegger's Tree
In What is Called Thinking?, Heidegger introduces the tree in bloom:
We stand outside of science. Instead we stand before a tree in bloom, for example -- and the tree
stands before us. The tree faces us. The tree and we meet one another, as the tree stands there
and we stand face-to-face with it. As we are in this relation of one to the other and before the other,
the tree and we are. This face-to-face meeting is not, then, one of those "ideas" buzzing about in
our heads. Let us stop here for a moment, as we would to catch our breath before and after a leap.1
I will, for now, set aside Heidegger's introductory "We stand outside of science."
What I want to focus on is the way in which Heidegger personifies the tree in bloom.
According to Heidegger, the tree and we both have faces: the tree faces us; we stand
face-to-face with the tree; each of us is before the other. Why does Heidegger personify the
tree in bloom?
I take it that the answer to this question comes in what Heidegger denies about the
meeting with the tree: "This face-to-face meeting is not, then, one of those "ideas" buzzing
about in our heads." Heidegger personifies the tree so as to depersonalize it. What I mean is
that Heidegger personifies the tree as a way of insisting that the tree is, indeed, before us,
separate from us. The tree is not our idea.2
To better understand what I take Heidegger to be doing, consider the following
famous passage from Schopenhauer (Heidegger prefaces his tree-in-bloom-passage with a
parallel passage from Schopenhauer):
"The world is my idea": -- this is a truth which holds good for everything that lives and knows, though
man alone can bring it into reflective and abstract consciousness. If he really does this, he has
attained to philosophical wisdom. It then becomes clear and certain to what he knows is not a sun
and an earth, but only an eye that sees a sun, a hand that feels an earth; that the world which
surrounds him is there only as an idea, i.e., only in relation to something else, the consciousness,
which is himself. If any truth can be asserted a priori, it is this: for it is the expression of the most
general form of all possible and thinkable experience. . . No truth is therefore more certain, more
independent of all others, and less in need of proof than this, that all that exists for knowledge, and
therefore this whole world, is only object in relation to subject, perception of a perceiver, in a word
idea. . . The world is idea.3
Schopenhauer personalizes the world: the world is our idea. And so, too, of course,
would be the tree in bloom. The tree, like the field in which it grows, the earth of which the
field is part, the sun that shines -- all are our ideas; all are buzzing about in our heads.
Schopenhauer personalizes the tree, makes it ours. Heidegger personifies the tree, makes it
an other, other than ours. And he treats doing this as requiring a great leap: after doing it we
must pause to catch our breath. Heidegger explains the need for rest:
For that is what we are now, men who have leapt, out of the familiar realm of science and even, as
we shall see, out of the realm of philosophy. And where have we leapt? Perhaps into an abyss?4
Heidegger thinks that standing face-to-face with the tree requires that we leap from
psychology and science, and even from philosophy. Evidently, in science and philosophy,
trees lack faces.5 (Personalized trees are not personified.) But where do trees have faces?
Where have we leapt? Where is there to be. . . besides in the realm of science or the realm
of philosophy? Into what Looking-Glass World is Heidegger asking us to leap? Surely,
beyond science and philosophy there is only the abyss.
Heidegger responds to his question, perhaps we have leapt into an abyss?, by
replying
No! Rather onto some firm soil. Some? No! But on that soil upon which we live and die, if we are
honest with ourselves. A curious, indeed unearthly thing that we must first leap onto the soil on
which we really stand.6
Heidegger's claim is that we have leapt onto the firm soil of our lives. What is
striking here, and what Heidegger underscores as "curious, indeed unearthly" is that we
have to leap from the familiar -- science, philosophy -- onto the unfamiliar, the firm soil of
our lives. We have to leap to get to where we always already are.
Thinking Outside the Head
I want momentarily to step away from the tree in bloom. What I take Heidegger to
be doing in this passage is battling a commitment shared by our familiar science and
philosophy, namely a commitment to psychologism. Psychologism, briefly, is best thought
of as a family of views. Each such view maintains that a subject-matter, say logic or morals
or thought, is a branch of psychology. As a result, the laws of that subject-matter are rightly
understood as generalizations over the goings-on in the human head. So, for example, a
psychologistic logician would treat the laws of logic as generalizations over the inferential
goings-on of the human head. Also, Heidegger's objection to the claim that the tree in
bloom is an idea buzzing in our head is an objection to a psychologistic claim.
Psychologism personalizes trees -- it personalizes the fields, etc. It does so by
treating them as ideas, buzzings in the head, psychological. Heidegger hints at this in the
passage immediately before the discussion of the tree in bloom, when he comments that in
order to understand thinking we must leave psychology to one side. Of course, given his
indebtedness to Husserl, Heidegger's anti-psychologism is not exactly surprising. But what
is surprising is the way in which, and the depth at which, Heidegger battles psychologism.
To make this clear, I want to compare Heidegger's anti-psychologism with Frege's. The
comparison will also serve as a bridge from the tree in bloom to what Heidegger calls
thinking.
Frege waged a lifelong war with psychologism. Frege over and over again engages
the psychologistic thinker, showing her that psychologism so misshapes her ostensible
topics as to render them unrecognizable. For example, in his famous paper "Thought,"
Frege turns on the same notion that Heidegger turns on when discussing the tree in bloom,
the notion of ideas. (Interestingly, Frege, too, uses a tree as an example.) Frege's argument
is lengthy (but I quote it in full):
Yet there is a doubt. Is it at all the same thought which first this and then that man expresses?
A man who is still unaffected by philosophy first of all gets to know things he can see and
touch. . . such as trees, stones and houses, and he is convinced that someone else can equally see
and touch the same tree and the same stone as he himself sees and touches. Obviously a thought
does not belong with these things. Now can it, nevertheless, like a tree be presented to people as
the same?
Even an unphilosophical man soon finds it necessary to recognize an inner world distinct
from the outer world, a world of sense impressions, of creations of his imagination, of sensations. . .
For brevity's sake, I want to use the word 'idea' to cover all these occurrences. . .
Now do thoughts belong to this inner world? Are they ideas?. . . How are ideas distinct from
the things of the outer world? First: ideas cannot be seen, or touched, or smelled, or tasted, or
heard.
I go for a walk with a companion. I see a green field, I thus have a visual impression of the
green. I have it, but I do not see it. Secondly: ideas are something we have. . . An idea that
someone has belongs to the content of his consciousness.
The field and the frogs in it, the sun which shines on them, are there no matter whether I
look at them or not, but the sense impression I have of green exists only because of me, I am its
owner. . . The inner world presupposes somebody whose inner world it is.
Thirdly: ideas need an owner. Things of the outer world are on the contrary independent. . .
My companion and I are convinced that we both see the same field; but each of us has a
particular sense impression of green. . .
Fourthly: every idea has only one owner; no two men have the same idea.
For otherwise it would exist independently of this man and independently of that man. Is
that lime tree my idea? By using the expression 'that lime tree' in this question I am really already
anticipating the answer, for I mean to use this expression to designate what I see and other people
too can look at . . .7
Frege is trying to accomplish two things here: first, he's trying to show that the
denizens of the inner world, ideas, are not thoughts. Ideas play no role in logic, as thoughts
do. The things buzzing in our heads are not thoughts, nor are they parts of thoughts.
Buzzings in our heads are not thoughts, since thoughts -- like lime trees, fields, and frogs --
are sharable and have no owner.
By 'thought' Frege means such ordinary, garden-variety things as "There are lime
trees" or "Tigers are animals" or "2 + 2 = 4." Frege's denial that thoughts have owners
needs to be understood in light of the act-content distinction: of course my thinking (act) of
the thought (content) that tigers are animals is owned -- I do the thinking; it's my thinking.
But the thought is not mine: any number of different people could have it; the thought is
sharable. If we both think that tigers are animals, then we share a thought.
Second, Frege is trying to show that ideas are not things, denizens of the outer
world. Schopenhauer's claim that the world is my idea would be greeted with the same sort
of response that the Frege gives to the question "Is that lime tree my idea?"
Now Frege goes on from this discussion of ideas to argue that thoughts, although
they are like lime trees, fields, and frogs, are also unlike them: thoughts are not perceptible
-- they are grasped or thought, not seen, heard, touched, or tasted. Frege then takes this to
show that thoughts are neither in the inner world nor in the external world. Instead, he takes
thoughts to be in the Third Realm:
So the result seems to be: thoughts are neither things in the external world nor ideas.
A third realm must be recognized. Anything belonging to this realm has it in common with
ideas that it cannot be perceived by the senses, but has it in common with things that it does not
need an owner so as to belong to the contents of his consciousness.
So an integral part of Frege's anti-psychologism is his Third Realm. What is important here
is that Frege's war with psychologism shares Heidegger's tactic of showing that ideas do
not have any role to play of the sort we think when we do science or philosophy (they are
neither things nor thoughts). However, Frege's war differs from Heidegger's in requiring
that to avoid psychologism we must leap from psychology or science into a Third Realm --
not onto the firm soil of our lives.
For Frege, thoughts are not in the head. But since they are not in the outer world,
either, they must be in some third place, The Third Realm. Heidegger shares Frege's
conviction that thoughts are not in the head. But he does not share Frege's conviction that
there must be a Third Realm -- or, better, Heidegger does not share Frege's conception of
the Third Realm. Explaining this will take some effort.
What Is Called Thinking
Perhaps the best way to begin is by giving the game away: Heidegger thinks that
the firm soil of our lives is the Third Realm. But what could this mean? The inner world is
not the firm soil of our lives. Is the outer realm the firm soil? No, the outer realm is the
realm of causation, science. When we stand on the firm soil we stand outside both
psychology (inner world) and science (outer world) -- so we stand in the Third Realm. But
Frege's Third Realm seems a strange land, and, as fleshly creatures, we seem strangers in it.
So how can the firm soil of our lives be the Third Realm?
Answering this requires thinking back to Husserl and then forward to Heidegger.
Famously, Husserl called thinkers to philosophy (phenomenology) with the cry, "Back to
things themselves." The way back to things themselves was methodologically strait -- it
required mastery of a new kind of seeing, mastery of epoche8 and it required mastery of a
bizarre new vocabulary in which to communicate the results of the new kind of seeing. If
Husserl's descriptions of the new kind of seeing and of what is seen by it are looked at
closely, we recognize how much the intentional realm (what is looked into in epoche)
resembles Frege's Third Realm. Indeed, although there are particular problems with saying
so, it makes useful sense to say that looking into the intentional realm just is looking into
Frege's Third Realm.9
By the time of his later writings, Heidegger has brooded over every feature of
Husserl's method. In fact, Heidegger has internalized the method to a remarkable degree.
But Heidegger wants the method to yield what Husserl promised -- a pathway back to
things themselves. From Heidegger's perspective, any method that takes me to the
intentional realm is not a method that takes me back to things themselves.10 (Husserl ends
up sounding too much like Schopenhauer, despite Husserl's struggle not to sound idealistic,
psychologistic. Things in the intentional realm show us facades merely, not faces.11)
Heidegger contrasts Husserl's epoche with his own (which will become the clearing):
For Husserl, [epoche]. . . is the method of leading phenomenological vision from the natural attitude
of the human being whose life is involved in the world of things and persons back to the
transcendental life of consciousness. . . in which objects are constituted as correlates of
consciousness. For us, [epoche] means leading phenomenological vision back from the
apprehension of a being, whatever may be the character of that apprehension, to the
understanding of the being of this being. . .12
In Heidegger's terms, the problem of Husserl's method is that in epoche "objects are
constituted as correlates of consciousness" -- they are ideas. In my terms, the problem is
that in epoche objects are personalized.
Heidegger responds to this problem by personifying the method itself and what the
method shows us. The method, since in Husserl's hands it took us to the intentional realm,
shows us what is personal, seemed itself to be personalized. Heiddegger depersonalizes it
by personifying it. How?
Heidegger takes the key features of the method and finds a way to bring the
practitioner of the method into a different relationship with those features, a different way
of conceptualizing them. So, Heidegger takes epoche out of the intentional, personal realm
and personifies it -- the epoche becomes the clearing. In the clearing, we can apprehend the
being of a being, apprehend the being as it is, where it is. In the clearing, the objects that we
face, and that face us, are not correlates of consciousness. No, since they and we stand
face-to-face, the objects are others -- they are personified. It is in the clearing that we can
come face-to-face with a tree, for instance, or with a Greek Temple. The epoche provides
only the tree-in-brackets, only the Temple-in-brackets. The epoche moves them, so to
speak, from the soil on which they stand into the intentional realm; the epoche personalizes
them. But the clearing lets the tree and the Temple stand where they stand, allows us to
come face-to-face with them, while standing on the soil with them. In brackets, the tree and
the Temple seem to be all facing surface -- seem to lack backs. But anything without a back
is something that cannot really be confronted face-to-face. Only in the clearing do the tree
and the Temple have backs, only there can I confront them face-to-face. In the clearing, the
tree and Temple are personified. To replace the epoche with the clearing requires us to leap
back to where we already stand. In the clearing we can come back to the things themselves.
In What Is Called Thinking?, Heidegger struggles to find a way to situate thinking
so that we can find a way not to psychologize thinking -- but also so that we can find a way
not to put thinking into the Third Realm as Frege understood the Third Realm. To do so,
Heidegger works back to Parmenides, and to Parmenides's famous and famously obscure
lines -- "One should both say and think that Being is"13 and "For it is the same to think and
to be." Now, I do not propose to follow the torturous windings of Heidegger's examination
of these lines. All I propose to do is to characterize the motive behind the examination.
What Heidegger is after is thought personified, not thought personalized. The attraction of
Parmenides's line is that it seems to place thought in the clearing -- it puts thought before us,
so that we can stand face-to-face with it. For Heidegger, Parmenides is attempting to do for
thought what Heidegger does for the tree. Parmenides is attempting to show us how to meet
our thoughts and not merely how to have them. For Heidegger, correctly following
Parmenides is a matter of thinking of our thoughts as themselves such as to be what we are
thinking of. To borrow a line of Wittgenstein's, thought so understood would be thought
that "does not stop anywhere short of the fact."14 To think such thoughts would be to think
outside the head. Fully articulating such an understanding of thought is more than even
Heidegger tries to do. What is Called Thinking? ends by pointing us in the direction of
Parmenides's pointing, and by helping us to understand why we should want to be pointed
that way. (As I will try to make clear below, and as I hinted at the beginning, what
Heidegger struggles to articulate is something that Bart manages effortlessly to live.)
Back now to a question that I may seem to have forgotten: How can the firm soil of
our lives be the Third Realm? The short answer is this: we have to see the firm soil of our
lives in the clearing -- we have to personify the soil. Doing so requires that we leap to
where we already are, doing so requires us to stand outside of psychology, outside of
science. Put it this way: to see the firm soil of our lives in the clearing, to personify it, is to
see (nothing other than) the spatial and temporal phenomena of our lives. But it is to see
these phenomena as we see a chess piece when we are playing chess, and not as we see a
chess piece when we describe its physical properties.15 So seen, the soil stands before us, it
stands where it stands. And we stand before it: we come face-to-face with where we stand.
By personifying the firm soil of our lives, by seeing it in the clearing, we see it as fit
for thought, as fit to be the content of thought. The things we think about no longer seem
alien to our thoughts, cut off from us, veiled by ideas. The things we think about are now
things that our thoughts reach out to and embrace. Our acts of thinking have the
spatio-temporal phenomena of our lives as their content. The world is all the things that are
fit for thought. Or, to quote Wittgenstein once more, "The world is everything that is the
case."16 And, what is the case is what we can think.
What Bart Calls Thinking
Bart Simpson helps to clarify what anti-psychologistic, personified thinking is.
Bart is, in all that he thinks and does, face-to-face with things. He stands outside of science,
but squarely in front of whatever engages him, present to it as it is present to him. For Bart,
nothing is merely in his head. There is no psychological, personal intermediary between
him and the world. For Bart, everything is personified. Everything is in the clearing.
When Bart gets something right, he does not take that to be a matter of having
something intermediary (between him and the world) correspond with the world. No, he
takes that to be a matter of having taken the world in hand or in mind.
That he does so puts Bart firmly among things, a being among beings. Bart's
thinking is determined by what there is to think about. That it is so determined makes Bart's
thinking peculiarly responsive to what there is, to what presents itself to him. This, I think,
is the source of many of Bart's singular existential powers: his mighty resourcefulness, his
preternatural knack to court and avoid danger and trouble, his oracular gift for predicting
the path of events. (I do not claim Bart always uses his powers for good!) Unlike the rest of
us, the rest of Springfield, who are saddled with the personal, who take ourselves to be
screened from the world by intermediaries -- by ideas buzzing in our heads -- Bart is
undistracted by buzzings, he is without screens, he is unsaddled.
Bart's thinking is intrinsically directed to the world. Bart is not stymied by
philosophical puzzlers like "How does thought hook onto the world?" A quick glance at
Bart in action shows that Bart would reject that question, if he were asked it, with a blank
stare. Bart takes the world to be in his thoughts, he takes his thoughts to be world-involving.
Since he does, there's no philosophical hooking of thought to world needed. It is Bart's
lived rejection of this question that makes him appropriate to begin and end this paper. To
his Heideggerian thinking I attribute Barts' powers to amuse, to bemuse, to be a Muse.
Now, can I prove that Bart is a Heideggerian thinker? No -- at least not as proving is
normally understood. The best I can do is what I have done: elucidate Heideggerian
thinking and then lay the elucidation alongside Bart, hoping that an internal relationship (a
relationship such that standing in it is essential to each relatum) between the two shows
itself. (Think of this procedure as roughly comparable to the following: I make clear to you
what ducks are, provide pictures of them, then present you with Jastrow's Duck-Rabbit. If
all has gone well, an internal relationship between the duck pictures and the Duck-Rabbit
should show itself.) No example I might provide from The Simpsons will clinch my claim
-- any example of that sort I might provide would be imponderable evidence at best. The
relationship between what Heidegger calls thinking and what Bart calls thinking is
something that I can help someone to see -- and I have tried to do so. But the relationship is
wrongly conceived if it is taken to be something that could fall out, consequentially, from a
syllogism.
1 Martin Heidegger. What Is Called Thinking? trans. J. Glenn Gray (New York: Harper and Row,
1968), p. 41.
2 Since I shall use these terms, and since they may not be made completely clear in my use of them,
let me say that to personify something is to treat it as an other, as independent of me, as something that is and
does on its own and in its own way. Hence the importance of faces -- something regarded as having a face is
something personified. (Think here of C.S. Lewis's novel, Till We Have Faces, part of the point of which is
that here -- short of heaven -- we are not fully personified, we do not have faces.) To personalize something is
to treat it as mine, as dependent on me, as something that is and does dependently on me. So, for example,
ideas as they figure in the coming quotations from Schopenhauer, Heidegger, and Frege, are personal(ized).
As Frege puts it, ideas are something we have, something we own. (Something personified is not something
that we have or own.)
3 Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation Vol. 1, trans E.F.J. Payne (Indian
Hook, Colorado: Falcon Wing Press, 1958), p. 1. I use this passage instead of its parallel since I think it is
clearer. (The parallel passage can be found in Vol. II, pp. 3-4.)
4 What Is Called Thinking?, p. 41.
5 By 'philosophy' Heidegger means philosophy as it has been and is done by others -- not philosophy
as he does it.
6 What Is Called Thinking?, p. 41.
7 Gottlob Frege. Logical Investigations, trans Peter Geach and R. H. Stoothoff (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1977), pp. 13-16.
8 Here are Husserl's instructions for epoche, for bracketing: "We put out of action the general thesis
which belongs to the natural standpoint, we place in brackets whatever it includes respecting the nature of
Being: this entire natural world therefore which is continually 'there for us', 'present to our hand', and will
ever remain there, is a 'fact-world' of which we continue to be conscious, even though it pleases us to put it in
brackets. If I do this, as I am fully free to do, I do not then deny this 'world', as though I were a sophist, I do
not doubt that it is there as though I were a skeptic; but I use the phenomenological [epoche], which
completely bars me from using my judgment that concerns spatio-temporal existence. Thus all sciences
which relate to this natural world, though they stand never so firm to me, though they fill me with wondering
admiration, though I am far from any thought of objecting to them in the least degree, I disconnect them all, I
make absolutely no use of their standards, I do not appropriate a single one of the propositions that enter into
their systems. . . -- so long, that is, as it is understood in the way the sciences themselves understand it, as a
truth concerning the realities of this world. I may accept it only after I have placed it in the bracket. That
means: only in the modified consciousness of the judgment as it appears in disconnexion. . ." Edmund
Husserl, Ideas, trans. W.R. Boyce Gibson (New York: Collier, 1962), pp. 99-100. When Heidegger
personifies epoche as the clearing he (putting this picturesquely and oversimply) takes the framing brackets
of epoche, which enclose a screen filled with two-dimensional intentional items (ideas), tilts the brackets
down to lie on the ground, and removes the screen -- so that the things themselves, and not their intentional
counterparts, can stand in the brackets, which now frame the clearing.
9 I will side-step the problems with saying this, since they are not stumbling-blocks in my path.
10 Whether Heidegger is right about this is a difficult question. For now I will ignore the question,
treating Heidegger as if he were right, without arguing that he is.
11 For Heidegger, the tree in bloom that we stand before is not a two-dimensional section of our
bracketed visual fields -- it is not in our heads, a mere correlate of consciousnesses. Nothing in our heads
could stand before us, meet us, face us. We cannot stand before, meet, or face an idea.
12 Martin Heidegger, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans. Albert Hofstadter
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982), p. 21.
13 By the time Heidegger finishes with this line, it has become: "Useful is the letting-lie-before-us,
so (the) taking-to-heart, too: beings in being". Cf. What Is Called Thinking?, p. 228.
14 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (New York:
MacMillan, 1953), 95. For more on this conception of thought, see John McDowell, Mind and World
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 27ff. See also his "Putnam on Mind and Meaning" in
Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 275-291.
15 Compare Philosophical Investigations, 109.
16 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Mineola, New York: Dover, 1999), p. 1.
Episode Titles
SEASON ONE 1989-1990
1. "Simpsons Roasting on an Open Fire" (7G08) - December 17, 1989
2. "Ban the Genius" (7G02) - January 14, 1990
3. "Homer's Odyssey" (7G03) - January 21, 1990
4. "There's No Disgrace Like Home" (7G04) - January 28, 1990
5. "Bart the General" (7G05) - February 4, 1990
6. "Moaning Lisa" (7G06) - February 11, 1990
7. "Call of the Simpsons" (7G09) - February 18, 1990
8. "The Telltale Head" (7G07) - February 25, 1990
9. "Life on the Fast Lane" (7G11) - March 18, 1990
10. "Homer's Night Out" (7G10) - March 25, 1990
11. "The Crepes of Wrath" (7G13) - April 15, 1990
12. "Krusty Gets Busted" (7G12) - April 29, 1990
13. "Some Enchanted Evening" (7G01) - May 13, 1990
SEASON TWO 1990-1991
14. "Bart Gets an F" (7F03) - October 11, 1990
15. "Simpson and Delilah" (7F02) - October 18, 1990
16. "Treehouse of Horror" (7F04) - October 25, 1990
17. "Two Cars in Every Garage and Three Eyes on Every Fish" (7F01) - November 1,1990
18. "Dancin' Homer" (7F05) - November 8, 1990
19. "Dead Putting Society" (7F08) - November 15, 1990
20. "Bart vs. Thanksgiving" (7F07) - November 22, 1990
21. "Bart the Daredevil" (7F06) - December 6, 1990
22. "Itchy & Scratchy & Marge" (7F09) - December 20, 1990
23. "Bart Gets Hit By A Car" (7F10) - January 10, 1991
24. "One Fish, Two Fish, Blowfish, Blue Fish" (7F11) - January 24, 1991
25. "The Way We Was" (7F12) - January 31, 1991
26. "Homer vs. Lisa and the 8th Commandment" (7F13) - February 7, 1991
27. "Principal Charming" (7F15) - February 14, 1991
28. "Oh Brother, Where Art Thou?" (7F16) - February 21, 1991
29. "Bart's Dog Gets an F" (7F14) - March 7, 1991
30. "Old Money" (7F17) - March 28, 1991
31. "Brush with Greatness" (7F18) - April 11, 1991
32. "Lisa's Substitute" (7F19) - April 25, 1991
33. "The War of the Simpsons" (7F20) - May 2, 1991
34. "Three Men and a Comic Book" (7F21) - May 9, 1991
35. "Blood Feud" (7F22) - July 11, 1991
SEASON THREE 1991-1992
36. "Stark Raving Dad" (7F24) - September 19, 1991
37. "Mr. Lisa Goes to Washington" (8F01) - September 26, 1991
38. "When Flanders Failed" (7F23) - October 3, 1991
39. "Bart the Murderer" (8F03) - October 10, 1991
40. "Homer Defined" (8F04) - October 17, 1991
41. "Like Father Like Clown" (8F05) - October 24, 1991
42. "Treehouse of Horror II" (8F02) - October 31, 1991
43. "Lisa's Pony" (8F06) - November 7, 1991
44. "Saturdays of Thunder" (8F07) - November 14, 1991
45. "Flaming Moe's" (8F08) - November 21, 1991
46. "Burns Verkaufen Der Kraftwerk" (8F09) - December 5, 1991
47. "I Married Marge" (8F10) - December 26, 1991
48. "Radio Bart" (8F11) - January 9, 1992
49. "Lisa the Greek" (8F12) - January 23, 1992
50. "Homer Alone" (8F14) - February 6, 1992
51. "Bart the Lover" (8F16) - February 13, 1992
52. "Homer at the Bat" (8F13) - February 20, 1992
53. "Separate Vocations" (8F15) - February 27, 1992
54. "Dog of Death" (8F17) - March 12, 1992
55. "Colonel Homer" (8F19) - March 26, 1992
56. "Black Widower" (8F20) - April 8, 1992
57. "The Otto Show" (8F21) - April 23, 1992
58. "Bart's Friend Falls in Love" (8F22) - May 7, 1992
59. "Brother, Can You Spare Two Dimes?" (8F23) - August 27, 1992
SEASON FOUR 1992-1993
60. "Kamp Krusty" (8F24) - September 24, 1992
61. "A Streetcar Named Marge" (9F18) - October 1, 1992
62. "Homer the Heretic" (9F01) - October 8, 1992
63. "Lisa the Beauty Queen" (9F02) - October 15, 1992
64. "Treehouse of Horror III" (9F04) - October 29, 1992
65. "Itchy & Scratchy: The Movie" (9F03) - November 3, 1992
66. "Marge Gets a Job" (9F05) - November 5, 1992
67. "The New Kid on the Block" (9F06) - November 12, 1992
68. "Mr. Plow" (9F07) - November 19, 1992
69. "Lisa's First Word" (9F08) - December 3, 1992
70. "Homer's Triple Bypass" (9F09) - December 17, 1992
71. "Marge vs. the Monorail" (9F10) - January 14, 1993
72. "Selma's Choice" (9F11) - January 21, 1993
73. "Brother From the Same Planet" (9F12) - February 4, 1993
74. "I Love Lisa" (9F13) - February 11, 1993
75. "Duffless" (9F14) - February 18, 1993
76. "Last Exit to Springfield" (9F15) - March 11, 1993
77. "So It's Come to This: A Simpsons Clip Show" (9F17) - April 1, 1993
78. "The Front" (9F16) - April 15, 1993
79. "Whacking Day" (9F18) - April 29, 1993
80. "Marge in Chains" (9F20) - May 6, 1993
81. "Krusty Gets Kancelled" (9F19) - May 13, 1993
SEASON FIVE 1993-1994
82. "Homer's Barbershop Quartet" (9F21) - September 30, 1993
83. "Cape Feare" (9F22) - October 7, 1993
84. "Homer Goes to College" (1F02) - October 14, 1993
85. "Rosebud" (1F01) - October 21, 1993
86. "Treehouse of Horror IV" (1F04) - October 28, 1993
87. "Marge on the Lam" (1F03) - November 4, 1993
88. "Bart's Inner Child" (1F05) - November 11, 1993
89. "Boy-Scoutz 'n the Hood" (1F06) - November 18, 1993
90. "The Last Temptation of Homer" (1F07) - December 9, 1993
91. "$pringfield (Or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Legalized Gambling)"
(1F08) - December 16, 1993
92. "Homer the Vigilante" (1F09) - January 6, 1994
93. "Bart Gets Famous" (1F11) - February 3, 1994
94. "Homer and Apu" (1F10) - February 10, 1994
95. "Lisa vs. Malibu Stacy" (1F12) - February 17, 1994
96. "Deep Space Homer" (1F13) - February 24, 1994
97. "Homer Loves Flanders" (1F14) - March 17, 1994
98. "Bart Gets an Elephant" (1F15) - March 31, 1994
99. "Burns' Heir" (1F16) - April 14, 1994
100. "Sweet Seymour Skinner's Baadasssss Song" (1F18) - April 28, 1994
101. "The Boy Who Knew Too Much" (1F19) - May 5, 1994
102. "Lady Bouvier's Lover" (1F21) - May 12, 1994
103. "Secrets of A Successful Marriage" (1F20) - May 19, 1994
SEASON SIX 1994-1995
104. "Bart of Darkness" (1F22) - September 4, 1994
105. "Lisa's Rival" (1F17) - September 11, 1994
106. "Another Simpsons Clip Show" (2F33) - September 25, 1994
107. "Itchy & Scratchy Land" (2F01) - October 2, 1994
108. "Sideshow Bob Roberts" (2F02) - October 9, 1994
109. "Treehouse of Horror V" (2F03) - October 30, 1994
110. "Bart's Girlfriend" (2F04) - November 6, 1994
111. "Lisa on Ice" (2F05) - November 13, 1994
112. "Homer Bad Man" (2F06) - November 27, 1994
113. "Grandpa vs. Sexual Inadequacy" (2F07) - December 4, 1994
114. "Fear of Flying" (2F08) - December 18, 1994
115. "Homer the Great" (2F09) - January 8, 1995
116. "And Maggie Makes Three" (2F10) - January 22, 1995
117. "Bart's Comet" (2F11) - February 5, 1995
118. "Homie the Clown" (2F12) - February 12, 1995
119. "Bart vs. Australia" (2F13) - February 19, 1995
120. "Homer vs. Patty and Selma" (2F14) - February 26, 1995
121. "A Star is Burns" (2F3D - March 5, 1995
122. "Lisa's Wedding" (2F15) - March 19, 1995
123. "Two Dozen and One Greyhounds" (2F18) - April 9, 1995
124. "The PTA Disbands" (2F19) - April 16, 1995
125. "'Round Springfield" (2F32) - April 30, 1995
126. "The Springfield Connection" (2F21) - May 7, 1995
127. "Lemon of Troy" (2F22) - May 14, 1995
128. "Who Shot Mr. Burns? (Part One)" (2F16) - May 21, 1995
SEASON SEVEN 1995-1996
129. "Who Shot Mr. Burns? (Part Two)" (2F20) - September 17, 1995
130. "Radioactive Man" (2F17) - September 24, 1995
131. "Home Sweet Homediddly-Dum-Doodily" (3F01) - October 1, 1995
132. "Bart Sells His Soul" (3F02) - October 8, 1995
133. "Lisa the Vegetarian" (3F03) - October 15, 1995
134. "Treehouse of Horror VI" (3F04) - October 29, 1995
135. "King-Size Homer" (3F05) - November 5, 1995
136. "Mother Simpson" (3F06) - November 19, 1995
137. "Sideshow Bob's Last Gleaming" (3F08) - November 26, 1995
138. "The Simpsons 138th Episode Spectacular" (3F31) - December 3, 1995
139. "Marge Be Not Proud" (3F07) - December 17, 1995
140. "Team Homer" (3F10) - January 7, 1996
141. "Two Bad Neighbors" (3F09) - January 14, 1996
142. "Scenes From the Class Struggle in Springfield" (3F11) - February 4, 1996
143. "Bart the Fink" (3F12) - February 11, 1996
144. "Lisa the Iconoclast" (3F13) - February 18, 1996
145. "Homer The Smithers" (3F14) - February 25, 1996
146. "The Day the Violence Died" (3F16) - March 17, 1996
147. "A Fish Called Selma" (3F15) - March 24, 1996
148. "Bart on the Road" (3F17) - March 31, 1996
149. "22 Short Films About Springfield" (3F18) - April 14, 1996
150. "Raging Abe Simpson and His Grumbling Grandson in 'The Curse of the Flying
Hellfish' " (3F19) - April 28, 1996
151. "Much Apu About Nothing" (3F20) - May 5, 1996
152. "Homerpalooza" (3F21) - May 19, 1996
153. "Summer of 4 ft. 2" (3F22) - May 19, 1996
SEASON EIGHT 1996-1997
154. "Treehouse of Horror VII" (4F02) - October 27, 1996
155. "You Only Move Twice" (3F23) - November 3, 1996
156. "The Homer They Fall" (4F03) - November 10, 1996
157. "Burns, Baby Burns" (4F05) - November 17, 1996
158. "Bart After Dark" (4F06) - November 24, 1996
159. "A Milhouse Divided" (4F04) - December 1, 1996
160. "Lisa's Date With Density" (4F01) - December 15, 1996
161. "Hurricane Neddy" (4F07) - December 29, 1996
162. "El Viaje Misterioso de Nuestro Jomer (The Mysterious Voyage of Homer)"(3F24) -
January 5, 1997
163. "The Springfield Files" (3G01) - January 12, 1997
164. "The Twisted World of Marge Simpson" (4F08) - January 19, 1997
165. "Mountain of Madness" (4F10) - February 2, 1997
166. "Simpsoncalifragilisticexpiala (Annoyed Grunt) cious" (3G03) - February 7, 1997
167. "The Itchy & Scratchy & Poochie Show" (4F12) - February 9, 1997
168. "Homer's Phobia" (4F11) - February 16, 1997
169. "Brother From Another Series"(4F14) - February 23, 1997
170. "My Sister, My Sitter" (4F13) - March 2, 1997
171. "Homer vs. the Eighteenth Amendment" (4F15) - March 16, 1997
172. "Grade School Confidential" (4F09) - April 6, 1997
173. "The Canine Mutiny" (4F16) - April 13, 1997
174. "The Old Man and The Lisa" (4F17) - April 20, 1997
175. "In Marge We Trust" (4F18) - April 27, 1997
176. "Homer's Enemy" (4F19) - May 4, 1997
177. "The Simpsons Spin-Off Showcase" (4F20) - May 11, 1997
178. "The Secret War of Lisa Simpson" (4F21) - May 18, 1997
SEASON NINE 1997-1998
179. "The City of New York vs. Homer Simpson" (4F22) - September 21, 1997
180. "The Principal and the Pauper" (4F23) - September 28, 1997
181. "Lisa's Sax" (3G02) - October 19, 1997
182. "Treehouse of Horror VIII" (5F02) - October 26, 1997
183. "The Cartridge Family" (5F01) - November 2, 1997
184. "Bart Star" (5F03) - November 9, 1997
185. "The Two Mrs. Nahasapeemapetilons" (5F04) - November 16, 1997
186. "Lisa the Skeptic" (5F05) - November 23, 1997
187. "Realty Bites" (5F06) - December 7, 1997
188. "Miracle on Evergreen Terrace" (5F07) - December 21, 1997
189. "All Singing, All Dancing" (5F24) - January 4, 1998
190. "Bart Carny" (5F08) - January 11, 1998
191. "The Joy of Sect" (5F23) - February 8, 1998
192. "Das Bus" (5F11) - February 15, 1998
193. "The Last Temptation of Krust" (5F10) - February 22, 1998
194. "Dumbbell Indemnity" (5F12) - March 1, 1998
195. "Lisa, the Simpson" (4F24) - March 8, 1998
196. "This Little Wiggy" (5F13) - March 22, 1998
197. "Simpson Tide" (3G04) - March 29, 1998
198. "The Trouble With Trillions" (5F14) - April 5, 1998
199. "Girly Edition" (5F15) - April 19, 1998
200. "Trash of the Titans" (5F09) - April 26, 1998
201. "King of the Hill" (5F16) - May 3, 1998
202. "Lost Our Lisa" (5F17) - May 10, 1998
203. "Natural Born Kissers" (5F17) - May 17, 1998
SEASON TEN 1998-1999
204. "Lard of the Dance" (5F20) - August 23, 1998
205. "The Wizard of Evergreen Terrace" (5F21) - September 20, 1998
206. "Bart, the Mother" (5F22) - September 27, 1998
207. "Treehouse of Horror IX" (AABF01) - October 25, 1998
208. "When You Dish Upon a Star" (5F19) - November 8, 1998
209. "D'Oh-in' in the Wind" (AABF02) - November 15, 1998
210. "Lisa Gets an 'A' " (AABF03) - November 22, 1998
211. "Homer Simpson in: 'Kidney Trouble' " (AABF04) - December 6, 1998
212. "Mayored to the Mob" (AABF05) - December 20, 1998
213. "Viva Ned Flanders" (AABF06) - January 10, 1999
214. "Wild Barts Can't Be Broken" (AABF07) - January 17, 1999
215. "Sunday, Cruddy Sunday" (AABF08) - January 31, 1999
216. "Homer to the Max" (AABF09) - February 7, 1999
217. "I'm With Cupid" (AABF11) - February 14, 1999
218. "Marge Simpson in: 'Screaming Yellow Honkers' " (AABF10) - February 21, 1999
219. "Make Room for Lisa" (AABF12) - February 28, 1999
220. "Maximum Homerdrive" (AABF13) - March 28, 1999
221. "Simpsons Bible Stories" (AABF14) - April 4, 1999
222. "Mom and Pop Art" (AABF15) - April 11, 1999
223. "The Old Man and the 'C Student" (AABF16) - April 25, 1999
224. "Monty Can't Buy Me Love" (AABF17) - May 2, 1999
225. "They Saved Lisa's Brain" (AABF18) - May 9, 1999
226. "30 Minutes Over Tokyo" (AABF20) - May 16, 1999
SEASON ELEVEN 1999-2000
227. "Beyond Blunderdome" (AABF23) - September 26, 1999
228. "Brother's Little Helper" (AABF22) - October 3, 1999
229. "Guess Who's Coming to Criticize Dinner" (AABF21) - October 24, 1999
230. "Treehouse of Horror X" (BABF01) - October 31, 1999
231. "E-I-E-I-(Annoyed Grunt)" (AABF19) - November 7, 1999
232. "Hello Gutter, Hello Fadder" (BABF02) - November 14, 1999
233. "Eight Misbehavin'" (BABF03) - November 21, 1999
234. "Take My Wife, Sleaze" (BABF05) - November 28, 1999
235. "Grift of the Magi" (BABF07) - December 19, 1999
236. "Little Big Mom" (BABF04) - January 9, 2000
237. "Faith Off (BABF06) - January 16, 2000
238. "The Mansion Family" (BABF08) - January 23, 2000
239. "Saddlesore Galactica" (BABF09) - February 6, 2000
240. "Alone Again Natura-Diddily" (BABF10) - February 13. 2000
241. "Missionary Impossible" (BABF11) - February 20, 2000
242. "Pygmoelian" (BABF12) - February 27, 2000
243. "Bart to the Future" (BABF13) - March 19, 2000
244. "Days of Wine and D'oh'ses" (BABF14) - April 9, 2000
245. "Kill the Alligator and Run" (BABF16) - April 30, 2000
246. "Last Tap Dance in Springfield" (BABF15) - May 7, 2000
247. "It's A Mad, Mad, Mad, Mad Marge" (BABF18) - May 14, 2000
248. "Behind the Laughter" (BABF19) - May 21, 2000
SEASON TWELVE 2000-2001*
249. "Treehouse of Horror XI" (BABF21) - November 1, 2000
250. "A Tale of Two Springfields" (BABF20) - November 5, 2000
251. "Insane Clown Poppy" (BABF17) - November 12, 2000
252. "Lisa the Tree Hugger" (CABF01) - November 19, 2000
253. "Homer vs. Dignity" (CABF04) - November 26, 2000
254. "The Computer Wore Menace Shoes" (CABF02) - December 3, 2000
255. "The Great Money Caper" (CABF03) - December 10, 2000
256. "Skinner's Sense of Snow" (CABF06) - December 17, 2000
257. "HOMR" (BABF22) - January 7, 2001
258. "Pokey Mom" (CABF05) - January 14, 2001
259. "Worst Episode Ever" (CABF08) - February 4, 2001
260. "Tennis the Menace" (CABF07) - February 11, 2001
261. "Day of the Jackanapes" (CABF10) - February 18, 2001
262. "New Kids on the Blecch" (CABF12) - February 25, 2001
263. "Hungry Hungry Homer" (CABF09) - March 4, 2001
264. "Bye Bye Nerdie" (CABF11) - March 11, 2001
265. "Simpson Safari" (CABF13) - April 1, 2001
* This was the most up to date information at the time this book went to press. For additional episode
information see The Simpsons Archive http: www.snpp.com/
Based on Ideas By
Thales (ca. 624-546 B.C.E.)
"All things are full of gods and have a share of soul."
Anaximander (ca. 611-546 B.C.E.)
"From what source things arise, to that they return of necessity when they are
destroyed; for they suffer punishment and make reparation to one another for their injustice
according to the order of time."
Lao Tzu (born ca. 604 B.C.E.)
"He who knows does not speak. He who speaks does not know. Close the mouth."
Anaximenes (ca.585-528 B.C.E.)
"Air is the principle of existing things; for from it all things come-to-be and into it
they are again dissolved."
Buddha (560-480 B.C.E.)
"All humanity is sick. I come therefore to you as a physician who has diagnosed
this universal disease and is prepared to cure it."
Confucius (ca.551-479 B.C.E.)
"Great man is always at ease; petty man is always on edge."
Heraclitus (died ca. 510-480 B.C.E.)
"You cannot step twice into the same river, for other waters and yet others go ever
flowing on."
Parmenides (515-445 B.C.E.)
"For never shall this be proved, that things that are not are."
Socrates (470-399 B.C.E.)
"Wealth does not bring about excellence, but excellence brings about wealth and all
other public and private blessings for men."
Plato (428/7-348/7 B.C.E.)
"Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading
men genuinely and adequately philosophize, that is, until political power and philosophy
entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are
forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils. . . nor, I think, will the
human race."
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.)
"That which is proper to each thing is by nature best and most pleasant for each
thing; for man, therefore, the life according to reason is best and most pleasant, since
reason more than anything else is man. This life therefore is also the happiest."
Epicurus (341-270 B.C.E.)
"We recognize pleasure as the first and natural good; starting from pleasure we
accept or reject; and we return to this as we judge every good thing, trusting this feeling of
pleasure as our guide."
Epictetus (50-130)
"It is not the things themselves that disturb men, but their judgments about these
things."
Marcus Aurelius (121-180)
"Everything that happens is as normal and as expected as the spring rose or the
summer fruit; this is true of sickness, death, slander, intrigue, and all other things that
delight or trouble foolish men."
Augustine (354-430)
"Even that which is called evil, when it is regulated and out in its own place, only
enhances our admiration of the good."
Anselm (1033-1109)
"You exist so truly, Lord my God, that You cannot even be thought not to exist."
Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274)
"Among all others, the rational creature is subject to divine providence in a more
excellent way, in so far as it itself partakes of a share of providence, by being provident
both for itself and for others. Therefore it has a share of the eternal reason, whereby it has a
natural inclination to its proper act and end; and this participation of the eternal law in the
rational creature is called the natural law."
Francis Bacon (1561-1626)
"And not only must we look for and acquire a great number of experiments, and
ones of a different kind from those used hitherto, but also a quite different method, order,
and procedure must be introduced for the continuation and furtherance of experience."
Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679)
"[In the state of nature] the life of man [is] solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short."
René Descartes (1596-1650)
"And let [the evil genius] do his best at deception, he will never bring it about that I
am nothing so long as I shall think that I am something. Thus, after everything has been
most carefully weighed, it must finally be established that this pronouncement 'I am, I exist'
is necessarily true every time I utter it or conceive it in my mind."
Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677)
"Nothing in nature is contingent, but all things are from the necessity of the divine
nature determined to exist and to act in a definite way."
John Locke (1632-1704)
"The natural liberty of man is to be free from any superior power on earth, and not
to be under the will or legislative authority of man, but only have the law of nature for his
rule."
Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716)
"The soul follows its own laws, and the body likewise follows its own laws; and
they agree with each other in virtue of the pre-established harmony between all substances,
since they are all representations of one and the same universe."
George Berkeley (1685-1753)
"To be is to be perceived."
David Hume (1711-1776)
"Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to
any other office than to serve and obey them."
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
"But though all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all
arises from experience."
G.W.F. Hegel (1770-1831)
"To help bring philosophy closer to the form of Science, to the goal where it can lay
aside the title 'love of knowing' and be actual knowing -- that is what I have set myself to
do."
Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860)
" 'The world is my representation': this is a truth valid with reference to every living
and knowing being, although man alone can bring it into reflective, abstract consciousness.
If he really does so, philosophical discernment has dawned on him."
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)
"It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be
Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied."
Soren Kierkegaard (1813-1855)
"Had I to carve an inscription on my grave I would ask for none other than 'that
individual'."
Karl Marx (1818-1883)
"As individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore, coincides
with their production, both with what they produce and with how they produce. The nature
of individuals thus depends on the material conditions determining their production."
Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914)
"Few persons care to study logic, because everybody conceives himself to be
proficient enough in the art of reasoning already. But I observe that this satisfaction is
limited to one's own ratiocination, and does not extend to that of other men."
William James (1842-1910)
"My first act of freedom will be to believe in free will."
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900)
"From life's school of war: What doesn't kill me makes me stronger."
Gottlob Frege (1848-1925)
"It is certainly praiseworthy to try to make clear to oneself as far as possible the
sense one associates with a word. But here we must not forget that not everything can be
defined."
Edmund Husserl (1859-1938)
"To the things themselves."
Henri Bergson (1859-1941)
"The eye sees only what the mind is prepared to comprehend."
John Dewey (1859-1952)
"The sense of an extensive and underlying whole is the context of every experience
and it is the essence of sanity."
Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947)
"Thus nature is a structure of evolving process. The reality is the process."
Bertrand Russell (1872-1970)
"Scepticism, while logically impeccable, is psychologically impossible, and there
is an element of frivolous insincerity in any philosophy which pretends to accept it."
G.E. Moore (1873-1958)
"If I am asked 'What is good?' my answer is good is good, and that is the end of the
matter."
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951)
"What is your aim in philosophy? -- To show the fly the way out of the fly-bottle."
Martin Heidegger (1889-1976)
"Dasein is an entity which does not just occur among other entities. Rather it is
ontically distinguished by the fact that, in its very Being, that Being is an issue for it."
Gilbert Ryle (1900-1976)
''Learning how or improving in ability is not like learning that or acquiring
information."
Karl Popper (1902-1995)
"I propose to replace the question of the sources of knowledge by the entirely
different question: 'How can we hope to detect and eliminate error?' "
Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980)
"Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself. That is the first principle
of existentialism."
Simone de Beauvoir (1908-1986)
"A woman is not born. . . she is created."
W.V.O. Quine (1908-2000)
"What the indeterminacy of translation shows is that the notion of propositions as
sentence meanings is untenable. What the empirical underdetermination of global science
shows is that there are various defensible ways of conceiving the world."
Albert Camus (1915-1960)
"There is but one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide. Judging
whether life is or is not worth living amounts to answering the fundamental question of
philosophy."
Featuring the Voices of
David L. G. Arnold is an Assistant Professor of English at the University of Wisconsin,
Stevens Point. Besides The Simpsons and popular culture, his research interests include the
laments of William Faulkner and the social protest novels of Chester Himes. David
believes he knows how Maude Flanders REALLY died.
Daniel Barwick is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Alfred State College. He is the
author of Intentional Implications and numerous articles. Barwick lectures widely on
ethics, metaphysics, and assessment of general education. He enjoys Spanish peanuts
(without skin), taking candy from babies (it's a larf), and wallowing in his own crapulence.
Eric Bronson is an instructor of Philosophy and World Civilizations at Berkeley College
in New York City. He is also a Visiting Professor at Altai State University in Barnaul,
Russia. Mmmmmm. . . kolbassa.
Paul A. Cantor is Professor of English at the University of Virginia, and has served on the
National Council on the Humanities. He has published several books and numerous articles
on such subjects as Shakespeare, Romantic literature, and literary theory. A collection of
his essays on popular culture will be published under the title Gilligan Unbound (Rowman
and Littlefield, 2001). His work on The Simpsons has been praised and quoted in the
National Enquirer. And he has just landed the coveted Danny DeVito role in Fox
Searchlight's remake of Twins, starring Rainier Wolfcastle.
Mark T. Conard is a fiction writer, philosopher, and Steppenwolf dwelling in
Philadelphia. His publications on Kant and Nietzsche have appeared in Philosophy Today
and The Southern Journal of Philosophy. His article, "Symbolism, Meaning, and Nihilism
in Quentin Tarantino's Pulp Fiction" was published in Philosophy Now. Mark doesn't
believe in anything any more and has decided to go to law school.
Gerald J. Erion teaches philosophy at Medaille College in Buffalo, New York. He has
published on philosophy of mind and ethics, but he never wins at Bible Bombardment.
Raja Halwani is assistant professor of philosophy in the liberal arts department at the
School of the Art Institute of Chicago. His philosophical interests are in ethics, philosophy
of art, and philosophy of sex and love. He has published a number of articles in
professional journals and is currently writing a book on virtue ethics. However, Raja's
greatest achievement was to have discovered a meal between breakfast and brunch.
Jason Holt is Sessional Instructor at the University of Manitoba. He is the author of
Blindsight and the Nature of Consciousness (forthcoming) and publishes on a variety of
philosophical topics. None of his work bears the Krusty Brand Seal of Approval.
William Irwin is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at King's College, Pennsylvania. He
has published scholarly articles on theory of interpretation and aesthetics, is the author of
Intentionalist Interpretation: A Philosophical Explanation and Defense (1999), and the
co-author of Critical Thinking (forthcoming, 2001). He is the editor of Seinfeld and
Philosophy: A Book about Everything and Nothing and The Death and Resurrection of the
Author? (forthcoming). Bill would like to thank David Crosby for keeping him out of
Moe's Tavern and off the Duff.
Kelly Dean Jolley is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at Auburn University. Among
his recent publications is "Philosophical Investigations and a Philosophical Education" in
The Modern Schoolman. Kelly owns the world's largest Malibu Stacy collection.
Deborah Knight is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Queen's National Scholar at
Queen's University, Kingston, Canada. She has published numerous articles on topics such
as aesthetics, philosophy of film, philosophy of literature, and philosophy of mind, and
always takes Bart's advice on the ponies.
James Lawler is an Associate Professor in the Philosophy Department at the State
University of New York at Buffalo. He is the author of The Existentialist Marxism of
Jean-Paul Sartre, and IQ, Heritability, and Racism, as well as articles on Kant, Hegel, and
Marx. He is editor of Dialectics of the U.S. Constitution: Selected Writings of Mitchell
Franklin, to be published this year by MEP Press, Minnesota. Jim spends his spare time
collecting early Bleeding Gums Murphy recordings, and is especially interested in
information on Bleeding Gums's infamous Paris period.
J.R. Lombardo is a member of the faculty of the City University of New York, and
provides counseling and psychotherapy in private practice. His is the winner of the
regional title "Best New Poet" for his "Tripping through the Celestial Woods," and works
in the area of mental illness and values. J.R.'s favorite Backstreet Boy is "the little rat-faced
one."
Carl Matheson is Professor of Philosophy and Head of the Department of Philosophy at
the University of Manitoba. He has published in the philosophy of art, the history and
philosophy of science, and metaphysics. With David Davies, he is currently editing an
anthology in the philosophy of literature for Broadview press. Budget permitting, he hopes
to hold students in place by means of giant magnets.
Jennifer Lynn McMahon is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Centre College. She has
published on Sartre, Eastern philosophy, and aesthetics. While she hasn't had to take a
second job to support her horse habit yet, with eight horses on her farm, Jennifer illustrates
what can happen when fathers buy their daughters ponies.
Aeon J. Skoble is Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the United States Military
Academy at West Point. He is the co-editor of the anthology Political Philosophy:
Essential Selections (Prentice-Hall, 1999) and author of the forthcoming Freedom,
Authority, and Social Order. He writes on moral, political, and social theory for both
scholarly and lay journals, and is Editor of the annual journal Reason Papers. He is also a
contributing editor of Corey Magazine.
Dale Snow is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at Loyola College in Maryland. She is
the author of Schelling and the End of Idealism and has published numerous scholarly
translations from the German. She agrees with Marge that all you college men are only
interested in one thing.
James Snow is an eighth-grade math teacher in the Baltimore County Public School
System. In addition, he is a member of the Graduate Faculty of Education at Loyola
College in Maryland, and day trades on the stock market. He has published on the novels of
Thomas Hardy, as well as the philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer; his most recent article
appears (in Dutch) in the journal Philosophie. His mantra comes directly from the lips of
Homer Simpson: "My coffee break is whenever I say it is!"
David Vessey is Assistant Professor of Philosophy and Religion at Beloit College. His
research focuses on contemporary European philosophy and he has published articles on
Sartre, Foucault, and Ricoeur. Like Ned he drives a Geo, and although he doesn't have a
Ph.D. in Mixology, he thinks he may have enough credits.
James M. Wallace is Associate Professor and Chair of English at King's College,
Pennsylvania. He has published on American literature, is the author of Parallel Lives: A
Novel Way to Learn Thinking and Writing, and is the co-author of Critical Thinking
(forthcoming, 2001). Jim fully expects to get pelted with tomatoes.
Joseph Zeccardi's current research interests include Sartre and existentialist literature.
You may remember Joe as the star journalist for such leading publications as Montgomery
"I Can't Believe It's a Newspaper" Life. As a starving philosopher, he is the author of
hundreds of newspaper articles, none of which have any relevance to this book. The
important thing is, he does exist.
Scan Notes, v3.0: Proofed carefully, italics and special characters intact. Annotations
collected and placed at the end of each essay.